Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Darwin's Metaphor:
Nature's Place in Victorian Culture
by
[ Introduction | Preface |
Chapter: 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 | Notes | Bibliography | Index ]
CHAPTER VI
THE HISTORIOGRAPHIC AND IDEOLOGICAL CONTEXTS OF THE
NINETEENTH-CENTURY DEBATE ON MAN'S PLACE IN NATURE
A scientific worker is necessarily the child of his time and the inheritor of the
thought of many generations. But the study of his environment and its conditioning power
may be carried on from more than one point of view.
Joseph Needham (1935)
I
This chapter is about theory and praxis. The theory in question is that of the
historiography of science, and the praxis to which it is applied is the attempt to write
about the debate on man's place in nature in nineteenth-century Britain. The praxis is
therefore theoretical praxis. For reasons which reflect both my own ideological position
and my personal style of research, I find it meaningless to discuss ideological and
historiographic questions in the abstract. I shall therefore consider these issues as they
have arisen in connection with particular problems in the course of my own research.
The epigraph is based on a Marxist approach to the history of science. It was written
at a time when Joseph Needham was just beginning to apply his political orientation to
systematic work in the history of embryology, in an essay delivered at Yale in 1935
entitled "Limiting Factors in the History of Science, observed in the History of
Embryology." Needham's research since then has continually broken new ground in the
field of the history of science. I have chosen the epigraph, not only because this essay
is written in his honor, but also because my main purpose is to attempt to stimulate
debate on the requirements of a radical historiography of science in the current period -
half a century after Needham laid out his position and the Soviet delegation to the Second
International Congress of the History of Science and
165
Technology came to London and dramatically introduced a version of Marxist
historiography to the awareness of historians of science in Britain. The attempt to work
toward a radical historiography cannot at present be based upon a settled conception of
what is meant by "radical." However, certain aspects of this conception can be
stated: it is concerned with an approach to history which is critical rather than
custodial or ornamental; it is in the service of transcendence and liberation rather than
mere reproduction, and gives insight into possibilities for achieving a society which is
not alienating and repressive.
The argument falls into two main parts and a number of distinct sections. The first
section is a brief exposition of my particular problem, written in relatively subjective
terms. The second is a discussion of what it meant to be "a child of one's time"
in the history and philosophy of science in Cambridge in the 1960s. The third is an
outline of the state of the literature on the nineteenthcentury debate on man's place in
nature. Taken together, these sections provide a statement of the problem. In the second
half of the essay, attention is directed to the available alternative perspectives for
doing research in the history of science. It begins with criticisms of the Marxist
"base-superstructure" model of interpretation, with particular emphasis on the
limitations of what has come to be known as "vulgar Marxism." This is followed
by my own criticism of the prevailing terms of the historiographic debate in the history
of science - the "internalist-externalist" distinction and the related claims of
"demarcationism." Within this general context, I go on to consider the scope of,
and to make objections to, the positions of those who concentrate on the role of external
factors in the history and sociology of science - the Weberian-Mertonian tradition - and
the debate between that and the internalist historians of ideas. The work of Lakatos,
Kuhn, Merton, and Hall is briefly evaluated, and the severe limitations of their
approaches are pointed out. This section is followed by an analysis of recent treatments
of Darwinism by New Left authors and a tentative look at the help which various
anthropological perspectives can provide for understanding my problem and, more generally,
the study of science and its history. This section refers to the work of Anderson,
Thompson, Marx, Lukács, Douglas, Horton, and Sohn Rethel.
In the course of the argument an attempt is made to suggest
166
that we reconsider the Marxist "base-superstructure" distinction, i.e., the
view that all intellectual and cultural phenomena are ultimately determined by
socioeconomic conditions. In so doing, attention should be shifted toward the complex and
subtle mediations between social and economic factors and the explicit content of
scientific findings and theories. It is suggested that the strategy for developing a
radical historiography in the current period should have two moments: first, the devotion
of serious attention to the dialectic between base and superstructure; and second,
the development of a theory of mediations which moves toward a concept of totality in
which man, nature, and society are seen in fully relational terms. Rather than abandoning
the study of the history of ideas, it is important that both ideas and their
institutionalizations continue to be given serious attention. But this must be done
without losing sight of their historical place in social and economic life and their
ideological role in maintaining existing social and economic relations by rationalizing
them. A double perspective on science as such and as ideology is advocated. This model is
applied to the approach I am attempting to use in writing about the nineteenth-century
debate - a debate which was itself concerned with the philosophies of man, God, nature,
and society and their interactions. The role of science as ideology is relatively
overemphasized in this essay in an effort to counterbalance the existing bias in the
literature toward the internal history of ideas. It is hoped that when the existing
approach has been sufficiently complemented by studies of the role of ideology as a
material force in our views of nature, man, and society, a more balanced view will
develop.
Many would argue that the base-superstructure distinction is beyond redemption, but
historians of science may well need to work their way through it before they can achieve a
more dialectical perspective. I should like to stress that this is offered as a working
paper" in which I have attempted to bring together in the compass of a single
argument a number of related issues, the relations among which have not been worked out at
all satisfactorily. My aim is to raise questions and to stimulate debate. The extensive
end notes are provided in order to draw attention to the wide spectrum of raw materials
for that debate. A great deal of further study of Marxist and related writings must be
undertaken
167
if the history of science is to take its place among critical studies in the service of
liberation.
II
The following two sections are written autobiographically. This style has been adopted
in the belief that others working in the field have had analogous experiences. Thus,
although the presentation is personal, one hopes that the argument is not merely so.
The general problem with which my research has been concerned is that of applying the
categories of natural science to the study of "man." After completing a series
of studies on the relationship between psychological and physiological categories -
considered in the context of philosophical and biological developments in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries - the scope of the inquiry was broadened to include the
intellectual context within which the scientific study of persons was undertaken. Thus,
although these investigations had originally been concerned with biology (as broadly
defined), it soon became apparent that the debate on evolution could not be considered in
isolation from theological, philosophical, literary, social, political, and economic
debates in the same period. It is a commonplace that the evolutionary debate was conducted
amid heated controversies in those related areas. However, a close study of the documents
has made it clear that it is difficult, and ultimately impossible, to maintain the
conventional distinction between the science of the period and the factors which are
usually considered to provide its context. This is as true of the boundaries between
science and pseudoscience as it is of the putative boundaries between the internal history
of scientific findings and ideas on the one hand, and so-called nonscientific factors on
the other.
In the course of the research and in conversations with colleagues working in an
earlier period, it became evident that this problem was not at all unusual among
historians and in particular among those who found it increasingly difficult to do justice
to developments in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries within a framework which
required the separation of "science" (as retrospectively defined) from social,
philosophical, and theological issues. They found it reassuring to encounter the same
problem in
168
the nineteenth century, since one of the ways in which their critics had dealt with
their interpretations was to argue that such "confusion" was to be expected in
the period when the methods and assumptions of modern science were being established. Of
course, research in the nineteenth century is faced with a version of the same argument in
the assertion that its domain is the period when the methods and assumptions of modern
science were being extended to the biological sciences and to the study of
humanity.
It would be wrong to claim that it was easy to refute the arguments of those who wanted
to separate internal from external factors and to concentrate on the advancing edge of
objectivity, the history of paradigms, or the progressive demarcation of real science from
contextual factors and from pseudoscience. Rather, we gained confidence from each other's
failure to find the accepted historiography congenial to our own inquiries and felt more
at home in the company of political and social historians who thought it odd that
historians of science could, with apparent confidence, claim to separate science from
other developments in a given period. We were not able to offer a coherent historiography
to counter the one which was derived from positivist and sociological models of science.
Rather, we called the practitioners of the internalist history of ideas "Whig"
historians and, as our detailed studies found sympathetic readers, we began to refer to
our own approach as "relativist" and "contextualist," embracing labels
which others had used as epithets. At the same time we came to ignore the official
historiography, since we felt that its strictures did violence to the fine texture of the
issues which we encountered in our work with primary sources.
In the same period that a group of professional historians was developing some
confidence - or at least mutual comfort - I was conducting research toward a (never to be
completed) work entitled Man's Place in Nature: The Nineteenth-Century Debate in
Britain. This research was not being carried out according to a clearly conceived
historiography. However, from the outset its scope was the interpretation of the
evolutionary debate in a wide context of late eighteenth- and nineteenth-century thought.
Since I had come to the research from the history of psychiatry, psychology, and
neurophysiology, I was more concerned with the question of humanity than with the
development of biological theory per se. The research has differed from existing work in
the general area
169
in that it has been concerned with geological, biological, theological, and social
issues from the point of view of what I take to be the central preoccupation of the
participants in the debate: a fundamental reorientation of the conception of the relations
between man, God, nature, and society. As the work progressed, this reorientation became
more closely defined as a change from mechanistic analogies employed within an explicitly
theistic natural theology to the use of organic analogies based on a secularized, implicit
natural theology.
As I have said, the research took the form of a close study of a particular line of
central works, those of T. R. Malthus, William Paley, Charles Lyell, the authors of the Bridgewater
Treatises, Charles Darwin, Robert Chambers, A. R. Wallace, Herbert Spencer, the
authors of Essays and Reviews, T. H. Huxley, and John Tyndall. The focus of the
existing literature on developments in geology and biology was complemented by placing
much greater emphasis on the writings of theological, psychological, philosophical, and
social theorists whose work was an integral part of the debate. As the study moved on and
as an analysis was undertaken of the reception of the central figures and their works, the
crucial role of a group of commentators became apparent. These were lesser men in the
pantheon of the history of science and were in many cases seen as second-rank at the time.
But it became clear that their role in the debate - considered as a debate in its own
terms rather than as the path to current views - was as important as that of the central
figures. They were the critics and interpreters of the new approaches of geology and
biology to the intelligentsia, and it was their criticisms which the main writers felt
they had to anticipate and to answer. The essays and the reviews of, for example, William
Buckland, William Whewell, Adam Sedgwick, Baden Powell, G. H. Lewes, William Carpenter,
and St. George J. Mivart were of considerable importance in this respect. There was also a
substantial network of periodicals in which the views of these "lesser" writers
appeared. Each of the main works was reviewed and debated in the Victorian periodicals
which approached the issues from identifiable points of view. Finally, one can supplement
these public documents with the reactions which were subsequently published in the
voluminous lives and letters of nearly all of the significant figures involved. It will
therefore be seen that a study of this debate can be based on an intricate
170
network of original contributions, criticisms, interpretations, and reactions extending
from the founding of the Edinburgh Review in 1802 and growing throughout the
century as the periodical press expanded. If one wanted to attach a name to the resulting
approach, it might be called "social intellectual history." Of course, limits
must be set to any systematic goals in covering the periodical literature, but the extent
of the critical discussion on particular works helps considerably in deciding how far to
follow a given aspect of the ongoing debate. That is, the danger of retrospective
distortion of emphasis is lessened by accepting guidance from the intensity and scope of
the contemporary debate as defined by its own organs. This approach is tempered by
awareness of "resounding silences" - problems which were not discussed
and the reasons for this. Even so, the literature involved is very extensive indeed.
It should be emphasized that the historiographic and ideological questions which are to
be raised here are germane to a particular historical problem, one which is concerned with
an important issue in the history of science and which is undoubtedly of interest to
students in a number of related fields. In attempting to work out a clear approach to the
argument I have found that the prevailing h'storiographic positions in the field are not
adequate for interpreting my findings. Furthermore, the problem should not be separated
from that of relating this project to the uncertain role of academic research in the
current political and ideological situation. This difficulty is particularly acute in
research on the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature, since the domain of
that research is itself a widespread controversy on the relations between the
interpretations of man and society and the categories of science which defined the problem
for the twentieth century. We are therefore faced with the problem at two levels: (1) the
interpretation of the nineteenth-century debate; and (2) the attempt to do this in a
period when the relations between scientific and political categories are once again at
the center of controversy among intellectuals and political activists. There is a third,
more fundamental, issue: this chapter must be seen as the first step toward a critique of
the project of writing social intellectual history, since a radical historiography must go
beyond the history of ideas - however broadly defined - and locate the debate on those
ideas
171
in the history of people, events, and institutions, of which it forms a constitutive
part, i.e., history as a resolution of forces.
III
The epigraph to this chapter should be applied not only to scientific workers but also
to workers in the history of science: they are children of their time.
That is, we are children of our time, and the issues raised by that
assertion should be applied to the questions being considered here. For a historian of
science beginning research in Cambridge (as in most centers in Britain and America) in the
early 1960s, this truism would have conveyed no echo of the Marxist thesis on which
it was based: "The mode of production of material life conditions the general process
of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men that
determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their
consciousness." Rather, the apprentice scholar was faced with a set of models which
implied the relative autonomy of ideas from their socioeconomic bases. The standard texts
to which he was exposed in Cambridge (and elsewhere) were all concerned with intellectual
history, although there were important differences between those who saw the history of
scientific ideas as a relatively autonomous study, e.g., Herbert Butterfield, Rupert Hall,
and M. A. Hoskin, and those who were keen to relate them to philosophical themes, e.g., N.
R. Hanson, G. Buchdahl, and M. B. Hesse. A. C. Crombie represented an intermediate
position, and his Augustine to Galileo was one of a relatively small number of
works which students read early in their studies in the field which was not written by
someone who was then, or had very recently been, on the teaching staff in the history and
philosophy of science in Cambri dge (though he had worked in Cambridge for many years as a
scientist). Butterfield was still active in Cambridge, although not then teaching history
of science. Hall and Hanson had recently left to take up professorships in America. The
approaches of the staff members in history and philosophy of science consisted of an
amalgam of Hoskin's internalism, Hesse's highly disciplined mixture of current philosophy
of science and history of scientific ideas, and Buchdahl's rich and allusive studies
172
in the history of the metaphysics of science from Descartes to Kant, coupled with an
infectious ability to explore all of the ambiguities in any apparently straightforward
statement. The standard introductory texts were Butterfield's The Origins of Modem Science (1949) and Hall's The Scientific Revolution (1954), both of which were almost
exclusively concerned with the internal history of scientific ideas. They were joined in
1960 by The Making of Modern Science, a useful collection of short essays edited by
Hall, and by Gillispie's synoptic work, The Edge of Objectivity. (His essay has
broader scope, but its title and its historiography perfectly reflect the prevailing
orthodoxy.) These were soon followed by introductory works by Boas and Hall which were
more detailed and limited in period but which continued the established tradition.
Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions appeared in 1962 and
seemed to many to herald "a revolution in the historiography of science," but
the debate about it in the intervening period and Kuhn's own replies to his critics and
interpreters make it clear that his attacks on the cumulative and positivist approaches do
not, in the end, transcend the established view of the history of science. The bridge
between historical and philosophical issues was built by the work of Crombie, Hanson, and
Buchdahl and by Hesse's Forces and Fields and Dijksterhuis' The Mechanization of
the World Picture, both of which appeared in 1961 (the latter in translation).
Moving closer to the philosophy of science per se, Blake, Ducasse, and Madden's collection
of case studies, Theories of Scientific Method, appeared in 1960. The standard
works in the (relatively ahistorical) philosophy of science were Braithwaite's Scientific
Explanation (1953, paperback edition 1960) and Popper's The Logic of Scientific
Discovery (1934, English translation, 1959). These were complemented by a number of
volumes of collected readings with a heavy bias toward the philosophy of the physical
sciences. Although these volumes included selections which were concerned with the
biological and human sciences, the approaches of the editors were toward the
physicochemical sciences as the model for all knowledge.
Taken together, these works - all of which appeared for the first time or in
translation (or were still being widely read) in the late 1950s and early 1960s - made up
a formidable orthodoxy in favor of treating the history and philosophy of science in
relative isolation from their social, economic, and political contexts. Although
173
many of the historical works make gestures toward society, this was their orientation.
The classics which somehow came to one's attention were concerned with the history of
scientific ideas in the context of philosophy, though they probed further than most of
those listed above into the philosophy of nature: A. N. Whitehead's Science and the
Modern World (1925), E. A. Burtt's The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical
Science (2nd ed., 1932), A. O. Lovejoy's The Great Chain of Being (1936),
and the essays of Alexandre Koyré.
It was known that Joseph Needham was working in Cambridge, that he saw himself as both
a Marxist and a Christian, and that he was engaged in a massive work, Science and
Civilisation in China. It was also known that he was conducting this
distinguished work while continuing to hold the position of Dunn Reader in Biochemistry
and that whenever the question was mooted of just recognition of his achievement in the
history of science in the form of a Chair, key individuals in the University saw to it
that the matter went no further. (He was able to resign his Readership in 1966, when he
became Master of Gonville and Caius College. He was awarded the Sarton Medal - the
profession's highest honor - at the Twelfth International Congress of the History of
Science in 1968.) His legitimate preoccupation with his self-imposed task, along with its
esoteric subject, meant that although young scholars perused his volumes and used his History
of Embryology, his presence in Cambridge did not appear to influence the
prevailing orientation of teaching and research in the history and philosophy of science.
(It was later possible to discern his role in subsequent developments in the subject in
Cambridge, but his stature and influence were not directly felt by most students in the
1960s.)
More importantly, the word "social" was seldom heard, and
"economics," "politics," and "ideology" were never uttered
with any historiographic implications, although they were obviously employed in
conversation. The explicitly Marxist writings of Needham and Bernal were seldom referred
to. I recall acquiring those of Bernal at bargain prices in 1965, and I sought out
Needham's essays only after that. Nor were the names of Marx, Weber, Mannheim, or Merton
prominent on any reading lists or in the informal reading of graduate students. One was
much more likely to study Wittgenstein, Wisdom, Ryle, Austin, and Strawson in
174
one's exploratory reading. While there were demarcations between those who were more
interested in the history than in the philosophy of science, the continuum led from the
history of scientific ideas to analytic philosophy. While relations with the History
Faculty were cordial, and history of science lectures were listed in the History syllabus,
there were no strong departmental or intellectual connections until 1966, when a
Special Subject in the history of science was invited by the History Faculty, and this was
an anomaly which caused difficulties on both sides.
The foregoing account would seem to be a necessary background for understanding a
series of remarks by Rupert Hall which would otherwise appear bizarre from a later vantage
point. In an assessment of the relations between the social and intellectual approaches to
the history of science, published in 1963, he drew the opposite conclusion to Marx and
wrote, "Thus recent historians reverse the arrow of economic inference: social forms
do not dominate mind; rather, in the long run, mind determines social forms." The
scientific revolution was "a phenomenon of intellectual history," and interest
had been withdrawn from externalist explanations. Modern science "is the fruit of an
intellectual mutation [and] its genesis must be considered in relation to an intellectual
tradition."
Social and economic relations are rather concerned with the scientific movement than
with science as a system of knowledge of nature (theoretical and practical); they help us
to understand the public face of science and the public reaction to scientists; to
evaluate the propaganda that scientists distribute about themselves, and occasionally -
but only occasionally - to see why the subject of scientific discussion takes a new turn.
But to understand the true contemporary significance of some piece of work in science, to
explore its antecedents and effects, in other words to recreate critically the true
historical situation, for this we must treat science as intellectual history, even
experimental science.
Hall's conclusions were borne out by the contemporary sociology of the history of
science:
Even without making a detailed review of the work of other historians of science active
at the present time it is clear that the trend towards intellectual history is strong and
universal. Since the journal Centaurus published in 1953 a special group of
articles on the social relations of
175
science no single article that can be judged to represent the sociological
interpretation of history has appeared in that periodical, or Isis, Annals of science,
Revue d'histoire des sciences, or the Archives internationales. There has been
little discussion of the historiographical issue: indeed, it sometimes seems that the case
for setting the development of scientific thought in its broader historical context is
condemned before it is heard, though one knows from personal conversations that it is not
neglected in pedagogic practice. Clearly, externalist explanations of the history of
science have lost their interest as well as their interpretive capacity.
How, in the face of this intellectualist orthodoxy, did the revival of the study of the
social dimension of science become attractive? Its relevance began to be felt in
Cambridge, not as a result of the intellectual preoccupations of the teaching staff in the
history and philosophy of science, but from three main sources: the influence of the Leeds
department; the approach of two philosophically oriented political historians in
Cambridge, John Dunn and Quentin Skinner; and the work of a group of Oxford-trained social
historians. Something very exciting was going on at Leeds under the catalytic influence of
Jerome Ravetz and three young scholars whom he had attracted there: P. M. Rattansi, J. E.
McGuire, and Charles Webster. None of these was from the mainstream of British academic
life: Ravetz is an American emigré and an ex-Marxist whose original training was in
mathematics; Rattansi is a Kenya Indian, an Ismaill, who worked as a journalist and took
his first degree in economics; McGuire is an Irish-Canadian of maverick intellectual
disposition; and Webster is a highly individualistic British radical who worked in
education before doing graduate work in the history of science. Rattansi moved on to
King's College, Cambridge, and from there to a Chair at University College, London;
Webster became Reader in History of Medicine at Oxford; McGuire took up a professorship at
Pittsburgh. All four of the Leeds group were placing the preoccupations of the
seventeenth-century natural philosophers in theological and social contexts. They were
interested in philosophical issues, but unlike Buchdahl and Hesse, this was not for the
sake of the good philosophy to be squeezed out of (or read into) them. Rather, they were
shamelessly relativist and contextualist and were far more interested in the social
milieux and the philosophies of nature underlying the works of the scientific virtuosi than
in the so-called
176
mainline of the development of modern science. Their work was consonant with (and
attractive to) eminent historians whose writings bore on science in differing ways but
were not at the center of consciousness of the professional group of historians of
science: H. Trevor-Roper, Christopher Hill, Joseph Needham, Walter Pagel, Frances Yates,
E. H. Gombrich, D. P. Walker.
Although the work of Dunn and Skinner had affinities with the approach of the Leeds
group - especially in their studies on Locke and Hobbes - they were also concerned to
argue on philosophical and historical grounds against the legitimacy of the history of
ideas as traditionally conceived. Both stressed that ideas do not beget ideas but that
people do so in particular historical contexts and that the meaning of those ideas is
exquisitely bound to the particularity of those contexts. They argued that the study of
the genealogy of ideas divorced from close study of their social and political contexts
could only lead to elaborate historical punning. Their approaches attempted to integrate
the tradition of analytic philosophy (with its elitist appeal to the intellectual
aristocracy) with the investigations of Duncan Forbes on the Scottish Enlightenment and
Peter Laslett on the Locke manuscripts. The influence of Dunn and Skinner in the history
of science led one to set ideas in their social contexts, using stern criteria of
investigation and inference in the close analysis of documents. A contemporary of theirs,
John Burrow, shared both their background in the Cambridge History Tripos and the
influence of Forbes and wrote an important study of nineteenth-century intellectual
history.
The appeal of the approach of Dunn and Skinner to social factors in intellectual
history was complemented by the influence of a group of young left-wing social historians
based at Oxford who were more concerned with the texture of history than with
historiographic and philosophical elegance. Foremost among them was Raphael Samuel of
Ruskin College. There is no direct connection between interest in the history of science
and in the work of Samuel on nineteenth-century British working-class history, that of Tim
Mason on the German unions under National Socialism, Gillian Sutherland on
nineteenth-century primary education in Britain, or Susan Budd on the Rationalist Press
Association. The connection lies rather in the fact that scholars become interested in
approaches of colleagues who are doing exciting work, find themselves influenced by their
perspectives, and ask how they would
177
see a given problem and how they would treat it. In retrospect, the affinities felt
with their work can be seen as an attempt to transcend the orthodoxy of internalist
intellectualist historiography of science. Among contemporaries, theirs seemed
particularly relevant research in that it was addressed to society.
It was in the atmosphere of a strong orthodoxy in the history and philosophy of science
at Cambridge, alongside a network of overlapping intellectual affinities and sympathies,
that in 1968 Rattansi and I brought together a number of the aforementioned scholars, and
others, for a seminar (sponsored by the King's College Research Centre) which met monthly
to consider the relationship between the history of science and other branches of
historical studies. At quarterly intervals senior visitors gave papers to the seminar
which represented established points of view in different branches of history: Joseph
Needham (history of science in the Chinese culture area), E. H. Gombrich (history of art),
Frances Yates (Renaissance studies), Hugh Trevor-Roper (social history), Philip Collins
(English literature). The seminar continued for over a year and was very stimulating.
There was, however, little pressure or inclination to attempt to integrate the approaches
of intellectual history, social history, and the philosophies of nature and society. The
dichotomy between internal history of scientific ideas and external or social factors was
regularly found to be at odds with our respective investigations, but no framework which
was remotely near to being coherent emerged to take its place. On several occasions lists
of "factors" were drawn up from the discussions, but no overall approach to the
issues was worked out. Most of the papers presented to the seminar were published in
learned journals, but the participants felt that they in no sense formed the basis for a
volume with a coherent theme. Indeed, the real work of the seminar was in the discussions,
but no one had the inclination to record and edit them. It was decided that the seminar
had been very successful, and there was some talk about reconstituting it around the topic
of historiography, but other priorities intervened.
The striking feature of this account of the local social history of the history of
science is that there was practically no discussion of, for example, economic or political
history (as distinct from the history of political theory), or of the writings of Eric
Hobsbawm, E. H. Carr, Christopher Hill, or E. P. Thompson. Nor was there
178
any serious consideration of the domain of cultural history, for example, the writings
of Raymond Williams. This list has not been drawn at random. The surprising point is that
there was nothing in the general coinage of intellectual discourse or of the books which
were recommended by and to colleagues - and, more particularly, there was little in the
deliberations of a seminar explicitly concerned with the relations between history of
science and other branches of historical studies - which said, even obliquely: confront
Marxism. By this I mean that there was no serious pressure to consider the perspective of
Marxism and its critical approach to the relations between knowledge and the
sociopolitical world in which it exists. (Michel Foucault's neostructuralist work was just
coming over the horizon of English-speaking readers and was to become an alternative to
Marxism.)
I am sure that most historians of science in Britain and America who were studying or
doing research in the 1960s could tell an analogous story. The particular and local
influences would be different, but the general ambience and the conclusion would be the
same. Internalist historians of science were reaching out uncertainly for alliances with
other approaches in historical studies especially social (and in America, sociological)
history. They did this with a sense of growing need for historiographic rigor. However,
neither the literature nor discussions with colleagues provide evidence for any awareness
that it might be worthwhile to consider the potential relevance of Marxism to our
problems. Readers who have not lived through this period in the subject can gain a sense
of the general atmosphere by considering the analogous situation in historical, economic,
and social research in America as discussed in William Appleman Williams' The Great
Evasion: An Essay on the Contemporary Relevance of Karl Marx and on the Wisdom of Admitting the Heretic into the Dialogue about America's Future. It would be an
exaggeration to say that there was a conspiracy of silence, but there certainly was
silence.
But this is to be unduly behaviorist. I now know that at least one member of the
seminar had begun his "confrontation" with Marxism even before the seminar began
and has subsequently reached the point where he regards himself as a Marxist. It is also
worth noting that of the members of the seminar, Mikulás Teich is a Czech refugee and a
Marxist and that George Stocking and Jerome Ravetz are ex-Marxists. That this personal
grappling had
179
no significant presence at the seminar can be seen as anecdotal evidence pointing to
the magnitude of the task that a radical change in ideological position involves one in.
The change has to have resulted in a coherence well above the level of a collection of
radical intuitions before it ceases to be readily vulnerable to attack from what it seeks
to counter. Another sort of indication of the size of this task is perhaps the nature of
this essay - which, though offered as the beginning of a critique, nevertheless is cast to
a large extent within the terms of "social intellectual history" (as defined in
Section II) which the critique aims to make constitutive of a totality of relations.
IV
It would be natural for the foregoing discussion of the prevailing orthodoxy in the
history and philosophy of science in the 1960s - and its failure even to raise the problem
of confronting Marxism - to be followed by a discussion of Marxist historiography, along
with other approaches to the history of science which give weight to the relationship
between the internal history of science and social and economic factors. These issues,
however, will be postponed until consideration has been given to the state of scholarship
on the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature. My purpose is to bring these
together. To introduce the specific problem first may help the discussion to avoid
departing into generalities.
If we turn, therefore, from the state of general approaches to the history and
philosophy of science to the literature on the nineteenth-century debate, the situation is
relatively straightforward. The first point is that the topics which were central to the
best work in the area were not concerned with "the debate on man's place in
nature" but with particular disciplines - geology and evolutionism - especially the
work and influence of Charles Lyell and Charles Darwin. The field was occupied by scholars
with an impressive command of the documents. In the case of Darwin, the most precise work
was being done by Sydney Smith, whose knowledge of the Darwin archive at Cambridge was
(and remains) nonpareil, and Sir Gavin de Beer, who (with others) edited Darwin's Notebooks and wrote prolifically on Darwin in the context of the history of biology. Neither had
the interest or the
180
inclination to set Darwin's work in a sociopolitical context. Smith concentrated on
Darwin's work on classification and on important bibliographical research on the Darwin
manuscripts. To those who came to consult him and seek guidance through the labyrinth, he
argued that Darwin's research on Cirripedes was the key to his mature work. The most
important problems, he felt, lay wholly inside the scientific debates of the time.
Similarly, de Beer explicitly opposed the assignment of any fundamental significance to
social, political, and economic ideas in the development of Darwin's theory of evolution.
In his biographical study of Darwin he reviews in detail the evidence for an important
role for Malthus' theory of population - and only in detail, with no reference to
broader issues - and draws a narrow conclusion followed by a very general non sequitur:
It is therefore clear that Darwin did not owe Malthus anything on the score of
variation or natural selection, but only the realization that the high rate of mortality
exacted by nature resulted in pressure, and while Malthus argued that this pressure was
exerted against the poor members of the human race, Darwin applied the principle to plants
and animals and argued that the pressure was exerted against the less well adapted ... He
had already arrived at the principle of natural selection and had seen how, given
variation, it would lead to unlimited change away from the ancestral type, improvement of
adaptation, and eventually to the production of new species. Malthus enabled him to see
how inexorably nature enforced this principle. The view that Darwin was led to the idea of
natural selection by the social and economic conditions of Victorian England is devoid of
foundation.
The question of the role of Malthus' theory in the actual formative process of Darwin's
mechanism of natural selection is, as we have seen, very complex and open to a number of
interpretations. Nevertheless, de Beer's sweeping conclusion about the irrelevance of
social and economic conditions does not follow from his argument, even if it were the case
that such questions could be meaningfully discussed in such a narrow context. The approach
is simplistic, as is the conclusion. However, de Beer subsequently discovered new evidence
which showed that Malthus' theory of population had played a much more intimate part in
the process of the formulation of Darwin's theory than had been supposed. A number of
scholars who have considered this issue have attempted
181
to reinterpret Malthus' role and have pointed out the significance of de Beer's new
evidence. He, however, has stood firm in attempting to separate the scientific issues from
the socioeconomic context and even from direct, acknowledged influences. In a subuent
essay, he cites the relevant passage from Darwin's Autobiography (not the more
significant passage from the Notebooks) and concentrates on making claims for how
much Darwin had sorted out before reading Malthus. He once again reduces the issue to
whether Darwin got the idea of natural selection from Malthus:
From this passage some commentators have deduced that it was from Malthus that Darwin
derived his principle of natural selection. As I have said above, this is quite false:
Malthus had not the slightest idea of natural selection and would have been horror-struck
at the notion of evolution. What Darwin got from Malthus was something that Malthus knew
nothing at all about, and about which he was not writing: how natural ,.selection is
enforced on plants and animals in nature.
It was certainly right to move on from the extreme claims of those who attempted to
deduce Darwin from Malthus, but the reaction subtly falsifies both the origins and the
context of the evolutionary theory of Darwin and, for that matter, of his codiscoverer A.
R. Wallace. To move in this argument from the questions of origin and context of the
theory, the internalist approach does not address itself to the sociopolitical context
into which the theory was received and which set the terms of the debate on its reception
in periodicals and public debate of the time. To move further, there has been little
tendency to consider the various extrapolations which were based on different versions of
evolutionary theory.
The point of this extended example is not to assert that it is illegitimate for
scholars to concentrate on one aspect of the history of science at the expense of others.
Rather, it provides a basis for suggesting that the approach of internalist history
impoverishes the understanding of its own subject matter and that its interpretive
bias isolates evolutionism from its social, political, and ideological articulations. The
most comprehensive study of the reception of Darwin's work in the period 1859-72
concentrates heavily on philosophical and theological issues at the expense of social and
political ones. Similarly, the best work being done on
182
evolutionism by younger scholars concentrates on internal theoretical issues,
applications to physiology, problems of demography, and methodology. (A decade later, this
situation remains true.)
The case of Charles Lyell's uniformitarian geology is somewhat different. It would be
absurd to argue that the uniformitarian-catastrophist debate could be studied in a purely
internalist way. It is just about plausible - though, as I have suggested, ultimately
distorting - to concentrate on purely scientific issues in tracing the development of
Darwin's theory. But theological issues were explicitly central and crucial in the
geological debate. These other aspects have been explored in detail by Cannon, Hooykaas,
Haber, Coleman, Wilson, Herbert, and Porter. Rudwick has shown that as time went on, the
geological debate became relatively internalist, and he has set new standards of research
in studying the positive science of geology in the period. However, all of those who have
contributed significantly to the literature in the history of geology have found it
necessary - for their own purposes - to understand the theologies and philosophies of
nature of the participants in the controversies which raged over the history of the earth
and its laws.
Similarly, the authors of the general works which attempt to provide a broader view of
the geological and evolutionary debates paid due attention to the interaction between the
theological and scientific issues. It can be argued that their perspectives, based as they
were on an interactive model, prevented their seeing that the theological and scientific
issues were constitutive of each other's domain. However, the point to be made here is
that none of them looked very far outside science to its social and economic context. The
argument of Eiseley's Darwin Century is laid out like a detective story or a jigsaw
puzzle, in which the clues or pieces are seen exclusively in the light of their
contribution to the "solution," the picture on the cover of the box. It is very
cleverly put together, but the contemporary contexts of issues and the different
perspectives in which they were seen at the time - let alone the different interests
(social, economic, and political, as well as intellectual) that these perspectives served
- are regularly sacrificed in favor of their contribution to the view of scientific truth
as seen in the light of current science. Gillispie's pioneering work Genesis and
Geology gives full weight to the theological context, but his basic approach
183
is to show how the advancing edge of objectivity came to relegate theology to the
prefaces and conclusions of geological works as it had earlier done in the physicochemical
sciences. The reader knows from the first page that theology is on its way out. Greene's The
Death of Adam is less elegantly written than the other standard works, but its looser
structure makes it a more attractive work, since the reader can retain some sense of the
multiple perspectives in which the issues were viewed in their contemporary context.
It is a commonplace that Darwin's achievement stood above that of the other
evolutionists, but even if one considers the nineteenth-century debate on its own terms,
the significance of the writings of Robert Chambers, Herbert Spencer, and A. R. Wallace
was far greater than has been reflected in writings about the debate. None of them has
been given his due. Millhauser's monograph on Chambers is significantly entitled Just
Before Darwin. Its subject is relegated to the subtitle: Robert Chambers and "
Vestiges." The author has obviously done a great deal of research into the
contemporary debate, as he did for an earlier study of "The Scriptural
Geologists," but he remains curiously diffident about Chambers' achievement. Chambers
leaped over the inhibitions and reservations of his scientific contemporaries and conveyed
the whole sweep of naturalism, embracing man, his mind, and society. Like Spencer, he
suffers at the hands of scholars from the retrospective judgment that he was a "bad
scientist." That is a fair, if blinkered, judgment, one which was made vehemently at
the time by nearly everyone who was sufficiently well informed to express a sound opinion.
Yet the application of current standards to the contemporary situation has helped to
obscure the fact that it was Chambers' admittedly speculative theory which provided the
basis for the British debate on evolution (or the "Development Hypothesis") for
fifteen years before the theory of Darwin and Wallace was made public. Similarly,
Chambers' book helped to stimulate Wallace's inquiries, was the subject of debates between
Lewes, Spencer, and Huxley, and was important in the thought of a number of other
scientists, philosophers, and theologians in the period. Indeed, the public controversy
over the anonymous Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation was far more heated
than that over Darwin's Origin of Species. Darwin was right to say in a later
edition of his book that
184
the work, from its powerful and brilliant style, though displaying in the earlier
editions little accurate knowledge and a great want of scientific caution, immediately had
a wide circulation. In my opinion it has done excellent service in this country in calling
attention to the subject, in removing prejudice, and in thus preparing the ground for the
reception of analogous views.
Chambers was also like Spencer (and indeed like Wallace) in his overriding interest in
the implications of evolutionary theory for social and philosophical issues, yet these
have not been explored in depth in the literature. Writings about Wallace have focused on
his zoogeographical work and theories of the mechanism of evolution, not on his socialism,
his work on land nationalization, or his spiritualism, even though these interests were
determinate in the course of his changing views on evolution. Once again, restriction of
the context of the inquiry impoverishes the elucidation even of the issues which interest
internalist historians. By now few historians of science would consider an account of
Newton's work to be adequate if it excluded analogous interests which played an important
part in his philosophy of nature and his science.
The respective literatures on Chambers, Wallace, and Spencer represent three sorts of
narrow treatment of the issues. Chambers is neglected because of the weak evidential basis
for his theory, leading to ignorance of his influence (both positive and negative) and the
sweep of his vision. Wallace is included in the standard accounts, but aspects of his work
which were highly integrated at the time are treated in isolation, and the deeper
political, economic, and philosophical ones are excluded. Spencer is hardly mentioned at
all, except by historians of the social sciences. He was neither scientifically reputable
nor politically radical, but his theory, along with the generalizations and extrapolations
based on it, was probably more influential in the general debates of the late nineteenth
century than those of any of the other evolutionists. We make a sharp distinction
between the evolutionary theories of Darwin and Spencer, but their ideas were routinely
conflated in the public mind. Moreover, the participants in the scientific debate itself
considered their ideas to be far closer together than our tidy categories seem prepared to
allow.
Spencer was, at bottom, entirely preoccupied with the social and ethical implications
of evolution. Indeed, he became interested in the subject as a result of his failure to
find a sound basis
185
for the integration and progress of society. He has received considerable and growing
attention from historians of social and political theory, but almost none from historians
of science. Two of the most important books which integrate scientific issues with social
and economic ones and which have considered the evolutionary debate, are importantly
concerned with his work: John Burrow's Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian
Social Theory and John Peel's Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist. The
former relates Spencer's work to the intellectual tradition of the Scottish Enlightenment
and Utilitarianism in the domain of anthropology; the latter provides an excellent study
of Spencer's social and sociological theories in their contemporary social, economic, and
theoretical contexts. Significantly, neither author is centrally interested in the history
of science as practiced by the specialists or is considered to be a member of "the
profession of the history of science." Burrow is an intellectual historian of
political theory, and Peel is a sociologist. Both works are defective in their
appreciation of the narrowly scientific issues, but these defects are far less severe than
the failure of historians of science seriously to consider Spencer at all. Their books are
symptomatic of the mutual isolation between the study of the history of science and the
study of social theory, while their subject is someone who never made that distinction.
It would be wrong to claim that the standard sources utterly fail to mention the role
of social, economic, and political issues in the evolutionary debate. It is nevertheless
true that their treatment of these issues would never lead a reader to appreciate the
importance of giving due weight to the roles of, for example, Adam Smith, Malthus, Owenite
socialism, the Philosophical Radicals, phrenology, the Positivists, Essays and Reviews, Bishop Colenso, G. H. Lewes, George Eliot, the Mechanics' Institutes, the Society for
the Diffusion of Useful Knowledge, John Draper, Walter Bagehot, the Metaphysical Society,
the X Club. Nor would the standard sources lead him to focus on a number of other figures,
works, and societies which played important parts in the wide debate on man, nature, God,
and society which, after all, did lead people in the nineteenth century and in the present
to interest themselves in the movement summarized by the terms "Darwinism" and
"evolution." Moreover, in case the reader has not noticed (which would be
understandable in the circumstances), my list of categories - "figures, works, and
societies" - is significant for what it
186
leaves out. It is at most tangential to the concerns of, for example, Thompson's The
Making of the English Working Class or Hobsbawm's Industry and Empire.
Although it is not central to my present purpose, it should be mentioned that,
conversely, the authors of standard works in the social, political, economic, and literary
history of the period make little or no attempt to include the influence of science and
scientific naturalism in their accounts. In the history of theology the issues are
considered, but at a relatively superficial level. Even the question of the relationship
between science and technology in the economic and social history of the period has been
sorely neglected. The gap between the internalist history of science and the perspective
of writers in other branches of historical studies means that there is little impetus to
investigate their relations. The thesis that they were part of a single debate does not
even arise if one works backward from the secondary literature to nineteenth-century
documents. There are, however, two other paths to that thesis. The first is to place
oneself in the midst of the periodical literature of the period and to discover the highly
integrated network of issues in all these spheres. The second lies in applying certain
fundamental assumptions of the sociology of knowledge or of one of its parent traditions -
Marxism.
The existing literature in any field sets very strong constraints on how one finds it
possible to conceive of a problem. There is no neutral naturalism in historical research
any more than there is in science itself. Science is a social activity, born of society,
and mediating its structures and values, at least as much as it is born of nature. The
same is true of the history of science. In both cases there is some domain of data, and
there is a "natural" world somewhere out there, but the interaction of the
historically constrained subject with these objects is as much involved in determining
what will be called a datum as it is in discovering one. Without an adequate theory to
explain these interrelations and determinations, a historical account will take shape in a
determinate but relatively undisciplined way. Some philosophically inclined historians
have attempted to solve this problem in the abstract, but it remains to be shown that the
philosophical approach to historiography, divorced from actual historical research, will
lead us very far toward a more adequate theory.
The consequence of this situation for a study of the debate on
187
man's place in nature in nineteenth-century Britain was that when one began to see a
pattern of interrelations and multiple perspectives in the writings of those who took part
in the overlapping controversies, it was difficult to put the issues in a single
framework. Chapter 2 took Malthus' Essay on the Principle of Population as a
matrix and showed that widely varying interpretations of that work were seemingly equally
justified by what Malthus wrote. These interpretations - by William Paley, Thomas
Chalmers, Darwin, Spencer, and Wallace - were themselves interacting, so that the problem
of interpretation and influence became impossibly complicated. Similarly, Chapter I, which
discussed the debate from the point of view of natural theology and the concept of
progress, followed later by a study of the relationship between natural theology, the
periodical press, and the development of scientific specialization (Chapter 5), produced a
different reading of the debate. Other exercises in this vein leave one feeling that
research in the history of science is rather like literary criticism, there competing
interpretations of a work are complementary, illuminating different aspects rather than
leading progressively to a consensus among scholars. If this model - or some version of it
- were to be found persuasive by scholars in the history of science, they would finally
cut themselves off decisively from seeing their subject as an extension of the positivist,
progressive view of science itself. Let us consider a number of figures whose writings
call for the use of more than one mode of interpretation.
Insofar as historians of science have considered Malthus, they have concentrated on his
abstract, Newtonlan model of science, one which he was a pioneer in applying to man. They
have also stressed his quasi-mathematical argument on the consequences of the potential
disproportion between geometrical growth of population and arithmetical development of
food production. This provided a natural law purporting to explain poverty, misery, theft,
famine, war, and death. His concepts of "pressure" and "struggle" were
undoubtedly fundamental in both the origins and exposition of Darwin's theory of natural
selection. Darwin wrote the introduction to the Origin that his theory was
"the doctrine of Malthus, applied to the whole animal and vegetable kingdoms"
Historians of science concentrate on these aspects when they give weight to Malthus at
all. However, his theory was just importantly a decisive intervention in the
eighteenth-century
188
debate on progress, written in the wake of the French Revolution and in reply to the
sanguine writings of Condorcet and Godwin on inevitable, unlimited social progress.
Similarly, his argument must be seen as an extension of Adam Smith's theory as presented
in The Wealth of Nations (1776), explaining the natural causes of poverty, where
Smith had focused on harmonious, progressive production of wealth. Once again, Malthus'
own perspective on his theory was explicitly natural theological, and the last two
chapters of the first edition of his Essay were devoted to this topic, while his
natural theological assumptions became more diffusely spread through the text in later
editions. (Darwin read the sixth edition of 1826.) The political and economic debate which
followed the publication of Malthus' theory raged throughout the nineteenth century and is
still with us. These aspects find no place in the writings of historians of science.
Conversely, Darwin and evolutionism are not mentioned in the standard account of The Malthusian Controversy.
It is well known that the nineteenth-century debate on parish relief and the Poor Laws
centered around Malthus' theory. It became the fundamental touchstone of the debate on the
relationship between human industry and provision for the indigent. At its own basis lay a
view of nature and human nature which was deeply pessimistic and offered progress only
through painful struggle, in which human inequality was taken as given, the result of
God's wisdom and benevolence. This image of nature and society was carried over into the
evolutionary debate, and the resulting fusion was the basis for debates on the social
meaning of evolutionary theory. The line from Malthus to Darwin and on to so-called Social
Darwinism is unbroken and continues to the recent writings on biology and society of, for
example, Morris, Ardrey, and Darlington. From start to finish, this has been a reconciling
approach. It has served as the basis for the secular theodicy of industrial society and
depends on a class doctrine. Malthus wrote in 1798, "If no man could hope to rise or
fear to fall, in society, if industry did not bring with it its reward and idleness its
punishment, the middle parts [i.e., the middle class] would not certainly be what they now
are." Thomas Chalmers echoed this doctrine in even sterner language. The use of
natural law as the basis for a given view of society became a commonplace in social,
political, and economic theory, and the theory of evolution was
189
employed as a new, more powerful, justification for industrial capitalism. It is
no wonder that Marx and Engels wrote some of their most vehement polemics against Malthus
and that Marxists and other sociologists came to see the union of evolutionary theory and
Malthusianism (and various racist and eugenic corollaries extending to the present) as
fundamental obstacles to believing that the existing society could be transformed into a
just one. These aspects of the debate on man's place in nature are inseparable. To
sequester the social and political debate from the scientific one is to falsify the
texture of the nineteenth-century debate and to mystify oppression in the form of science.
William Paley is another writer who is given a small place in the work of historians of
science on Darwinism. His Natural Theology (1802) and his Evidences of
Christianity (1794) were very important in Darwin's education, and Darwin later
admitted that even in overthrowing Paley's world view, he was surprised to discover how
many of Paley's most basic assumptions he had retained. Paley is seen as the
representative of the eighteenth-century natural theology based on Design and harmony
which was set aside by scientific naturalism and industrialism. His conception of natural
theology was shown to be untenable in a period of growing scientific detail and finally
collapsed in the Bridgewater Treatises, the reductio ad absurdum of parading
the details of all the sciences seriatim as a cumulative series of proofs of the
wisdom, goodness, and benevolence of God. His was also the last plausible effort to speak
of natural harmony without giving serious weight to the dimension of time and to the
evidence of geology. The example with which his Natural Theology begins illustrates
this point: finding a stone on a path implies nothing, while finding a watch implies a
watchmaker. No literate person could make that simple contrast two or three decades after
1802, as the meaning of rocks became the central issue in the geological debate on the
nature of God's relationship with the history of the earth. Attempts were, of course, made
to integrate natural theology with the new evidence of geology, but it was no longer
possible to do so on the model of a Newtonian Heavenly Clockmaker.
The existing literature in the history of science fails to give sufficient weight to
some of these aspects of Paley's thought, just as it fails to indicate how much of the
nineteenth-century debate was conducted within the context of natural theology. Having
made
190
these points, it is important to see that historians of science reveal an almost total
lack of awareness of Paley's significance in the tradition of Utilitarian ethical and
social thought. Going beyond this in ways which are parallel to the points made earlier
about Malthus, there is no awareness at all of the political aspect of Paley's theodicy of
harmony. Malthus went beyond Paley and set the stage for nineteenth-century
rationalizations of slow change through struggle. In the area of population theory, Paley
had at first considered population growth an unmixed blessing. On reading Malthus, a
slight frown appeared on his brow and remained there until he could absorb pain and
suffering into his theodicy and could even regard himself as an adherent to Malthus'
theory.
In the area of politics, Paley was also able to absorb pain and suffering within his
generally sanguine theory. The last chapters of his Natural Theology (1802) were
explicitly concerned with reconcilng people with the status quo. He wrote, "The distinctions of civil life are apt enough to be regarded as evils, by those who sit under them;
but, in my opinion, with very little reason." A decade earlier, during the height of
Robespierre's dictatorship and the consequent anxieties among the bourgeoisie in Britain,
he had spelled out the basis for this view, in a pamphlet called "Reasons for
Contentment Addressed to the Labouring Part of the British Public":
The wisest advice that can be given is, never to allow our attention to dwell upon
comparisons between our own condition and that of others, but to keep it fixed upon the
duties and concerns of the condition itself.
But Providence, which foresaw, which appointed, indeed, the necessity to which human
affairs are subjected (and against which it were impious to complain), hath contrived,
that, whilst fortunes are only for a few, the rest of mankind may be happy without them.
The labour of the world is carried on by service, that is, by one man working
under another man's direction. I take it for granted that this is the best way of
conducting business, because all nations and ages have adopted it.
Like Malthus', Paley's later writings contained the same reconciling doctrines but in
muted form. The theme which is here mentioned explicitly - that of the basis for the
hierarchical division of labor in society (with feudalistic echoes) - is justified on the
combined bases of divine ordinance and efficiency in the writings of
191
Adam Smith, Paley, and Malthus. In the course of the nineteenth century, its basis
changes from a theological theodicy to a biological one in which the so-called
physiological division of labor provides a scientific guarantee of the rightness of the
property and work relations of industrial society. Although it also had other roots in
Continental thought (e.g., Saint-Simon, Comte, and German organic theories of the state),
this doctrine is carried on in social and political writings up to and including the
current orthodoxy.
Once the apologetic and reconciling aspects of writers such as Malthus and Paley come
to the fore, the ideological basis and implications of the orthodox dichotomy between
science on the one hand and social and ideological functions on the other begin to become
clear. One finds that these investigations lead to the ideological foundations of the
modern scientific view of the earth, living nature, man, and society but that the same
structures support the modern rationalizations of industrial capitalism, colonialism, and
imperialism. In the existing literature discussions of the scientific debate in terms of
theological positions are routine, but there is almost no full-blooded attempt to include
the social, political, and ideological roles played by the debate itself. These were to
rationalize the existing social and political order, and to reconcile people to it. The
famous controversy in the nineteenth century between science and theology was very heated
indeed, and scholars have concentrated on this level of analysis. However, at another
level the protagonists in that debate were in fundamental agreement. They were fighting
over the best ways of rationalizing the same set of assumptions about the existing order.
An explicitly theological theodicy was being challenged by a secular one based on
biological conceptions and the fundamental assumption of the uniformity of nature.
Once one begins to see the debate in this double perspective of science and ideology, it becomes necessary to keep both of its aspects constantly in the forefront and
to maintain simultaneous awareness of both. It would be misleading to suggest that they are in tension, since they are mutually consistent and support one another. Rather,
the tension lies in the mind of the scholar whose training leads him habitually to
separate his subject matter into "science" and "contextual factors,"
treating one and then (if he is
192
so inclined) the other. It is therefore very difficult indeed to refrain from treating
the materials in terms of the model of "internal" and "external"
factors, science and society.
It is very striking how we blinker ourselves and separate intellectual history from its
ideological dimension. We have seen that the same Malthus who pioneered the scientific
treatment of man was engaged in an important ideological task which dominated the
perception of the mood of nature and society throughout the century and has remained
prevalent to the present. Paley's theodicy was the best summary and popularization of an
older, more harmonious, view but the theme of a higher harmony persisted in the doctrine
of progress through struggle which replaced his equilibrium model. Similar accounts can be
given of the writings of all the major and minor participants in the debate in the main
periodicals of the early decades - Edinburgh Review, Quarterly Review, and Westminster Review. Indeed, there have been political analyses of these, notably Benthamite
Reviewing, Nesbitt's study of the early years of the Westminster. Later
generations of periodicals have received similar treatment, for example, Everett's study
of the Fortnightly, The Party of Humanity. The literature on the Victorian
periodicals is central to the understanding of the political meaning of the major vehicles
for the conduct of the debate. Approaching the problem from this point of view leads one
to find it natural that the periodicals interpreted the findings and theories of the
scientists from a political perspective. Moving on to the end of the period it is also
significant that the most eminent scientists, theologians, philosophers, men of letters,
politicans, and editors of periodicals met together in the period 1869-80 to consider all
of the aspects of the ascendancy of scientific naturalism as it bore on morality, society,
and the social order. As I have shown, Gladstone, Walter Bagehot, John Ruskin, Alfred Lord
Tennyson, Leslie Stephen, F. D. Maurice, Cardinal Manning, John Tyndall, and T. H. Huxley
all saw the point of their meeting together. I hope that it is becoming increasingly clear
why we seem unable to see the point of their Society.
The group which came together in the meetings of the Metaphysical Society shows how
highly integrated the debate in the nineteenth century was. The social and intellectual
milieu in which these men moved extended beyond science, philosophy, and theology to
include politics and literature. One of the most
193
prominent members of this intellectual elite was George Eliot. Her milieu was that of
nineteenth-century naturalism; she had close relations with Spencer and was, of course,
living with Lewes. Before she met him she had developed her naturalistic philosophy under
the influence of Bray, Hennell, and Combe, along with members of the Positivist circle of
the period. For three years she was virtual editor of the Westminster. Her writings
integrated aspects of the prevailing naturalistic ethical, scientific, and social
philosophies. Implicit in this integration was a reconciling political philosophy which
becomes explicit in her support for the conservative radicalism of Felix Holt. Felix
states his position in a nomination-day meeting:
But I should like to convince you that votes would never give you political power worth
having while things are as they are now, and that if you go the right way to work you may
get power sooner without votes. Perhaps all you who hear me are sober men, who try to
learn as much of the nature of things as you can, and to be as little like fools as
possible. A fool or idiot is one who expects things to happen that never can happen . . .
The way to get rid of folly is to get rid of vain expectations, and of thoughts that
don't agree with the nature of things.
Lest this position be seen as one which George Eliot developed only in the service of
fiction (a hypothesis which would miss the whole point of her intentions in writing
novels), it should be added that she willingly enlarged upon its reconciling message in a
didactic essay, published separately in Blackwood's Magazine: "Address to
Working Men by Felix Holt."
Well, but taking the world as it is - and this is one way we must take it when we want
to find out how it can be improved - no society is made up of a single class: society
stands before us like that wonderful piece of life the human body, with all its various
parts depending on one another, and with a terrible liability to get wrong because of that
delicate dependence. . . . Now the only safe way by which society can be steadily improved
and out worst evils reduced, is not by any attempt to do away directly with the actually
existing class distinctions and advantages, as if everybody could have the same sort of
work, or lead the same sort of life (which none of my hearers are stupid enough to
suppose), but by the turning of Class Interests into Class Functions or duties.
The nature of things in this world has been determined for us before-hand.
194
She again refers to "this society of ours, this living body in which our lives are
bound up." The combination of organic analogies and the reduction of social change to
the uniform action of natural laws has the effect of pure reconciliation:
The solution comes slowly, because men collectively can only be made to embrace
principles, and to act on them, by the slow stupendous teaching of the world's events.
But now, for our own part, we have seriously to consider this outside wisdom which lies
in the supreme unalterable nature of things, and watch to give it a home within us and
obey it.
George Eliot's interpretation of the social meaning of scientific naturalism is of a
piece with the ideological statements of Paley and Malthus.
The argument, as presented so far, is easy prey to the distinctions of an internalist,
who would simply argue that the aspects of Malthus, Paley, the periodical press, and
certainly George Eliot which I have discussed are external to the history of science as an
internalist understands it. I am, in effect, lending credence to the reasons for largely
ignoring their relevance, except in contextual terms. In order to make my case stronger,
we must move closer, knowing that we are many steps away from figures whose writings would
touch his definition of science. Although I am profoundly out of sympathy with the idea of
a continuum from contextual to internal factors, if we take that approach it is still a
matter of relative indifference where we place ourselves on it or the related one
extending from allegedly pure scientists to marginal figures. It is also obvious that the
case can be developed more easily on the basis of evidence from some figures than from
others. After all, there must have been some basis for the development of the
orthodox distinction between internal and external factors.
Robert Chambers' Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation provides a
relatively easy example, both for my position and for the internalist's. That is, it is a
commonplace that his science was very shaky. At the same time, his generalizations were of
fundamental importance in the development of the debate on man's place in nature. He had
no well-developed mechanism for explaining evolutionary change; several were mentioned,
but they were not mutually consistent. He confused the general principles of scientific
195
naturalism with the specific, then-unknown causes of evolution. He was heavily
criticized for these failings by his contemporaries, notably by Herschel and by Huxley,
whose review of a later edition of Vestiges was so vituperative that even Huxley
came to regret its tone. Chambers did not even become aware of the scientific weaknesses
of his work until he reflected on the almost universal criticism which it received at the
hands of "better-qualified" scientists. He then wrote a sequel, Explanations, and appended apologetic passages to later editions of Vestiges, in which he
made it clear that he had not aimed or claimed to spell out the specific causes of
evolution but to establish the general principles of scientific naturalism in the realms
of life, mind, and society. In doing this he struck the keynote of contemporary scientific
naturalism and drew general conclusions which "the experts" reached only decades
later.
For present purposes, however, it is important to note that Vestiges was
in a direct lineage from Malthus and Paley, and indeed from the Bridgewater Treatises, which
could also be used to develop the general thesis. Chambers' final chapters were
expressions of the developing theodicy of naturalism, and once again, the message was
social progress through reconciliation with the laws of nature:
To secure the immediate means of happiness it would seem to be necesary for men first
to study with all care the constitution of nature, and, secondly, to accommodate
themselves to that constitution, so as to obtain all the realizable advantages from acting
conformably to it, and to avoid all likely evils from disregarding it.
... we must endeavour so to place ourselves, and so to act, that the arrangements which
Providence has made impartially for all may be in our favour and not against us; such are
the only means by which we can obtain good and avoid evil here below.
It may be that, while we are committed to take our chance in a natural system of
undeviating operation, and are left with apparent ruthlessness to endure the consequences
of every collision into which we knowingly or unknowingly come with each law of the
system, there is a system of Mercy and Grace behind the screen of nature, which is to make
up for all casualties endured here, and the very largeness of which is what makes these
casualties a matter of indifference to God . . . To reconcile this to the recognised
character of the Deity, it is necessary to suppose that the present system is but a
part of a whole, a stage in a Great Progress, and that the Redress is in reserve.
196
Thinking of all the contingencies of this world as to be in time melted into or lost in
the greater system, to which the present is only subsidiary, let us wait the end with
patience, and be of good cheer.
Chambers has here reconciled the Malthusian conception of progress through struggle
with a calm sense of Paleyan harmony. In preparing his views he relied heavily on the
doctrines of phrenology, particularly the work of George Combe, whose popularizations of
the doctrines of Franz Joseph Gall and J. C. Spurzheim were immensely popular in the
period as a vehicle for ideas of social welfare, self-improvement, and progress. Combe,
along with Charles Bray, also influenced the views of nature of George Eliot. If we wish
to relate these doctrines directly to the theory of reconciliation to industrial
capitalism, we can do so by two paths. The first is through the wide current of Calvinism
running through all these works, leading us to Weber's thesis in The Protestant Ethic
and the Spirit of Capitalism. The second path leads to the theory of which Weber's
thought was in important ways a bourgeois transformation, i.e., to Marxism. The same year
in which Chambers extolled a faith in progress and harmony based on a partially
secularized theodicy embracing the entire physical and living universe, Friedrich Engels
(a twenty-four-year-old German whose family owned a cotton mill in Manchester) wrote The
Condition of the Working-Class in England in 1844. His reaction to Malthusianism and
the legislation which was enacted under its influence was very different:
Meanwhile the most open declaration of war of the bourgeoisie upon the proletariat is
Malthus' Law of Population and the New Poor Law framed in accordance with it. We have
already alluded several times to the theory of Malthus. We may sum up its final result in
these few words, that the earth is perennially overpopulated, whence poverty, misery,
distress, and immorality must prevail; that it is the lot, the eternal destiny of mankind,
to exist in too great numbers, and therefore in diverse classes, of which some are rich,
educated, and moral, and others more or less poor, distressed, ignorant, and immoral.
Hence it follows in practice, and Malthus himself drew this conclusion, that charities and
poor-rates are, properly speaking, nonsense, since they serve only to maintain, and
stimulate the increase of, the surplus population whose competition crushes down wages for
the employed; that the employment of the poor by the Poor Law Guardians is equally
unreasonable, since only a fixed quantity of the products of labour can be consumed, and
for every un-employed
197
labourer thus furnished employment, another hitherto employed must be driven into
enforced idleness, whence private undertakings suffer at cost of Poor Law industry; that,
in other words, the whole problem is not how to support the surplus population, but how to
restrain it as far as possible. Malthus declares in plain English that the right to live,
a right previously asserted in favour of every man in the world, is nonsense. He quotes
the words of a poet, that the poor man comes to the feast of Nature and finds no cover
laid for him, and adds that "she bids him begone," for he did not before his
birth ask of society whether or not he is welcome. This is now the pet theory of all
genuine English bourgeois, and very naturally, since it is the most specious excuse for
them, and has, moreover, a good deal of truth in it under existing conditions. If, then,
the problem is not to make the "surplus population" useful, to transform it into
available population, but merely to let it starve to death in the least objectionable way
and to prevent its having too many children, this, of course, is simple enough, provided
the surplus population perceives its own superfluousness and takes kindly to starvation.
Engels argues, in short, that poverty is a political - manmade - and not a natural
phenomenon. The contrast between the sweet reconciling reason of Chambers' passage in his
chapter "Purpose and General Condition of the Animated Creation" and the
polemical agitation of the passage from Engels' chapter on "The attitude of the
Bourgeoisie towards the Proletarist" helps to point out the two perspectives on the
debate on man's place in nature which must be seen if we are to move from loose contextual
references (e.g., to "the social dimension") to a genuinely radical
historiography.
The continuum through Malthus, Paley, and Chambers leads on to Herbert Spencer, perhaps
the most influential of all the interpreters of the philosophical, ethical, social, and
political meaning of Victorian scientific naturalism. The case for an intimate mixture of
sociopolitical and scientific considerations in his thought has been made out many times
and hardly needs rehearsing, especially since the appearance of Peel's biography and
Macrae's edition of his essays. There is no need to reveal Spencer's motives as primarily
sociopolitical, since he repeatedly makes the point himself. He turned to phrenology, to
psychology, and then to biology-as we have seen-in search of new guarantees to replace
those which had been found wanting in theism and in Utilitarianism. The problem with
Spencer is not that of showing that he
198
conforms to the position being argued here. Rather, it is to get historians to see how
central his work and influence were to the nineteenth-century debate, both among
scientists and the broader public. His reputation has suffered most among the leaders of
thought in the period because subsequent scientists (followed dutifully by historians)
have anachronistically dismissed him for holding a "Lamarckian" theory of the
mechanism of evolution. Two things should be recalled about his position. First, that it
was a theory which, though embattled, was taken seriously throughout the nineteenth
century and, indeed, was given increasing weight by Darwin (just as Spencer allowed an
increasing role for natural selection). This point should lend perspective to the
dismissal of Spencer as a serious figure. Second, he was unequivocal in pointing out that
he attached great weight to the question of the mechanism of evolution precisely because
of its ethical, educational, social, and political consequences. Throughout his mature
life he was seeking a scientific basis for a doctrine of inevitable progress which would
justify his belief in an extreme form of laissez-faire economic and social theory.
A. R. Wallace held a different theory of the mechanism of evolutionary change, one
which was initially based on a fusion of ideas drawn primarily from Lyell and Malthus.
When he saw that this theory had implications which were in conflict with his more
fundamental belief in socialism, it was not socialism which yielded, but his belief in the
Malthusian mechanism of natural selection. Important exceptions were made to his earlier
belief in the total adequacy of natural selection to account for man and his mind. It
should be remembered that he came to feel that not only his socialism but also his
spiritualism and his belief in phrenology were in conflict with total adherence to natural
selection. This is not the place to develop an analysis of the relationships among these
influences (and their own deeper political meaning) and the biological findings which
worried him. The point which I wish to make here is merely that they were all mixed up
together.
Similar cases can be made out for each of the significant figures in the mainstream of
the evolutionary debate and the wider debate on man's place in nature. In each case -
e.g., those of Buckland, Whewell, Wilberforce, Sedgwick, Powell, Chalmers, Lewes,
Carpenter, Mivart - scientific, philosophical, theological, and explicitly political
considerations form a closely woven network of
199
factors in their own theories and in their considerations of the theories of others.
Interpreters of evolutionary theory such as the Duke of Argyll, William Graham, Ernst
Haeckel (who was influential in translation) followed the same pattern. But what of Lyell
and Darwin, the real scientists whose ideas were at the heart of the debate as it occurred
and whose theories dominate the secondary literature to an even greater extent? Part of
the answer has been given already in chapters which point out the importance of
theological, philosophical, and other nonpositivist factors in their work. In the case of
Lyell, new evidence about the overriding role of his concerns about man's special status
has recently come to light in Wilson's edition of Lyell's hitherto unpublished Scientific Journals on the Species Question; and Rudwick has argued forcefully that this
evidence calls for an orderly retreat on the part of those who formerly argued that Lyell
could be studied along relatively internalist lines. Even so, the role of social and
political factors in the work of both Lyell and especially of Darwin is a highly mediated
one. Having got part of the way by showing the centrality of theological and philosophical
questions in the origins, substance, and vicissitudes of their theories, one is left with
the need for a subtle and complex theory of mediations if it is to be possible to make a
strong case for them as figures who should be viewed in the simultaneous perspectives of
science and sociopolitical ideas. It is beyond doubt that their theories were central to
others' reconciling and apologetic doctrines. It is also becoming increasingly clear that
orthodox accounts which stress the growth of scientific naturalism as a development away
from traditional theological and social doctrines must be fundamentally reconsidered. In
their place we require an interpretation which shows the deeper continuities. Rather than
focus on the overthrow of the relatively static theistic cosmology by a secular and
progressive one, an interpretation must be worked out which stresses the development from
one theodicy - in both its scientific and its social aspects - to another. The first was
suitable for a relatively static and rural economy while the other was developed for a
rapidly changing and industrializing society. Although the theories of Lyell and Darwin
were at the center of the role of science in this change of rationalization, it may be
necessary in the short run to overemphasize the breadth and texture of the wider movement
of which their work was but a part, however essential their particular contributions
200
were to it. Once we have gained a broader view of the general movement of
nineteenth-century naturalism, it will be a much less daunting task to place their work in
it, without unduly exaggerating or minimizing their respective and related roles.
It should be granted that the work and influence of Lyell and Darwin were less
intentionally and obviously an expression of more basic socioeconomic forces and
structures than, for example, the work and influence of Chambers, Spencer, and Wallace.
Similarly, their greater scientific prestige meant that those who employed their theories
for sociopolitical purposes could claim a sounder foundation in the nature of things - in
scientific laws - for their extrapolations and generalizations. A scholar who interprets
the history of science in terms of internal and external factors or some related model
would make a sharp distinction between their work and the contexts in which it developed
and into which it fed. Rather like Lyell and Darwin, who withdrew from the political
issues raised by their work, he would not want to get involved in that sort of thing.
A radical scholar would make two replies, one on the internalist's ground and one on
his own. The first is that, by the internalist's criteria of understanding, his
historiography unnecessarily blinkers his own perspective and impoverishes his
understanding of the very problems which interest him. Second, a radical approach requires
that the sociopolitical basis and its relations with the putatively autonomous scientific
results be explored in depth and detail. He must make this effort in order to understand
the role of scientific rationality and its technological expressions (and affiliations) in
maintaining the established order of society and in sustaining the false consciousness
which prevents people from believing that it can be transformed into a society in which
the division of labor need not be hierarchical and exploitative, one in which
inegalitarian structures are no longer maintained by being mystified and justified by a
spurious foundation in the laws of nature. Put simply, a radical and critical
historiography of science is required so that it can be seen that the present order of
society is a fundamentally political, not merely a natural, and much less an inevitable,
one and that it is therefore open to change through political struggles, once people's
consciousness is freed from the fetters of deference to a natural basis for the present
social order.
However, in order for this change of consciousness to occur, it
201
will be necessary critically to evaluate the model of science and its history which
considers the substance - the findings and theories - of intellectual development to be
relatively autonomous and independent of sociopolitical determination.
The cases of Lyell and Darwin are thus part of a much wider problem. They are,
relatively speaking, the purest of the scientists in the Victorian debate and as such are
nearer to the positions of physicists, chemists, and mathematicians. If one is studying
the writings of town planners, political scientists, sociologists, anthropologists,
economists, psychologists, ethologists, physiologists, geneticists, molecular biologists,
chemists, physicists, or mathematicians, one finds oneself at different points on a
continuum, between writings which obviously reflect sociopolitical assumptions and those
which do not obviously do so. In studying disciplines which are near the beginning of that
list, ideological assumptions appear, as it were, on the surface of the page. At the other
extreme, a student of the history of physics or mathematics - or indeed of recent
molecular biology - would be very incredulous if faced with an interpretation of his data
which stressed ideological assumptions which appeared to play no part in the data before
him. Of course, there are those who defend the positivist purity of the woolliest of the
social sciences and model them on the physicochemical sciences. At the other extreme are
those who have attempted to account for findings in so-called pure science by claiming
that they are direct, unmediated expressions of economic forces in the period or,
alternatively, of the psychopathology of the scientist as seen from a psychoanalytic point
of view. Isaac Newton is generally considered to be the paradigm scientist of the
scientific revolution, and Boris Hessen's classical essay "The Social and Economic
Roots of Newton's 'Principla"' is an example of the former approach, while Frank
Manuel's A Portrait of Isaac Newton is a notable example of the
psychoanalytic view.
What is required in the first instance, it seems to me, is a radical historiography
which goes far beyond these simplistic approaches and which is based on a sufficiently
flexible theory of mediations between socioeconomic base and intellectual superstructure,
so that it can take account of scientific developments at any point on the continuum of
"purity" of the sciences. This approach to the concept of mediation is not new.
It is a revival of views which were expressed by Marx and Engels. However, the concept has
202
degenerated in the hands of those who have reduced Marxism to "vulgar
Marxism" The theory of mediation must include not only concepts for working along
that continuum but must also address itself to the assumptions on which the continuum
rests, that is, the paradigm of explanation of modern science which was elaborated in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in specific sociopolitical conditions and which forms
the basis of the orthodox practice of scientists and of historians who study the advancing
edge of objectivity. The development of such a historiography is a fundamental desideratum
both for those who have found themselves working with a relativist and contextualist
approach which is not well articulated, and for those who seek to make the historical
study of science play a part in changing the world into one which is genuinely liberating,
socialist, and egalitarian. Of course, many historians of science will wish to continue -
as one put it - "working in my own corner," either implicitly or explicitly
making a contribution to the maintenance of the existing order of society. They will argue
that a call for a "radical" historiography of science is "dragging politics
into the classroom" and that the status quo in the subject is apolitical. Others
would argue on political grounds that the present approach to the subject is political
and that it has the right politics.
What are the available perspectives for a Marxist historiography of science, and what
is wrong with them?
V
Reverting once again to Needham's Marxist thesis about men and their ideas being born
of their time, it is important to add the corollary that changed men with changed
consciousness are the products of changed times. This is as true of the present as it was
of the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature. It was also true of Joseph
Needham's development. In his essay "Metamorphoses of Scepticism" (1941), he
reports that "The process of socialisation of my outlook, however, really began with
the general strike in 1926 [in which he was on the government's side] and was completed by
the rise to power of Hitlerite fascism in 1933." Between these two events there
occurred the Second International Congress of the History of Science and Technology in
London (1931), at which the Soviet delegation put forth the version of
203
Marxist historiography of science which inspired the approaches of Needham and Bernal,
and which influenced Crowther and others. Needham later wrote in "Limiting Factors in
the History of Science",
In sum, we cannot dissociate scientific advances from the technical needs and processes
of the time, and the economic structure in which all are embedded.
.......The history of science is not a mere succession of inexplicable geniuses, direct
Promethean ambassadors to man from heaven. Whether a given fact would have got itself
discovered by some other person than the historical discoverer had he not lived it is
certainly profitless and probably meaningless to enquire. But scientific men, as Bukharin
said, do not live in a vacuum; on the contrary, the directions of their interests are ever
conditioned by the structure of the world they live in. Further historical research will
enable us to do for the great embryologists what has been well done by Hessen for Isaac
Newton . . .
Similar tributes to Hessen can be found in writings of the other two major Marxist
historians of science in England. Bernal wrote that "Hessen's article on Newton . . .
was for England the starting point of a new evaluation of the history of science."
This tribute appears in his The Social Function of Science, a work which was one of
the most notable expressions of the new Marxist historiography. J. G. Crowther did not
identify himself as a Marxist to the extent that Needham and Bernal did, but he was
influenced by Marxist historiography. The acknowledgments of his The Social Relations
of Science began as follows: "The views of B. Hessen and T. Veblen have provided
much inspiration for this book." In the course of the book he gives an account of the
Congress and its influence.
Hessen gave the first concrete example of how science should be interpreted as a
product of the life and tendencies of society... Hessen's demonstration of the depth and
range of Newton's dependence on the ideas promulgated by the epoch in which he appeared,
made a profound impression on some of the younger members of the congress. It transformed
the study of the history of science, and out-moded the former conceptions of the subject,
which treated it as governed only by the laws if its internal logical development.
Henceforth, no satisfactory history of science could be written without giving adequate
attention to the dependence of science on social factors.
... The movement, of which Hessen's essay was the most stimulating
204
expression, transformed the history of science from a minor into a major subject. It
showed that a knowledge of the history of science was not only of entertaining antiquarian
interest, but was essential for the solution of contemporary social problems due to the
unorganized growth of the technological society.
Clearly, Needham, Bernal, Crowther, and others who were very inspired by the
interpretation of the history of science which the Soviet delegation brought to the
Congress, and their subsequent work in the field (though in the cases of the three persons
mentioned it was a part-time activity, albeit a prolific avocation) continued to adhere to
the model of intellectual work in science as a direct and relatively straightforward
superstructural expression of the socioeconomic base in a given society. This model proved
useful in its time, but I do not propose to discuss it in detail. It is noteworthy that
its basic documents remain in print, and many of them have been reprinted, in particular
the papers presented by the Soviet delegation to the London Congress in 1931. The
reprint contains an excellent analytical introduction by R. G. Werskey, "On the
Reception of Science at the Cross Roads in England." The revival of interest
in this historiographic approach is significant, but it is basically pointless to attempt
to recapture an atmosphere which played no part in the education of younger historians of
science in the present generation and which, when recovered, is clearly to be set aside.
Werskey's introduction, his book, and his related studies of the period and the genre are
reliable guides for those interested in this topic, but it is a historical topic,
and I propose to discuss it only as reflected in criticisms of its limitations.
Conservative and radical historians are understandably united in the belief that the
base-superstructure model, as advocated by Hessen and his followers, led too easily to
crude economic reductionism. It is, frankly, difficult to recover the enthusiasm generated
by Hessen's essay. He makes a gesture to the complexity of his problem:
It would, however, be too greatly simplifying and even vulgarising our object if we
began to quote every problem which has been studied by one physicist or another,
and every economic and technical problem which he solved..... the above general analysis
of the economic problems of the epoch would not be sufficient. We must analyse more fully
Newton's epoch, the class struggles during the English Revolution, and the political,
205
philosophic and religious theories [that] are reflected in the minds of the
contemporaries of these struggles.
Even so, no amount of disarming qualification can prevent the reaction one feels
against the simple one-to-one correlations beween economic and technological problems on
the one hand and scientific ideas on the other, of which the bulk of his argument
:consists. For example,
The above specified problems embrace almost the whole of physics. If we compare this
basic series of themes with the physical problems which we found when analysing the
technical demands of transport, means of communication, industry and war, it becomes quite
clear that these roblems of physics were fundamentally determined by these demands ....We
have compared the main technical and physical problems of the period with the scheme of
investigations governing physics during the period we are investigating, and we come to
the conclusion that the scheme of physics was mainly determined by the economic and
technical tasks which the rising bourgeoisie raised to the forefront.
In the face of this approach, one can only feel sympathy and understanding on being
told that in the 1940s young Anglo-American historians of science turned to the internal
history of ideas as practiced by Koyré and Meyerson with a sense of relief, excitement,
and liberation. This is not, however, to say that the base-superstructure model could not
be skillfully applied to yield subtle historical work, as it undoubtedly did in the major
writings of Needham and Bernal. However, in their zeal to follow Marx and Engels in
deploring the practice of writing the history of the sciences "as if they had fallen
from the skies," many practitioners of the Marxist historiography of the period after
1931 fell into the opposite error of writing it as if it always rose directly and
straightforwardly from the base, without mediation. Moreover, they did not even entertain
the possibility that the metaphors of that model - base, superstructure - might need to be
complemented, if not finally superseded. Hall was entirely correct when he wrote in 1963,
"In its crudest form at any rate the socioeconomic interpretation of the scientific
revolution as an offshoot of rising capitalism and mercantile militarism has perished
without comment." A decade later it can be added that its revival is a mistake,
except as a basis for developing a more subtle version of the fundamental Marxist thesis.
This is precisely what the most
206
sophisticated of the historians who have been influenced by Marxism have recently been
doing. Eric Hobsbawm, a Marxist economic historian, provides an exposition of the
initial effects and of the debasement of Marx's fundamental insights.
Yet those of us who recall our first encounters with historical materialism may still
bear witness to the immense liberating force of such simple may simple discoveries
[relating ideas to economic conditions]. However, if it was thus natural, and
perhaps necessary, for the initial impact of Marxism to take a simplified form, the actual
selection of elements from Marx also represented an historical choice ...The bulk of what
we regard as the Marxist influence on historiography has certainly been vulgar-Marxist
...It consists of the general emphasis on the economic and social factors in history which
have been dominant since the end of the Second World War in all but a minority of
countries (e.g. until recently West Germany and the United States), and which continues to
gain ground. We must repeat that this trend, though undoubtedly in the main the product of
Marxist influence, has no special connection with Marx's thought. The major impact which
Marx's own specific ideas have had in history and the social sciences in general, is
almost certainly that of the theory of "basis and superstructure"; that is to
say of his model of a society composed of different "levels" which interact.
At this point the historian of science begins to feel the primitive state of discussion
on these issues in his own discipline, and the historian of the biological and human
sciences is in a particular difficulty. He or she is still striving to apply certain of
the most basic insights of Marxism as a corrective to positivist approaches both to the
history of science in general and especially to living nature and humanity. Thus, even the
vulgar-Marxist tradition has played an important part in attempting to transform history
into a critical discipline among the social sciences. Hobsbawm writes,
The major contribution of Marxism to this tendency in the past has been the critique of
positivism, i.e. of the attempts to assimilate the study of the social sciences to that of
the natural ones, or the human to the non-human. This implies the recognition of societies
as systems of relations between human beings, of which the relations entered into for the
purpose of production and reproduction are primary for Marx. It also implies the analysis
of the structure and functioning of these systems as entities maintaining themselves, in
their relations both with the outside environment - non-human and human - and in their
internal relationships. Marxism is far from the only structural-functionalist theory of
society, though it has good claims to be the first of them, but it differs
207
from most others in two respects. First, it insists on a hierarchy of social
phenomena (e.g. "basis" and "superstructure"), and second, on the
existence within any society of internal tensions ("contradictions") which
counteract the tendency of the system to maintain itself as a going concern.
These points are directly germane to the analysis of the nineteenth-century debate on
man's place in nature, a debate in which the modern theory which reduces the human to the
non-human was being elaborated. It also points to the role of the debate itself in
maintaining a given social order in the face of rapid socioeconomic change and to the
important interactions between intellectual developments and social ones. Yet just as
historians of science are getting near to these insights, Marxist historians in other
fields are moving on, partly on the basis of a new political context and partly as a
result of reading more widely in Marx's writings, some of which are newly published.
Hobsbawm continues,
Moreover, the diminishing returns on the application of vulgar-Marxist models have in
recent decades led to a substantial sophistication of Marxist historiography. Indeed, one
of the most characteristic features of contemporary western Marxist historiography is the
critique of the simple, mechanical schemata of an economic-determinist type. However,
whether or not Marxist historians have advanced substantially beyond Marx, their
contribution today has a new importance, because of the changes which are at present
taking place in the social sciences. Whereas the major function of historical materialism
in the first half-century after Engels' death was to bring history closer to the social
sciences, while avoiding the oversimplifications of positivism, it is today facing the
rapid historicisation of the social sciences themselves. For want of any help from
academic historiography, these have increasingly begun to improvise their own - applying
their own characteristic procedures to the study of the past, with results which are often
technically sophisticated, but, as has been pointed out, based on models of historic
change in some respects even cruder than those of the 19th century. Here the value of
Marx's historical materialism is great, though it is natural that historically minded
social scientists may find themselves less in need of Marx's insistence on the importance
of economic and social elements in history than did the historians of the early 20th
century; and conversely might find themselves more stimulated by aspects of Marx's theory
which did not make a great impact on historians in the immediately post-Marxian
generations.
208
I appreciate that the quotation of long passages from Hobsbawm's analysis in "Karl
Marx's Contribution to Historiography" may appear confusing and that his remarks call
for careful exegesis and translation into terms which apply directly to problems in the
historiography of science. My aim in quoting them is to bring into sharp relief the
distance between the level of debate on these issues among certain social and political
historians and that among the mainstream of professional historians of science. This is
not to say that no professional historians of science have addressed themselves to issues
which would also interest a Marxist. However, they have not done so in a theoretically
self-conscious way. The separation of historians of science from these issues, which Hall
pointed out, had already lasted for a decade by 1963; it has since grown more marked, and
the incomprehensibility and apparent irrelevance of Hobsbawm's analysis can be argued to
be a measure of the gap which must be bridged if a radical historiography of science which
is relevant to current conditions is to be developed. For example, the following statement
about historical studies in general is simply not true of the history of science: ".
. . history is a discipline into which Marxist ideas and a Marxist approach have already
penetrated deeply, so that there is not such a gap between a Marxist historian and a
non-Marxist colleague as there would be, for instance, among philosophers."
It can, of course, be argued that the base-superstructure distinction is only useful to
historians of science as a vehicle for freeing themselves from the restrictions of the
internalist-externalist distinction and that having once freed themselves, they should lay
aside the model which has led so disastrously to economic reductionism in vulgar Marxism.
It may be that the base-superstructure model is too encrusted with barnacles or too
redolent of stale debates to be refurbished and made useful. My own current position is
that the employment of a sufficiently subtle theory of mediations and interactions between
socioeconomic factors and intellectual life would make the base-superstructure model
serviceable once again, at least in an interim way, until we can develop a fully
relational, totalling approach. But most historians of science who have any sympathy at
all with radical historiography are still at the stage which Hobsbawm mentioned as
"first encounters" which have a tremendously liberating force, and they are
tempted to be
209
sanguine about possibilities which those who have had more experience with this model
are likely to discount.
Raymond Williams made this point very forcefully in "Marxism and Culture" in
his Culture and Society where he was at pains to separate Marx and Engels from
their vulgarizers. He refers to an important letter which Engels wrote to J. Bloch in
1890:
According to the materialist conception of history, the ultimately determining element
in history is ultimately the production and reproduction of real life. More than
this neither Marx nor I have ever asserted. Hence if somebody twists this into saying that
the economic element is the only determining one, he transforms that proposition
into a meaningless, abstract, senseless phrase. The economic situation is the basis, but
the various elements of the superstructure - political forms of the class struggle and its
results, to wit: constitutions established by the victorious class after a successful
battle, etc., juridical forms, and even the reflexes of all these actual struggles in the
brains of the participants, political, juristic, philosophical theories, religious views
and their further development into systems of dogmas - also exercise their influence upon
the course of the historical struggles and in many cases preponderate in determining their form. There is an interaction of all these elements in which, amid all the endless
host of accidents (that is, of things and events whose inner interconnection is so remote
or so impossible of proof that we can regard it as non-existent, as negligible) the
economic movement finally asserts itself as necessary. Otherwise the application of the
theory to any period of history would be easier than the solution of a simple equation of
the first degree.
After giving some examples and suggesting that it would be far better to read Marx's
writings and his own and not to approach the problem at second-hand, Engels continues,
Marx and I are ourselves partly to blame for the fact that the younger people sometimes
lay more stress on the economic side than is due to it. We had to emphasise the main
principle vis-à-vis our adversaries, who denied it, and we had not always the
time, the place or the opportunity to give their due to the other elements involved in the
interaction. But when it came to presenting a section of history, that is, to making a
practical application, it was a different matter and there no error was permissible.
Unfortunately, however, it happens only too often that people think they have fully
understood a new theory and can apply it without more ado from the moment they have
assimilated its main principles, and even those not always correctly. And I cannot exempt
many
210
of the more recent "Marxists" from this reproach, for the most amazing
rubbish has been produced in this quarter, too ...
Williams notes that this formulation is richer than that of vulgar Marxism but still
finds it static. Its application by Marxist theorists of culture seemed to him to employ
different aspects of it in varying ways "as the need serves." His
position in Culture and Society was very much like that of current historians of
science. His grasp of the fine texture of cultural history in nineteenth-century Britain
and his determination to remain true to his materials led him to take up a relativist and
contextualist standpoint without any clear theoretical position. His own historiographic
certainties were negative: he could neither adhere to the approach of idealist and elitist
cultural historians nor allow himself to conform to the impoverishing model of vulgar
Marxism.
Over a decade later his writings on these issues began to reflect a much surer and more
optimistic approach to historiography. In an essay on ideas of nature in
nineteenth-century Britain, he offered a rendering which reflects an ability to maintain
simultaneously the same perspectives which were being suggested above: "What is often
being argued, it seems to me, in the idea of nature is the idea of man; and this not only
generally, or in ultimate ways, but the idea of man in society, indeed the ideas of kinds
of societies." The context of this passage suggests an ability on his part to unite
science, the philosophy of nature, and theories of man and society in a single theoretical
framework.
Williams' approach has a clear basis in Engels' own self-critical reflections. In a
letter to Mehring in 1893, he developed the point that he and Marx had failed sufficiently
to stress the process of mediation ("ways and means") and the relative autonomy
of ideas and their interactions with history. I quote this important self-criticism at
length:
... one more point is lacking, which, however, Marx and I always failed to stress
enough in our writings and in regard to which we are all equally guilty. That is to say,
we all laid, and were bound to lay, the main emphasis, in the first place, on the derivation of political, juridical and other ideological notions, and of actions arising through
the medium of these notions, from basic economic facts. But in so doing we neglected the
formal side - the ways and means by which these notions, etc., come about - for the sake
of the content. This has given our adversaries a welcome opportunity for misunderstandings
and distortions....
211
Ideology is a process accomplished by the so-called thinker consciously, it is
true, but with a false consciousness. The real motive forces impelling him remain unknown
to him; otherwise it simply would not be an ideological process. Hence he imagines false
or seeming motive forces. Because it is a process of thought he derives its form as well
as its content from pure thought, either his own or that of his predecessors. He works
with mere thought material, which he accepts without examination as the product of
thought, and does not investigate further for a more remote source independent of thought;
indeed it is a matter of course to him, because, as all action is mediated by
thought, it appears to him to be ultimately based upon thought.
The historical ideologist (historical is here simply meant to comprise the political,
juridical, philosophical, theological - in short, all the spheres belonging to society and
not only to nature) thus possesses in every sphere of science material which has formed
itself independently out of the thought of previous generations and has gone through its
own independent course of development in the brains of these successive generations. True,
external facts belonging to one or another sphere may have exercised a codetermining
influence on this development, but the tacit presupposition is that these facts themselves
are also only the fruits of a process of thought, and so we still remain within that realm
of mere thought which apparently has successfully digested even the hardest facts.
It is above all this semblance of an independent history of state constitutions, of
systems of law, of ideological conceptions in every separate domain that dazzles most
people. If Luther and Calvin "overcome" the official Catholic religion or Hegel
"overcomes" Fichte and Kant or Rousseau with his republican social contract
indirectly "overcomes" the constitutional Montesquieu, this is a process which
remains within theology, philosophy or political science, represents a stage in the
history of these particular spheres of thought and never passes beyond the sphere of
thought. And since the bourgeois illusion of the eternity and finality of capitalist
production has been added as well, even the overcoming of the mercantilists by the
physiocrats and Adam Smith is accounted as a sheer victory of thought; not as the
reflection in thought of changed economic facts but as the finally achieved correct
understanding of actual conditions subsisting always and everywhere - in fact, if Richard
Coeur-de-Lion and Philip Augustus had introduced free trade instead of getting mixed up in
the crusades we should have been spared five hundred years of misery and stupidity.
This aspect of the matter, which I can only indicate here, we have all, I think,
neglected more than it deserves. It is the old story: form is always neglected at first
for content. As I say, I have done that too and the mistake
212
has always struck me only later. So I am not only far from reproaching you with this in
any way - as the older of the guilty parties I certainly have no right to do so; on the
contrary. But I would like all the same to draw your attention to this point for the
future.
Hanging together with this is the fatuous notion of the ideologists that because we
deny an independent historical development to the various ideological spheres which play a
part in history we also deny them any effect upon history. The basis of this is the
common undialectical conception of cause and effect as rigidly opposite poles, the total
disregarding of interaction. These gentlemen often almost deliberately forget that once an
historic element has been brought into the world by other, ultimately economic causes, it
reacts, can react on its environment and even on the causes that have given rise to it.
The perspective of Raymond Williams is illuminating for another reason. Not only was he
able to avoid vulgar Marxism while writing from a socialist point of view, but he also
increasingly shows an ability to mediate between the Old Left and the New Left. He
continues to play a leading part in theoretical formulations for English-speaking
socialists begun in the 1960s. It was said earlier that while all people are children of
their time, changed people are children of changed times. The developments which Needham,
Bernal, and others refer to as leading them to see science and society from a socialist
perspective have their parallels in developments in the 1960s in the growth of civil
disobedience, in the Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament in Britain and the struggles for
civil rights in America; in the growth of radical student movements, particularly in
America, Germany, France, Japan, Italy, and to a lesser extent in Britain; in the
worldwide protest movement against the American intervention in Southeast Asia; in the
bitter disappointment over the policies of the British Labour Government; in the invasion
of Czechoslovakia; in repressive political trials in Britain and America. Among committed
members of the Communist Party there was an earlier reaction to the invasion of Hungary,
followed by the revelations about Stalin and other repressive measures extending from
treatment of minorities to the absurdities of the Lysenko affair in biology. Although
there are continuities between the civil disobedience movements and the more radical phase
which grew up around the Vietnam War, it was in the period after 1964 that the
implications of these developments for our perception of liberal institutions
213
and liberal scholarship began to penetrate the consciousness of scholars and slowly led
them to reflect about the political meaning of their work. In the 1960s and early 1970s,
writers (including Williams) who centered around the May Day Manifesto group and the New
Left Review played an important part in bringing about a reconsideration
of approaches to scholarship and political strategy, at the same time that they set up a
translation industry for bringing the attention of others to important theoretical
developments in the Marxist tradition which had been going on in relative isolation from
Anglo-American scholars. (A similar role was being played by C. Wright Mills in the United
States.) These are the writings of continental and émigré ideologues extending from Rosa
Luxemburg, Georg Lukács, and Antonio Gramsci, to the works of the Frankfurt School -
Horkheimer, Adorno, and especially Marcuse - followed more recently by Habermas and
Schmidt and on to the related works of Walter Benjamin and Lucien Goldmann. There are, of
course, other writers whose works have played an important part in continental debates on
Marxism. In particular, continuous discussion of these issues has been occurring in
Yugoslavia, Czechoslovakia, Austria, and Italy, but these have not on the whole been
brought to the attention of scholars in England and America. The writings of Sartre and
Garaudy are more accessible. There is also a growing literature from the network of people
who are routinely called "structuralists" - some of whom themselves reject the
designation or affiliation with others who are so labeled - Lévi-Strauss, Foucault,
Althusser, and Balibar. Not all of these would be happy to be identified as part of a
Marxist tradition, but it does seem fair to suggest that all of them have worked out their
positions in relation to Marxism. Some of the issues raised in this debate will be
considered later. For the present I only want to suggest that historians of science could
more profitably turn to this literature for stimulating issues and analogies than to the
writings of traditional historiography.
In an extremely perceptive and moving essay entitled "Literature and Sociology: In
Memory of Lucien Goldmann," Raymond Williams provides a clear expression of the
experience of finally finding someone who spoke to his intellectual and political needs.
In suggesting that his sense of fellowship has great relevance for the current situation
in the historiography of science, I appreciate that orthodox historians will feel that I
am begging large
214
questions about the putative differences between the history of science and cultural
history. I can only say that I have begun to consider these questions elsewhere and state
the interim conclusion that a consequence of the perspective being argued here is that the
history of science is far more like the histories of literature, art, and society than has
hitherto been supposed and that to appreciate this, it is necessary to adopt an
"anthropological" point of view for considering the history of science.
Williams speaks of his embarrassment in earlier decades over the conflict between the
cultural elitism of the group of critics writing for Scrutiny and contemporary
vulgar Marxism.
Marxism, as then commonly understood, was weak in just the decisive area where
practical criticism was strong: in its capacity to give precise and detailed and
reasonably adequate accounts of actual consciousness: not just a scheme or a
generalisation but actual works, full of rich and significant and specific experience. And
the reason for the corresponding weakness in Marxism is not difficult to find: it lay in
the received formula of base and superstructure, which in ordinary hands converted very
quickly to an interpretation of superstructure as simple reflection, representation,
ideological expression - simplicities which just will not survive any prolonged experience
of actual works. It was the theory and practice of reductionism - the specific human
experiences and acts of creation converted so quickly and mechanically into
classifications which always found their ultimate reality and significance elsewhere -
which in practice left the field open to anybody who could give an account of art which in
its closeness and intensity at all corresponded to the real human dimension in which art
works are made and valued.
It was above all, as I have said, the received formula of base and superstructure which
made Marxist accounts of literature and thought so often weak in practice. Yet to many
people, still, this formula is near the centre of Marxism, and indicates its appropriate
methodology for cultural history and criticism, and then of course for the relation
between social and cultural studies. The economic base determines the social relations
which determine consciousness which determines actual ideas and works. There can be
endless debate about each of these terms, but unless something like that is believed,
Marxism appears to have lost its most specific and challenging position.
Now for my part I have always opposed the formula of base and superstructure: not
primarily because of its methodological weaknesses but because of its rigid, abstract and
static character. Further, from my own work on the nineteenth century, I came to view it
as essentially a bourgeois formula; more specifically, a central position of utilitarian
thought. I did not want to give up my sense of the commanding importance of
215
economic activity and history. My inquiry in Culture and Society had begun from
just that sense of a transforming change. But in theory and practice I came to believe
that I had to give up, or at least to leave aside, what I knew as the Marxist tradition:
to attempt to develop a theory of social totality; to see the study of culture as
the study of relations between elements in a whole way of life; to find ways of studying
structure, in particular works and periods, which could stay in touch with and illuminate
particular art works and forms, but also forms and relations of more general social life;
to replace the formula of base and superstructure with the more active idea of a field of
mutually if also unevenly determining forces. That was the project of The Long
Revolution, and it seems to me extraordinary, looking back, that I did not then know
the work of Lukács or Goldmann, which would have been highly relevant to it, and
especially as they were working within a more conscious tradition and in less radical an
isolation. I did not even then know, or had forgotten, Marx's analysis of the theory of
utility, in The German Ideology in which - as I now find often happens in reading
and re-reading Marx - what I had felt about the reductionism now embodied in the
base-superstructure formula was given a very precise historical and analytic focus.
This being so, it is easy to imagine my feelings when I discovered an active and
developing Marxist theory, in the work of Lukács and Goldmann, which was exploring many
of the same areas with many of the same concepts, but also with others in a quite
different range. The fact that I learned simultaneously that it had been denounced as
heretical, that it was a return to Left Hegelianism, left-bourgeois idealism, and so on,
did not, I am afraid, detain me. If you're not in a church you're not worried about
heresies; the only real interest is actual theory and practice.
What both LukAcs and Goldmann had to say about reification seemed to me the real
advance. For here the dominance of economic activity over all other forms of human
activity, the dominance of its values over all other values, was given a precise
historical explanation: that this dominance, this deformation, was the specific
characteristic of capitalistic society, and that in modern organized capitalism this
dominance - as indeed one can observe - was increasing, so that this reification, this
false objectivity, was more thoroughly penetrating every other kind of life and
consciousness. The idea of totality was then a critical weapon against this precise
deformation; indeed, against capitalism itself. And yet this was not idealism: an
assertion of the primacy of other values. On the contrary, just as the deformation could
be understood, at its roots, only by economic analysis, so the attempt to overcome and
surpass it lay not in isolated witness or in separated activity but in practical work to
find, to assert and to establish more human social ends in more human political means.
216
And so we come back to Malthus again and to the process of nineteenth-century
naturalism, embracing first the history of the earth and then of life, mind, and society
in a reifying perspective of unvarying and inescapable natural law. One must transcend the
prevailing historiography of science in order to understand the history of science as the
history of reification: "the process through which relations between men take on the
appearance of relations between things; human society and human history, the products of
man, appear not as the products of social activity but as alien and impersonal forces,
laws of nature which impose themselves on humanity from without." The crucial episode
in the history of reification occurred in the Victorian debate on man's place in nature
and laid the foundations of the modern extension of the process to all aspects of thought
and life. It was the nineteenth-century debate which led to the conclusion that morality
and social theory could be - must be - natural sciences and that poverty and inequality
and the hierarchical division of labor are natural, not political, phenomena.
Of course, men and women are both natural and political beings, but the reduction of
the latter to the former converts the general principle of scientific naturalism into an
instrument for domination which elicits deference and resignation. A crucial moment in the
reversal of this process is the overthrow of the views of science and its history which
have led to the mystification known as reification. If we are to understand why people
defer to experts about how they can and should live and to biology for the limits of human
nature and society, we must understand the historical process which produced this set of
abstractions to become common sense and to replace outrage, sapping faith in the ability
to transform society for the benefit of all. The road from Adam Smith and Malthus to the
present and to the critiques by radicals from Marx and Engels to Marcuse's One
Dimensional Man is an unbroken one, and the prerequisite for a radical, critical view
of science and its history is the recovery of outrage at this colossal confidence trick.
The advancing edge of objectivity must be replaced by a revival of radical consciousness
which is developed concomitantly with the growth of radical will and action.
The scientists and historians who were attracted by vulgar Marxism still believed that
science was an unequivocally progressive force, subject only to use and abuse and better
or worse planning.
217
Better planning, it was thought, was occurring in the Soviet Union. A generation later,
many writers of the New Left have also been reluctant to include the ideas and assumptions
of science in he superstructural realm which they are criticizing. There is still tendency
to treat science as an exception, while indulging in criticisms of its abuse in the form
of scientific and technological rationality. Indeed, it can be argued that some of the
Marxists who have been most concerned with science - the Althusserians - indulged
in a theoretical perpetuation of Stalinism. Thus, with this positivism - both in its
post-1930s form and its recent one - has gone deference toward the model for the
development of socialsm which was allegedly being implemented in the Soviet Union.
Characterized in the first place by its assertion of the radical distinction between
judgments of fact and judgments of value, between external reality which is subject to
objective" laws and human activity which can at most pass moral judgments on this
reality or modify it by means of technical action based on the knowledge and utilization
of these objective laws, positivism corresponds to situations where the structures of
.society are so stable that their existence seems unaffected by the action of men who
compose them and experience them. It is true that Marx had exposed at length, in Capital, the illusions of the fetishism of commodities, which makes economic and even
historical laws appear independent of the will of men and comparable to natural laws. This
warning had not, however, been enough to prevent later Marxists from falling victim to the
same illusion, in so far as they lived inside a society which was .relatively stable and
apparently little affected by the transforming action of social classes.
In the Bolshevik camp a situation which until 1917 was in many ways different
nevertheless favoured a related ideology, most clearly expressed in Lenin's What Is To
Be Done? [Because of the low level of political conciousness of the proletariat, it
could not lead to a revolution.] . . . This meant that this part had to be played
by the party, an organization of professional revolutionaries, whose action as the
collective engineer of the revolution would implant a socialist consciousness in the
working .class. The Bolsheviks thus arrived at an equally positivist and objectivizing
conception of society . . .
For the earlier generation, this occurred in the period before there was general
awareness of the nature of the purge trials of the
late 1930s, and long before many socialists came to feel that Stalinism was the truth
of Bolshevism. A society which promises
218
socialism imposed from above, without bringing the consciousness of the people into
full account and without allowing theoretical and practical diversity in implementing it -
a repressive approach embodied in "democratic centralism" in the Soviet Union
and imperial hegemony whereever it could be exercised - could only sanction
"socialist realism" in the arts and vulgar Marxism in the critique of culture.
Nigel Harris points out that vulgar Marxism was the obvious expression of Stalinism and
that it is evident throughout Stalin's theoretical writings:
A "material base" to society, the economic functioning of society, as almost
independent of men. Ideas merely "reflected" material reality (a point from
early Lenin), and political consciousness merely "reflected" the state of
technology - put crudely, gasometers produce poetry via men. The actual lumps of the
economic base - steel plants, cranes, factories and so on - seemed to possess a life of
their own and to compel society to transform itself in conformity with this life. E. P.
Thompson describes the relationship thus: "Ideas are no longer seen as the medium by
which men apprehend the world, reason, argue, debate, and choose; they are like the evil
and wholesome smells arising from the imperialist and proletarian cooking pots."
There is little or no interaction between the base and the rest of society, the
"superstructure," only the base dragging the reluctant superstructure along
behind: "The superstructure is created by the base precisely to serve it, to actively
help it to take shape and consolidate it, to actively fight for the elimination of the old
moribund base, together with its superstructure."
So the specific expressions of Marxism which came to be known as "vulgar" are
themselves the essence of the very reification which Lukács and Goldmann - following the
early Marx - decried. This formulation was the predominant one which was available to
admirers of socialism in action in the 1930s and after. A generation later, some theorists
of the New Left have returned to the writings of the early Marx and argued that these are
continuous with his later writings and provide the basis for a richer theory of the
relationship between socioeconomic factors and intellectual life. They are also free from
deference to the Soviet model and its intellectual expressions and are, indeed, attempting
to elaborate a theory of culture which is inconsistent with the Stalinist experience. One
can remain in sympathy with the struggles of the Soviet
219
people without adhering to the theory of culture which expressed the severest
limitations of that path to socialism.
If there is any life remaining in the base-superstructure distinction, it must be seen
in the light of a much richer conception of the base, one which recovers the manifold
aspects of human experience as expressed in Marx's early writings. His comprehensive view
of nature and society is now being dug out from layer after layer of interpretation from
the point of view of crude economism and supported by the discovery and exegesis of such
fundamental documents as the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 and the Grundrisse.
VI
Before looking further into the potentialities which are held out by New Left and
related writings and which can be employed in the development of a radical historiography
of science and applied to the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature, some
attention should be given to the available alternatives to Rupert Hall's position in the
current bourgeois historlography of science. I shall briefly consider three positions -
only briefly, because I agree in this respect with one of the main current leaders in the
field, Thomas Kuhn, that passé paradigms are not really refuted but merely left behind
when people come to see science in terms of a new framework. The three alternatives are
Imre Lakatos' arguments for "demarcationism" and for the history of science to
be conducted as "rational reconstruction," Thomas Kuhn's theory of
"paradigm shifts" as the process by which science changes, and Robert Merton's
Weberian view of the sociology of science. The main burden of my argument is simple: since
all three of these positions depend upon a fundamental distinction between
"internal" and "external" factors, between science and its context,
they must ultimately be transcended. That is not quite all, however, since some insight
might be gained from noticing the ideological work which such theories perform in
maintaining the central position of scientific rationality at the expense of the
possibilities of liberation.
Of the three positions, Lakatos' demarcationism and his call for "rational
reconstruction" are the easiest to deal with. It is the
220
extreme case of interpreting the past in the light of the present, of seeing the
history of science in the perspective of current orthodoxies. In his papers and his public
performances, Lakatos drew a sharp line between the scientists and the nonscientists.
Since all the candidates for the category of "scientist" turn out to have - as
he put it - "misbehaved" more or less often in their careers, the acceptable
list tends to reduce itself to Galileo and Newton, who are easily dispensed with by
relativists and contextualists who can point to Galileo's Platonism and deductivism and to
Newton's preoccupations with alchemy, biblical chronology and related aspects of his work
which are integral both to his science and to his philosophy of nature. The other side of
Lakatos' firm demarcation is normally filled facetiously with, for example, Marx, Hegel,
Marcuse, Habermas. When critics ask where such ambiguous philosopher-scientists such as
Paracelsus, van Helmont, Priestley, Lyell, Darwin, and Wallace, or the disciplines of
astrology, alchemy, physiognomy, phrenology, mesmerism, spiritualism, and so on are to be
placed, confusion sets in. Lakatos' model is supposed to be falsifiable by means of the
close study of the writings of scientists, conducted by reputable scholars, but when
points are raised which make nonsense of a rigid demarcation between science and other
factors at the center of the scientists' work the scientists are said to have
"misbehaved" or the scholars who make the challenge turn out not to qualify as
"reputable." At the suggestion that the rigid distinction between fact and value
cannot be maintained, Lakatos says that at that point he reaches for his machine gun,
while at the suggestion that his position can best be described as
"meta-methodological Stalinism," he smiles. In order to make the data of the
writings of scientists conform to his model, it is necessary to jettison the fine texture
of history and to rewrite the theories of past scientists as though they knew what we know
now or, more accurately, to stress the aspects of their work which can be tidied up in the
light of modern knowledge. Any strong evidence of intermingling cognitive and social,
constitutive and contextual, factors is relegated to the realm of motivation or of use and
abuse of truth. Lakatos grants that these are interesting subjects, but they are unrelated
to the serious study of the history of scientific rationality itself. Like most approaches
to the history of science which begin with logical preoccupations in the philosophy of science, his development of the Popperian position
221
proves itself both distorting and irrelevant to the preoccupations of historians. In
short, most significant questions are begged as a result of appealing to a fundamentally
positivist conception of "rationality."
Thomas Kuhn's theory as set forth in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions must
be taken altogether more seriously, if only because it has been the single most
influential view in the historiography of science for the past two decades. While its
catalytic role is very important, it is also necessary to take a critical view of the
reactions which it has facilitated. It has undoubtedly had an important liberating effect
on practicing scientists (both natural and social) and on students in the history and
philosophy of science. It was not too sanguine to ask, when his essay first appeared, if
it heralded "A Revolution in the Historiography of Science." I shall argue that
the intervening decades have shown that as far as any radical political implications which
might have flowed from his work are concerned, the clear answer is no. However, it has the
significant merit of having freed the self-consciousness of both scientists and of
neophytes in the study of its history and concepts from a unilinear, cumulative,
progressive conception of scientific change. His own work - as well as that of the
critics, interpreters, and expositors of it - has suffered from an important uncertainty
over pursuing its sociological or its philosophical implications. Kuhn brought
sociological criteria to bear on the alternating periods of stability and change within
the scientific community and immensely sharpened our sense of the social process of
conceptual change. His distinctions between "normal" and
"revolutionary" periods in science, and between preparadigm and paradigmatic
states of scientific disciplines have proved very attractive, and in some circles the term
"paradigm" has replaced those of "concept," "theory," and
"idea." Kuhn would be the last to be glad about the loose use of his key
theoretical term, but he has admitted that it is very difficult indeed to specify the
units of change which qualify as paradigm shifts. Even so, scientists who read his book
say that it is the only writing in the history and philosophy of science which comes near
to reflecting the way science feels to those who are doing it.
At the philosophical level his theory raised fundamental questions, leading even the
attentive reader to find in his writings a strong support for historical relativism.
People who think in
222
different paradigms seem to inhabit different worlds with sharp discontinuities between
them. Facts which are explained in one paradigm become less important if unexplained in
another. The image of the slow accumulation of anomalies which produce a fundamental
reorientation of explanatory priorities - a "gestalt switch" - highlights the
discontinuities in scientific change at the expense of leaving its conceptual - and
especially its methodological - continuities unexplained. It is not surprising that the
apparently relativistic implications of his theory produced considerable alarm among
rigorous, traditional philosophers of science, who have argued that he is in danger of
undermining the very basis of rationality in science.
But it turns out that there is little to worry about. Kuhn has been unequivocal and
vocal in dissociating himself from the potentially radical implications of his theory in
both the sociological and epistemological realms. His comments on the reception of his
theory and his "Reflections on My Critics" have been very reassuring, even
affable. But more important than this, his analysis of the relationship between
"internal" and "external" factors has reinforced the very distinction
which he appeared at one time to be bringing into question. Having produced a lucid
analysis of the dilemma, he has gone on to stress the internal factors at the expense of
the external ones, thereby falling even to address himself to the issue of their mutual
interpenetration and the deeper claim that they are constitutive of each other. On the
question of the origins of Darwin's theory, for example, he considers the influence of
Malthus to be "vitally important" and challenges those who do not agree to
explain the proliferation of evolutionary theories in the pre-Darwinian era. He goes on to
say, however,
Yet these speculative theories were uniformly anathema to the scientists whom Charles
Darwin managed to persuade in the course of making evolutionary theory a standard
ingredient of the Western intellectual heritage. What Darwin did, unlike these
predecessors, was to show how evolutionary concepts should be applied to a mass of
observational materials which had accumulated only during the first half of the nineteenth
century and were, quite independently of evolutionary ideas, already making trouble for
several recognised scientific specialties. This part of the Darwin story, without which
the whole cannot be understood, demands analysis of the changing state, during the decades
before the Origin of Species, of fields like stratigraphy and paleontology, the
geographical
223
study of plant and animal distribution, and the increasing success of classificatory
systems which substituted morphological resemblances for Linneaus' parallelisms of
function. The men who, in developing natural systems of classification, first spoke of
tendrils as "aborted" leaves or who accounted for the differing number of
ovaries in closely related plant species by referring to the "adherence" in one
species of organs separate in the other were not evolutionists by any means. But without
their work, Darwin's Origin could not have achieved either its final form or its
impact on the scientific and the lay public.
Kuhn deplores the absence of a literature "which has attempted to explain the
emergence of Darwinism as a response to the development of scientific ideas or
techniques" and finds irony in an analysis of the relations between Malthus and the
evolutionists which does not "make any attempt to deal with the technical issues
which may have helped to shape Darwin's thought." The irony is said to lie in my
failure to make that attempt in a treatment which seeks to break down the barrier between
internal and external factors by stressing the crucial role of Malthus' theory in the
formulation of the mechanism for evolutionary change independently discovered by Darwin
and Wallace.
We are here involved in many layers of irony. At the simple level, to some of Darwin's
contemporaries - for example, Wallace, Owen, and Lewes - the so-called speculative
theories of evolution were far from "uniformly anathema." Wallace was inspired
by Chambers' theory to seek a mechanism; Owen was attracted by it (but unconvinced by
Darwin); and Lewes defended both. Similarly, Lyell's attempted refutation of Lamarck's
theory was decisive in leading Spencer to accept and expound a version of Lamarckianism,
and Spencer's evolutionary theory was accepted wholeheartedly by Hughlings Jackson, whose
influence was fundamental in the development of evolutionary neurology and
neurophysiology. Such examples can be greatly multiplied in support of the conclusion that
it is difficult to maintain a sharp distinction between the nature and influence of the
Darwin-Wallace theory and of those of the so-called speculative evolutionists.
It is certainly true, as Kuhn argues, that geological, paleontological, and
zoogeographical data were central to the work of both Darwin and Wallace and especially
that Darwin's Notebooks and his published writings contain and explain "large
classes of facts." Kuhn is also obviously right to say that without consideration of
224
these data, the whole of the origin, development, and reception of their theories
cannot be understood. But the task does not merely involve a judicious mixture of
so-called internal and external factors. The factors are indeed mixed, and Kuhn's position
is an advance on the unrelenting internalism of Smith and de Beer. The very sort of close
analysis of the relevant empirical findings in their intricate relations with Darwin's
speculations and the theories which he considered in the course of his reflections has
been undertaken by Howard Gruber in his conceptual biography of Darwin's discovery. In
addition, a study of the crucial role of Malthus' theory helps to redress the balance of
historical analysis, but even a balanced view cannot overcome the deeper irony in Kuhn's
approach.
His theory is based on the claim that it is a buildup of anomalous empirical findings
which leads finally to a paradigm shift. That is, the accumulation of internal findings,
in the social context of the internal logic of the scientific community, is the decisive
factor. Kuhn relegates "the ambient intellectual milieu" to "the
rudimentary stages of the development of a field" and, after that, confines its
influence "to the concrete technical problems with which the practitioners of that
field engage." This approach, of course, omits both the general theoretical level in
a given science and, more importantly, the central role of socioeconomic assumptions in
the philosophies of nature, man, and society which underlie and constrain, and in some
cases determine, the content of scientific theories and even particular facts. As I have
argued here, these pervasive assumptions are more obvious - i.e., less mediated - in the
biological and human sciences. It is not surprising that Kuhn's background in the physical
sciences has led him to develop a general theory which is hardly relevant to the features
of the non-physicochemical sciences which are most interesting to historians and which
lead most directly to an ideological analysis.
Looking briefly at Kuhn's view of the influence of science on the general culture, his
claims are more extreme and even astonishing: "Science, when it affects
socio-economic development at all, does so through technology." He goes on to argue
that science and technology should, as a first approximation, be treated "as
radically distinct enterprises." A consistent application of his approach in
this aspect of the subject would preclude an appreciation
225
of the role of science and scientific rationality in shaping the assumptions of modern
capitalistic society, extending even to its concept of rationality. In the particular case
of the nineteenth-century debate, it would lead one to declare irrelevant the whole
structure of social, political, economic, and related theories which was erected on the
basis of extrapolations from and rationalizations of evolutionary theory.
When the consequences of the internalist-externalist dichotomy and the ultimate failure
of Kuhnian historiography to transcend it finally become clear, it also becomes evident
that the excitement caused by his approach is, in the end, a mystification. In the course
of finding his insights liberating because of their introduction of social factors in the
process of conceptual change, it was not noticed that he thereby excluded socioeconomic
factors from the substance of science, and he precluded the fundamental task of
analyzing the levels of the relevance of the assumptions on which they were based.
In some respects, Kuhn's critique lends support to a contextualist approach, but in the
end he repudiates the relativist - and certainly the ideological - affiliations which his
admirers have offered. He has provided us with a sort of internalist's contextualism
concerned with a social milieu, but it is the social context of scientists in the society
of science, not in the world. It is for this reason that the similarities between Kuhn,
Gillispie, Popper, and Lakatos are greater than those between Kuhn and others whose
research can be described as full-bloodedly (many would still add sanguinely)
contextualist and relativist. He appears to be more of an ally than he is because he
undermines belief in one continuous rational tradition in science, but he has shown
himself to be very unwilling to allow radical implications (either philosophical or
political) to be drawn from his position. Indeed, he is not unnaturally rather like
Lakatos in expecting the history of science to conform to his model, and attempts to
influence research in the history of science accordingly. It should be obvious from the
argument of this essay that all of us do this more or less selfconsciously. The
politically partisan nature of these activities and their parent ideological positions
must, however, be made explicit. Then we can get on with determining whose view of science
and its history is just and liberating rather than whose is "rational."
Debates about justice are frankly concerned with conflicts
226
of values, while those about rationality appeal to the very concept of objectivity
which is in question. (Of course, the issue will not be decided in a debating chamber.)
Kuhn might forcefully reply that we see the world according to different paradigms of
science. The rebuttal to that is that we see science through different paradigms of the world as it is, as it ought to be, and might be if people were freed from the mystifications
of scientific rationality.
Kuhn's work is representative of the highest standards in the prevailing orthodoxy in
the history of science. It is also seductive in that it takes us to the limits of the
current orthodoxy and appears to go beyond them. His own reactions to those who have
attempted to step beyond the established tradition help to show that he ultimately draws
back.
Robert K. Merton is the doyen of the sociology of science. His pioneering Science,
Technology, and Society in Seventeenth-Century England was his doctoral
dissertation, was first published in 1938 as an entire issue of Osiris, and
reappeared in 1970 with a new introduction in a paperbound edition. His volume of essays, Social Theory and Social Structure - including seven chapters on the sociologies of
science and of knowledge - went through three editions and nineteen printings between 1949
and 1968. When Merton took up the subject of the sociology of science, it was a neglected
area. Although it remains so, interest in it is growing (largely for political and
ecological reasons), and most subsequent work has taken Merton's writings as a starting
point for development or criticism. His is therefore the central position for assessing
the sociological analysis of science. He sees his own work in the tradition of the
"sociology of knowledge," an approach which studies the relations among the
social origins, the substance, and the role of ideas. The originator of modern analyses of
the sociology of knowledge was Karl Mannheim, whose Ideology and Utopia itself
reflects a bourgeois version of Lukács' argument in History and Class Consciousness. The
other major influence on Mannheim was Max Weber, whose The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism provides the conceptual framework for Merton's approach. Weber
has been called "the bourgeois Marx," Mannheim "the bourgeois
Lukács." Merton's intellectual debts extend further, to the Harvard "Pareto
Circle," led the conservative physiologist by Lawrence J. Henderson. This was a group
explicitly concerned with providing an alternative to the growing radicalism in Cambridge,
Massachusetts, in the years of the Great
227
Depression. In the light of this intellectual parentage, it would be surprising if
Merton's approach proved to be of much use to a radical historiography, and there are, it
turns out, no surprises in store.
The criticisms to be made about Merton's approach from the point of view of the
requirements of a radical historiography of science are relatively straightforward and add
up to the conclusion that he never confronts the substance of scientific findings,
theories, or assumptions about nature, man, and society. He is far in advance of the
traditional internalist history of ideas in addressing himself to the social and
ideological context and basis of the ethos of science, but his approach to these issues is
expository and analytic and is entirely lacking a critical dimension. His analyses are
concerned with the role, the tempo, and the choice of research problems of science and
scientists; externalist criteria are applied to these. Yet despite his commitment to
treating the sociology of science as a branch of the sociology of knowledge, he nowhere
confronts the very relationships which define the domain of investigation of the sociology
of knowledge. He is concerned with science on the one hand and its context on the other,
and that very distinction precludes serious analysis, even according to the limited goals
of the sociology of knowledge. He is aware of the central issue in the Mannheimian
approach - whether or not there is any knowledge which is "objective" or value
neutral - but he skirts it and its relativistic implications. Instead of addressing it
directly, he mentions it as a fear on the part of those who oppose the sociological
approach to science. In the light of these features of his work, it is not surprising that
he is dismissive of the Marxist approach. Even in expressing sympathy for the general
investigation of "the interplay between socio-economic and scientific
development" and in pointing out the limits of the vulgar-Marxist line, he simply
sidesteps the central problem and concentrates on the "structural determinants of
scientists' behaviour."
A few examples will illuminate his characteristic avoidance of the substance of
science. In his work on the seventeenth century, he says, "Much of our study will, in
fact, be devoted to the isolation of some of the extra-scientific elements which strongly
influenced, if they did not determine, the centering of scientific attention upon certain
fields of investigation." There is no analysis of the results of tilling those
fields, only of what religious, social, and economic motives led men to do so. Elsewhere
he mentions
228
characteristic preoccupations such as the influence of the Protestant ethic on
"the attitudes of scientists toward their work. Discussions of the why and wherefore
of science bore a point-to-point correlation with the Puritan teachings on the same
subject." Similarly, for the virtuosi, "science found its rationale in the end
of all existence: glorification of God." He discusses "a set of largely implicit
assumptions which made for the ready acceptance of the scientific temper characteristic of
the seventeenth and subsequent centuries." He is particularly interested in the
social and theological roots of the value-free orientation of science - the scientific
ethos - and their 'nfluence on the motives and personal attitudes of natural philosophers
in the period, as well as their modern expressions. Finally, he directs attention to the
socioeconomic factors which facilitate and obstruct scientific activities in general and
as directed toward individual problems.
I want to make three points about Merton's work. First, as I have said, neither his
interests nor his methods lead him into the substance of science: he need never read
through and analyze the argument of a given scientific paper or treatise. He can skim it
in order to determine its topic rather than concern himself with what is said about the
topic. He seeks to identify the religious affiliations of its practitioners, to determine
the subject matter of papers and treatises, and to read personal and reflective works
which link science - as an activity directed to particular topics - to the Puritan ethos.
The internal-external dichotomy can never be transcended, since the substance of science
is never considered in detail.
Second, there is no critical approach to the socioeconomic, theological, and
ideological factors which are being related to science. These are taken as given, and
there is therefore no evaluative dimension to the inquiry. Since the objectivity of
scientific findings and theories is also taken as given, the exercise reduces itself to a
desiccated correlation. Since a critical approach to the ideological dimensions and their
relations to the substance of scientific findings and theories are the sine qua non of
a radical historiography, Merton can provide no aid in that endeavor, except as a case
study in mystification. Little purpose would be served by dwelling on this point, since
excellent critiques are available of the parent tradition of Weberian analysis in Herbert
Marcuse's essay "Industrialisation and Capitalism in the Work of Max Weber" and
M. D. King's devastating criticism of Merton's (and to a lesser extent
229
Kuhn's) positivist approach and his assumptions in a penetrating essay entitled
"Reason, Tradition, and the Progressiveness of Science."
The third point to be made about Merton's work has a reflexive quality which brings us
back to our original problem. That is, his assumptions are functionalist. Indeed, he is
probably the most sophisticated expositor of the functionalist approach in the social
sciences. In a separate study, I have attempted to provide a critical outline of
functionalism, the relevant aspect of which for present purposes is the profoundly
reactionary effect of attempting to base sociological assumptions on the model of
evolutionary biology, since the concepts of adaptation, equilibrium, and survival of the
system are taken as given and value neutral. In the context of the problem of studying the
nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature, it is particularly ironic that one of
the main reconciling rationalizations which was erected on the basis of evolutionary
theory could be used as an approach for the critical study of the origins and ideological
role of evolutionary theory. The use of an approach which assumes the validity of
biological analogies to evaluate critically the role of biological analogies seems rather
unpromising.
Once again, let us recall the distance between the positions of Lakatos, Kuhn, and
Merton on the one hand and the orthodoxy in the historiography of science reflected in
Hall's article, "Merton Revisited," on the other. In order to gain a clear
perspective on the work of each of them, it would be necessary to examine in detail the
meaning of their being children of their times according to the theory of mediation which
is being called for here. In the case of Merton, we have a number of analyses of the
intellectual tradition of functionalism and its particular social basis at Harvard in the
1930s from the research of Barbara Heyl. This would have to be complemented by a detailed
knowledge of Merton's personal history. Such studies would play a useful role in the
development of a radical historiography, but they do not accurately reflect the gap
between that and the current consciousness of the profession of the history of science.
For the great majority of those doing research in the 1960s and 1970s the current view was
still expressed by Hall's analysis. How do he and the positions he defends reflect their times?
The decade which Hall reviews was one of avoidance of overt
230
political agitation: it was the period which lay between the era of witch-hunting of
Communists (the Army-McCarthy hearings were in 1953) and the emergence of the student
movement (the Berkeley protests and the Gulf of Tonkin Resolution occurred in 1964). This
atmosphere was reflected, although less intensely, in other NATO countries. In the
relevant period, Hall worked in Cambridge, England, Indiana, and London. That period was
also the era of the conservatives' claim that we had reached "the end of
ideology." Hall's thesis not only fails to find promise in Merton's approach, but in
rejecting it, he equates it with externalism. He is thereby unable to make a clear
distinction between idealist explanations in the light of the Puritan ethos and other
arguments about the intellectual superstructure which relate it directly to economic and
social factors. That is, in the period in which no one was confronting Marxism, Hall was
allowing the Weberian-Mertonian tradition to stand for all sorts of socioeconomic
interpretations. For example, his analysis of Merton's work is interrupted by comments on
the Marxist historian S. Lilley, without any indication that there is a fundamental
distinction between their approaches: Lilley asks a question which would not occur to
Weber or Merton - "What is Puritanism a mediation of?"
Hall's fastidious reaction to the assumptions of Merton's thesis clearly shows the
strong disinclination which the advocates of the internal history of scientific ideas feel
toward approaching science in even contextualist terms. They would presumably be even less
inclined to welcome a step beyond contextualism - from the ethos and activities of science
and scientists to their substantive findings and theories. If Weber was a bourgeois Marx,
and Merton a functionalization and Americanization of that position, and if Hall finds this too political and social, how can one expect any sympathetic understanding of Marxism
itself? However, it would be wrong to conclude that Hall's position is merely one of false
consciousness.
On the contrary, he is candid about the basis of internalism as seen from his own point
of view:
One issue between the externalist and the internalist interpretation is this: was the
beginning of modern science the outstanding feature of early modern civilisation, or must
it yield in importance to others, such as the Reformation or the development of
capitalism? Before 1940 most general historians and many historians of science would have
adopted the latter
231
position; since 1940 nearly all historians have adopted the former one. Why this change
should have come about is not hard to imagine.
By this I do not mean to suggest that the problems raised by the sociologists of
science are obsolete; on the contrary, as some scientists like J. D. Bernal have been
saying for a long time and many more are saying now, they are immensely real and direct at
this moment. Consequently the historical evolution of this situation is of historical
significance too, and I believe we shall return to its consideration when a certain
revulsion from the treatment of scientists as puppets has been overcome, when (if ever) we
are less guiltily involved in the situation ourselves so that we can review it without
passion, and when a fresh approach has been worked out. This will not, I imagine, take the
form so much of a fusion between two opposite positions in the manner of the Hegelian
dialectic, as the demarcation of their respective fields of application with some degree
of accuracy. There may also develop a socio-techno-economic historiography whose study
will be the gradual transformation of society by science and not (as too often in the
past) the rapid transformation of science by society. All this will require a fine
analysis, a scrupulous drawing of distinctions and a careful avoidance (except under
strict controls) of evidence drawn from subjective, propagandist and programmatic sources.
A true sociology of science will deal with what actually happened and could happen, not
with what men thought might happen or should happen.
It would be difficult to imagine a better expression of the position of a
humane, liberal scholar, speaking with complete sincerity. Hall suggests a sociopolitical
basis for the trend toward internalist historiography of ideas: the abuse of science and
scientists since the early days of World War II and the continuation of this in the atomic
arms race. Remove these abuses, and the students of science be able to return to
distinguishing clearly and carefully the sphere of science from that of society in a
dispassionate, scrupulous, objective way. All trace of subjective, political, or
ideological bias must be kept out "(except under strict controls)." Lastly, a
true sociology of science should be concerned with the facts, not with the aims or
purposes of interest groups.
Hall's explanation should be contrasted on the one hand with J. G. Crowther's review of
it and on the other with the criteria of a radical historiography. Crowther devotes two
short chapters to it: "A New Scholasticism" and "External and Internal
Influences on Research." Once again, we should recall the epigraph: Crowther is a
child of the same times that inspired Needham and
232
Bernal, and one would therefore expect his interpretation to err on the side of direct
correlation between sociopolitical and intellectual developments. It should not be
thought, however, that the earlier Marxist historiography was simply mistaken: it was
merely woefully incomplete. Crowther does not appeal to liberal revulsion but to political
and economic self-interest on the part of historians of science:
The social relations of science, which have such an intense bearing on contemporary
politics, are liable to become controversial and disturbing. It is easy to understand the
attraction of other aspects of the history of science, which are less liable to invoke
controversy, and offer the promise of a long period of undisturbed study.
Nor are the foundations which disburse research funds
disposed to support researches which might attract public attention in a period of
political excitement. They do not favour researches which might throw an unfavourable
light on how the capital, with which the foundations are endowed, was originally
accumulated. In recent times, this has often been the result of the exploitation of
science and invention.
Hence there is a tendency to support researches on non-controversial, non-social and
non-political subjects, and the young historian of science is under pressure to choose
subjects which appear to have as little relevance as possible to contemporary events, and
engage in the solitary explorations of scholasticism.
He explains the small volume of work on the social relations of science since 1940, and
more particularly since 1953, as
the result of a long-range natural protective action, by dominant interests that do not
wish to have the social and political implications of their scientific policy
comprehensively investigated.
They prefer that historians of science should withdraw into the socially disembodied
history of scientific ideas. This would tend to establish the notion that science exists
without any obligations to society.
So, since 1940, the historians of science have given less and less aid to the solution
of the problem of science in its relation to society. The effect of this is to strengthen
the traditional conservative theory of the dominant interests, and widen and harden the
ancient fissure between the intellectual and the social life. A ruling conservative
ideology is left more firmly than ever in control of the new scientific powers.
It is a typical vulgar-Marxist exaggeration to attribute self-conscious policies and
intentions to the ruling elite and to young
233
historians of science. I cannot speak for the grant-giving foundations, but as one who
began research in the period, I can only say that there was in us an unanalyzed sense that
communism was bad but no conscious juxtaposition of Marxism with the history of science.
We were not keeping our heads down: it simply never occurred to us to select socially
relevant problems or to approach them from a Mertonian, much less a Marxist, perspective.
False consciousness is not self-consciousness: it is highly mediated by the social and
intellectual context. But, as we have noted, changed people with changed consciousness are
the products of changed times which react upon the interpretation of science in society.
And that brings us back to the New Left.
VII
It would be gratifying if - having attempted to work our way through the mystifications
of the internal history of ideas, vulgar Marxism, and the historiographic approaches of
Lakatos, Kuhn, and Merton - we could turn with confidence to the writings of current
Marxist historians for guidance. Instead, we find that many Marxists are as deferential to
science as their bourgeois antagonists, and it becomes necessary to pick one's way with
great care through a whole body of literature for suggestions and hints. The New Left has
been very successful indeed in bringing about the end of "the end of ideology"
in intellectual life - or, rather, in unmasking it. The Marxist views of intellectual
production, the role of the intelligentsia and of the universities have, in varying
degrees, been revived by recent Marxist writers. They have also produced a critique which
grants a potentially significant revolutionary role to students and intellectuals and have
pointed out their long-term interests in making common cause with the workers against the
ruling elites. But they stop short at the door of the scientific laboratory.
An excellent example of this comes from an acrimonious debate between two socialist
historians, Perry Anderson and E. P. Thompson. Anderson was the editor of the New Left
Review, the leading intellectual periodical of the New Left. Although many would argue
that its policy leaves a great deal to be desired in the realm of political agitation and
praxis (especially with respect to the relations between the role of intellectuals and the
struggles of
234
other workers) its role in consciousness raising has been considerable. Partially in
collaboration with Tom Nairn, Anderson wrote a series of articles which covered a wide
range of issues which had - and have - to be faced by the British Left., Edward Thompson
is an ex-member of the British Communist Party (resigned over Hungary, 1956) and
the author of a distinguished and massive work, The Making of the English Working
Class, a model of Marxist analysis of the fine texture of a historical development. It
was from the depths of his detailed scholarship that Thompson made a highly polemical
critique of Anderson and Nairn's theoretical endeavors, especially their sweeping
generalizations. It is not central to my present purpose to attempt to evaluate their
respective positions, although the issues which they were debating are basic ones which
must be faced in any serious Marxist analysis. Rather, I want to focus on their treatment
of my own topic.
The first point is that Anderson and Nairn simply do not mention Darwin in their
critique of the Victorian bourgeoisie in the nineteenth century. In this they have much in
common with other intellectual, political, and social historians of the period. But in
pointing out this omission, Thompson gives an assessment of Darwin and evolutionism which
is simplistic in the extreme and is difficult to credit to such a meticulous and incisive
scholar. Darwin is represented as the pure empirical scientist, the quintessential example
of the best in the British tradition. Thompson notices the basis of the facts which Darwin
considers in the "culture of agrarian capitalists, who had spent decades in empirical
horticulture and stock-breeding." It is true that Darwin relied very heavily on data
from the world of domestic stock-breeding, yet Thompson's account utterly fails to notice
Darwin's place in the intellectual tradition of ideological debate on the philosophies of
nature, man, and society. At this deeper level it is absurd to suggest that Darwin was a
pure scientist and to contrast him sharply with Huxley, who is represented as a pure
ideologue. Marx and Engels saw Darwin's role and context very clearly; how could Thompson
have forgotten it? When he turns to the evolutionary debate, he reveals almost total
ignorance.
There should have been more crisis than there was, more of a parting of the ideological
heavens. The intellectuals should have signalled their commitments; signed manifestos;
identified their allegiances in the
235
reviews. The fact that there was comparatively little of this may be accounted for by
the fact that Darwin addressed a protestant and post-Baconian public, which had long
assumed that if God was at issue with a respectable Fact (of if a dogma was at odds with a
man's conscience) it was the former which must give way.
The simplest way of dealing with this and Thompson's other pronouncements on Darwin
would be - as a first approximation - to place "not" at the relevant place in
each sentence; the result would be closer to the situation in the period than what he does
say.
It would be helpful if Perry Anderson's (even more) polemical reply simply corrected
Thompson's crudities, but it only compounds them. He reveals no better appreciation of one
of the most vehement debates among all levels of society in the period - and especially in
manifestos and reviews. Anderson merely (and erroneously) notes that the issue had been
settled earlier - in the Enlightenment. This only adds to the absurdities, since at one
level the debate was very heated indeed, while at another it is clear that evolutionism
was not opposed to theism. It only shifted the level of analysis of a theistic
approach: identifying the laws of nature with the laws of God. On the question of whether
or not there was a crisis, the writers in the Victorian periodicals studied by Ellegard in
his book on the reception of Darwin's theory of evolution in the British periodical press,
1859-72, would have been surprised to be told this: the mere listing of the periodicals
covers fifteen pages, while a comparable list of pamphlets and books would be very
extensive indeed. Even the most unsatisfactory accounts of the debate acknowledge the
tremendous controversy which evolutionism engendered: the dramatic confrontation between
Bishop Samuel Wilberforce and T. H. Huxley at the Oxford meeting of the British
Association in 1860 is the incident in the Victorian crisis of faith which is perhaps the
most widely known of all.
But Thompson and Anderson share a far more misleading and fundamentally un-Marxist
assumption which Anderson puts unequivocally as "the basic ontological difference
between the natural and the human sciences." He concludes that "it follows, of
course, that the modern natural sciences are relatively (not, of course, absolutely)
asocial in character. They partake of a 'natural objectivity,' which is precisely that of
the structure of their object.
236
Darwinism is no exception." For both Thompson and Anderson, Darwin was a pure
scientist. Anderson makes a sharp distinction between Darwin as a scientist and the
ideological uses to which his theory was put:
Darwin's discoveries were not, of themselves, ideological: ' it was their use which was - and about this he [Thompson] says nothing at all. Yet Darwinism is probably
the most dramatic case history of a scientific theory giving immediate birth to a social
ideology. No other scientific discovery was ever as rapidly "politicized" as
this. "The survival of the fittest" and "the natural law of selection"
became a ruthless celebration of Victorian racism and imperialism: These axioms provided a
benison for class, society, and a mystique for militarism. They did so in the name of a natural destiny inscribed in the course of things.
Anderson is certainly right to relate the evolutionary movement to the social and
political philosophies which employed "Darwinism" as a rationalization. But,
unlike Marx and Engels, he fails to see the continuity between Utilitarianism, the wide
movement which included Darwinian and other evolutionary theories, and post-Darwinian
social and political rationalizations. It is an unbroken tradition, aspects of which have
been discussed here, and which must be seen in a single, totalizing framework embracing
science and society and their mutual determinations. The distinction between the
constitutive aspects of science and the contextual factors which play upon it must be
broken down. One can only say "Et tu" to two of Anderson's concluding
remarks: "Thompson tribute to Darwin ..... over-simplifies the question of the social
character of natural science." "He has leapt into controversies about which he
knows little; he has allowed literary flourishes to get the upper hand over sober
accuracy."
It would be misleading to suggest that Anderson's position over Darwinism is an
aberrant mistake. On the contrary, it is consistent with his whole approach to ideology.
In his otherwise valuable critique of the ideology of British intellectual life,
"Components of the National Culture," he explicitly excludes the natural
sciences and the creative arts from his analysis and suggests that
the dose of "objectivity" in the natural sciences and
"subjectivity" in art is symmetrically greater than either in the social
sciences......., and they therefore have correspondingly more mediated relationships to
the social structure. They do not, in other words, directly provide our basic concepts
237
of man and society - the natural sciences because they forge concepts for the
understanding of nature, not society, and art because it deals with man and
society, but does not provide us with their concepts.
Anderson has changed his views more than once since writing this, but since the changes
were in the direction of Althusserian and Popperian positions - ones which intensify the
problems being discussed here - the point being made here remains.
It should be clear by now that the approach I am advocating implies that the "more
mediated relationships" of the natural sciences to the social structure should become
the central concern of a Marxist historiography of science. Once again, it should be
stressed that this is not a new suggestion but a revival of the original Marxist position,
one which has been vitiated by vulgar Marxism. Anderson's claims are very ironic in the
present, since the natural and especially the biological sciences are - both
directly and analogically - providing basic concepts for the interpretation of society.
Until we understand the central role of scientific rationality in the network of issues
which sustains the hierarchical division of labor, there will be an irreconcilable
conflict between the sources of the potential liberation of humanity from struggle with
nature and people on the one hand and genuine democracy on the other. The undertaking of
this analysis is being blocked by the distinction which Anderson wants to maintain in both
the Darwinian case and in the analysis of current intellectual life. The same approach
should be applied both to Darwin and to the present. As Marx said,
Upon the different forms of property, upon the social conditions of existence, rises an
entire superstructure of distinct and peculiarly formed sentiments, illusions, modes of
thought and views of life. The entire class forms and creates them out of its material
foundations and out of the corresponding social relations.
It is particularly ironic that Anderson should - in a Marxist argument - preclude
Darwin from ideological analysis, since one can buy a whole volume of writings by Marx and
Engels arguing against the Malthusian basis of Darwinism and the whole philosophy of
nature and man which this putatively unideological Darwin crowned with scientific
respectability. Where are we to draw the line between the sources, content, and influence
of Darwinism? Anderson should be able to see that the applicability of
238
ideological analysis to the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature is not
as contentious as it would be, for example, in physics, where the mediations are far more
complex and subtle. Ideological analysis was originally applied to the examination of
social ideas in terms of their social location - the class interests of those who produce
them and benefit from them, along with the general conditions that affect their nature,
distribution, and acceptance. The point about evolutionary theory is that it is the
central conception linking humanity and social theory to natural science. The very
existence of evolutionary theory and its general acceptance raise the question of whether
sharp distinctions can be made between those disciplines which are amenable to ideological
analysis and those which are not or are qualitatively less so.
In this form the question highlights the pivotal position of biology between the
natural and the human sciences. In the present connection, however, the problem arises in
another form. The distinction between the inescapability of ideology in the liberal arts
including history - and the alleged objectivity of the natural sciences place the
historian of science in an absurd position. All of these problems come together if
one is (1) a historian of (2) science whose interest is (3) evolutionary
theory (4) in the period when the putative boundaries between science and matters to do
with human nature were (5) the subject of intense public debate. Even if one wanted to
argue for sharp distinctions between the physicochemical and other sciences, the history
of biological and human sciences in the nineteenth century could not confidently be
excluded from the domain of ideological analysis on the most restricted definition of that
domain. My own position is that ideological analysis knows no boundaries, but even those
who do not grant this position should be able to see its applicability to the
nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature.
If we cannot turn directly to otherwise sophisticated and subtle Marxist writers, where
can we look for guidance and solidarity in the task of developing a radical, libertarian
socialist approach to science and its history? There are grave limitations to the
usefulness of the writings of Thompson and Anderson on the matters discussed earlier, but
other aspects of their work are important and useful. Similarly, as we have seen, the
historiographic writings of Hobsbawm and Williams are directly relevant. There are other
239
helpful current writers who will be mentioned later, but surely the first task is to
return to Marx:
The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas: i.e., the class
which is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the material means of production at its disposal, has
control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally
speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it.
The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material
relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the
relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its
dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things
consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and
determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its
whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and
regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are
the ruling ideas of the epoch.
... If now in considering the course of history we detach the ideas of the ruling class
from the ruling class itself and attribute to them an independent existence, if we confine
ourselves to saying that these or those ideas were dominant at a given time, without
bothering ourselves about the conditions of production and the producers of these ideas,
if we thus ignore the individuals and world conditions which are the source of the ideas,
we can say, for instance, that during the time that the aristocracy was dominant, the
concepts honour, loyalty, etc., were dominant, during the dominance of the bourgeoisie the
concepts of freedom, equality, etc. The ruling class on the whole imagines this to be so.
This conception of history, which is common to all historians, particularly since the
eighteenth century, will necessarily come up against the phenomenon that increasingly
abstract ideas hold sway, i.e., ideas which increasingly take on the form of universality.
For each new class which puts itself in the place of one ruling before it, is compelled,
merely in order to carry through its aim, to represent its interest as the common interest
of all the members of society, that is, expressed in ideal form: it has to give its ideas
the form of universality, and represent them as the only rational, universally valid ones.
Although Marx is here talking about nonscientific ideas, it is the general form of his
thesis which should provide the perspective for a radical interpretation of science and
its history in any
240
epoch. In particular, the development of the philosophies of nature, man, and
society which run through the debate on man's place in nature in nineteenth-century
Britain needs to be interpreted in the light of general trends from a theory suitable for
a pastoral, agrarian, aristocratic world to one which reflects a competitive, urban,
industrial one. In the same period the view of God changed from a natural theology of
harmony in nature and society (with direct appeals for explanation of their order), to a
Deity identified with the self-acting laws of nature. The latter were laws of progress
through struggle, in which the inequalities of society were not justified by a divinely
ordained social status. Rather, they were based on a biological one of the hierarchical
division of labor which, in turn, depended on the universal law of "the physiological division of labor." Science did not replace God: God became identified with the laws
of nature. Adam Smith, Paley, Malthus, Darwin, Chambers, Spencer, the "Social
Darwinists," and the emergence of functionalism, pragmatism, psychoanalysis, and
numerous other theorists and their schools can then be seen as part of a continuous
development. That development was the substitution of one form of rationalization of the
hierarchical relations among people for another - from the projection of natural theology
to the reification of society through biologism. Belief in the mystical union of
"order and progress" altered in the course of the debate from natural theology,
in alliance with the mechanical psychology of associationism, to biological evolutionism
in alliance with an organic version of associationism. In the course of this period there
was a change from the theodicy of sufficient reason of Adam Smith and William Paley to
that of Herbert Spencer: cosmic evolution. The secularization which occurred in the period
was really a new context for belief in progressive harmony based on "the nature of
things." Looking further, it is worth considering whether or not the new
technological revolution in our own time is merely an extension of the same historical
development - based on organic analogies but embodied in scientific management, management
science, cybernetics, systems analysis, operational research, and the world of computers
and biotechnology.
This view of the debate extending from the Newtonian conception of society in Adam
Smith to the present is based on a general notion of history and epistemology: the
processes by which
241
conceptions of nature come to be defined are fundamentally the same as those by which
conceptions of society are developed. The traditional distinction between genetic and
analytic accounts in philosophy and science should be softened so as to mesh with the
weaker use of that distinction in interpersonal and social interpretations. Similarly, the
whole distinction between the content and validity of an idea and its context should also
be considerably softened. Nothing is ultimately contextual: all is constitutive, which is
another way of saying that all relationships are dialectical.
Marx admitted no absolute division between nature and society, and hence no fundamental
methodological distinction between the natural sciences and historical science. As he
wrote in the German Ideology: "We know only a single science, the science of
history. History can be contemplated from two sides, it can be divided into the history of
nature and the history of mankind. However the two sides are not to be divided off; as
long as men exist the history of nature and the history of men are mutually
conditioned." An "opposition between nature and history" is created by the
ideologists in that they exclude from history the productive relation of men to nature.
Of course, external nature exists, but all attempts to know it - to qualify or quantify
it in any way - are inescapably mediated through human consciousness, and consciousness is
a sociopolitical and ideological mediator. The nature of consciousness is inconsistent
with any positivist view of coming to know external nature. Things exist independent of
humans, but, as the Sophists said, "Man [i.e., human praxis] is the measure of
all things." An exclusively contemplative relationship to nature or to humanity is
out of the question except as a result of the praxis of those whose interests are served
by such a posture. It is in our practical behavior - encountering, suffering, struggling,
laboring, and cooperating - that we come to know ourselves, one another, and things.
Schmidt writes,
Marx's polemic against Feuerbach in the German Ideology is an absolutely classic
demonstration of the point that the natural sciences, a main source of materialist
assertions, provided no immediate consciousness of natural reality at all, because man's
relation to reality is not primarily theoretical but practical and modificatory. In their
field of vision, their methodology, even in the content of what they regard as matter, the
natural sciences are socially determined.
242
Marx said, "Here, as everywhere, the identity of nature and man appears in such a
way that the restricted relation of men to nature determines their restricted relation to
one another, and nature, just because nature is as yet hardly modified historically . .
." Goldmann connects humanity and nature via science: "Human thought in general,
and therefore scientific thought, which is a particular aspect of it, are closely related
to human conduct and to the effects man has on the surrounding world." If we are to
continue to attempt to employ the base-superstructure distinction in any form, and, a
fortiori, if we are to move beyond it, our perception of the base must be
enriched so as to include an epistemology of labor and struggle, not a passive,
contemplative attitude toward nature and humanity or indeed toward the study of their
history.
From Marx and the framework he provides, we can move on to Lukács, whose analysis of
reification provides tools for looking more closely at the ways in which science has been
used for the purpose of reconciling people to the status quo. In History and Class
Consciousness he developed with great care and subtlety the ways in which the
categories of science were applied to economic and social relations in ways which led to
fatalism. One of the major themes in the book is that nature is a social category. Most of
his analysis is devoted to the ways in which society is objectified. For example,
What is important is to recognise clearly that all human relations (viewed as the
objects of social activity) assume increasingly the objective forms of the abstract
elements of the conceptual systems of natural science and of the abstract substrata of the
laws of nature.
The view that things as they appear can be accounted for by "natural laws" of
society is, according to Marx, both the highpoint and the "insuperable barrier"
of bourgeois thought.
Although the majority of his examples are drawn from the ways in which classical
economics employed the model of natural science in the process of reification, Lukács'
argument can be extended from economic and social laws to the scientific - especially the
biological - laws on which these extrapolations are based. At one point he appears to
provide a general warrant for extending ideological analysis from scientized (or reified)
social relations to science itself.
243
Nature is a societal category. That is to say, whatever is held to be natural at any
given stage of social development, however this nature is related to man and whatever form
his involvement with it takes, i.e., nature's form, its content, its range and its
objectivity are all socially conditioned.
But Lukács does not himself extend the analysis to nature itself in History and
Class Consciousness and indeed Gramsci complained of this:
It seems that Lukács asserts that one can only speak of the dialectic for the history
of man but not for nature. He may be right and he may be wrong. If his assertion
presupposes a dualism between nature and man he is wrong, because he falls into a view of
nature proper to religion and Greco-Christian philosophy and also into idealism, which in
reality does not manage to unite men and nature and relate them together other than
verbally. But if human history should be conceived also as the history of nature (also
through the history of science), how can the dialectic be separated from nature?
This fundamental issue has remained unresolved in Marxist thought. On the one hand, one
of the bases of Marxism is the reaction against converting people into things, leading
Marxists to posit a distinction between their dialectical view of humanity-and-nature and
a reductive, positivist conception of nature, while on the other hand, dualist ontologies
are anathema both because of their reconciling role in the history of thought and because
they lead to various forms of idealism. The only alternative to dualism would seem to be
to treat science and nature in an anthropological perspective, thereby fully extending
ideological analysis to the history of science and its metaphysical assumptions. Aspects
of this critique can be developed by combining the analyses of A. N. Whitehead and E. A.
Burtt with ones which have been influenced by Lukács, especially that of Herbert Marcuse
in One Dimensional Man.
The conception of "an anthropological perspective" might easily be
misleading, since much current anthropology is based on the very mystifying functionalist
conception which one is attempting to transcend. Thus, the term
"anthropological" must be defined with care. I am using it to refer to two sorts
of writing. First, that of the early Marx, who was unequivocally approaching
244
nature and society in terms of human values. I agree with those who argue that there is
no "epistemological break" between these and his later work. The writings of
Lukács, Goldmann, Mészáros, and Ollman fall clearly within this approach to Marx, while
those of Avineri, Schmidt, and Lefebvre are helpful.
The second sense in which I am using the term "anthropological" is to refer
to the approaches of two social anthropologists whose work seems to me to be adaptable for
our purposes in developing a richer theory of mediation, one which may lead ultimately to
a totalizing perspective. The first is Robin Horton, whose anthropological study of the
affinities between African traditional thought and Western science helps us to see the
relativity of ways of "ordering the world." He does this without considering
that the various ways of doing this are greater or lesser approximations to the
indubitably "objective" way of Western science. The comparative method which he
employs can be seen as the social scientists' version of the experimental method in
science. But the worries which his ideas have caused among British philosophers would seem
to imply that his challenge is promising. Horton does not appear to be developing this
line of inquiry further into the analysis of Western concepts of science and rationality.
This is unfortunate, but the issues are being pursued with considerable subtlety and depth
by Mary Douglas. Beginning with her study of pollution and taboo in Purity and Danger she
has, with increasing boldness and imagination, applied the approach of the anthropologist
to the economic, technological, and scientific cosmologies of her own culture. Professor
Douglas is more interested in the texture of the mediation of social arrangements in the
conventions of society than she is in questions about power or about what these highly
ordered conventions are mediations of. Even so, her analyses are excellent models
for our own efforts, and she has suggested - however little she may wish to set in train
politically radical thinking - ways of freeing ideological analysis from the restrictions
which have kept it away from the domain of natural science. Her essay "Environments
at Risk" and her inaugural lecture, "In the Nature of Things," offer
important encouragement and guidance for explicitly political investigations of scientific
cosmologies. It may be that Horton and Douglas were only - by analogy - extending the
relativism of social anthropology to our
245
own society, but they have provided significant tools for a radical analysis of
science.
I can point out one other writer whose work promises to play an important part
in the development of a radical critique of science and its history: Alfred Sohn Rethel.
He has taken on the daunting task of relating the problem of the origins and role of
abstract - particularly scientific - thought to the basic problem of the separation
between mental and manual labor, i.e., to one of the fundamental bulwarks of hierarchical,
antidemocratic societies. He has also integrated this analysis with a critique of the
ideology of science as applied in industrial processes. These analyses are contained in a
book and a number of papers which are not widely known in Britain and America and which
are almost completely unknown to historians of science.
Any impression which may be forming that a long analysis is by now degenerating into a
reading list would be accurate. In formulating a radical historiography of science there
is much of existing and earlier approaches to be overcome and little, as yet, is available
which has been sufficiently worked out as a new approach. But it should not be thought
that this is a bad position for a Marxist to find himself in:
The materialist doctrine that men are the products of circumstances and upbringing, and
that, therefore, changed men are products of other circumstances and changed upbringing,
forgets that it is men that change circumstances and that the educator himself needs
educating.
VIII
I have tried to suggest that we set aside the internalist-externalist dichotomy in the
historiography of science and that we consider going beyond the Marxist
base-superstructure model to a far richer and more subtle theory of mediations, moving
toward a theory of totality. The base-superstructure distinction is overlaid with decades
of vulgarization, and it should ultimately be superseded after its strengths and
weaknesses have been better understood by students of science and its history. For by then
it will have served its purpose as a bridge between the crude polarity of "idealism
versus materialism," and a genuinely totalizing,
246
relational theory of persons, nature, and society. I am not yet able to gain a clear
picture of what that would mean.
In attempting to take a more radical approach to the nineteenth-century debate on man's
place in nature, however, it is also abundantly clear that the scientific and ideological
perspectives should be held in constant tension and that in considering man, God, nature,
and society, no one of these topics should be considered except in its relations with the
other three. Relativism and contextualism are useful as first approximations, but they are
ultimately useless to socialists unless they are subsumed under a strong ideological
approach. In the nineteenth-century the boundaries between humanity and nature were in
dispute. On the whole, nature won, which means that reification won. It is still winning,
but some radicals are trying to push back the boundaries of reifying scientism as far as
they can, and a critical study of the development of the models which underlie reifying
rationalizations may be of service to them as they begin to place science in history - the
history of peoples and events.
POSTSCRIPT
I would like to think that this book is timely, not only for Darwin scholarship but for
the fruits of Darwinism for our own time, that is, for nature's place in
late-twentieth-century culture. When I first began to study these matters a quarter
century ago, it was prudent to refrain from making too many connections, particularly
across disciplines. I came to Darwin scholarship at a time when scholars were first
raising their eyes from a hagiography of the facts and the great discoveries of great men,
to vast sweeps of ideas. However, in so doing they missed out everything in between. The
research in this book traces a trajectory which came to include society, politics, and
ideology. A study of mind and brain led by a series of expanding contexts within the
history of ideas to the debate on man's place in nature which, in turn, led to Malthus and
to Darwin's metaphor. These, in turn, and in the context of the ferment of the late 1960s
and early 1970s, led to a recontexturalization and reconceptualization of the issues - to
nature's place in Victorian culture (hence my subtitle) and in ours. The place of nature -
of science as such, as practice, as ideology - needs critical
247
reassessment. Science is too often and too uncritically seen as fundamentally
progressive; it needs to be viewed in the context of our lives and of contending class
forces.
Science is not born of Platonic forms, living in a pure realm of ideas. The current
context for reflecting on these matters is a period in which biotechnology is harvesting
and commercializing the long-term fruits of Darwinism and making commodities out of the
least elements of living nature - amino acids and genes. The practitioners of
science and the students of its history, philosophy, and social relations should recall
the fate of its first advocate. Adam and Eve were innocent until tempted to hubris, to
knowledge, wisdom and good and evil. As punishment, their tempter was accursed.
The Lord God said unto the serpent, because thou hast done this, thou art accursed
above all cattle, and above every beast of the field; upon thy belly shalt thy go, and
dust shalt thy eat all the days of thy life. (Genesis 3: 14)
If science is to take its place in the making of a better world, it is best to know
that the problem of science in society begins with the Fall, with the serpent, and with
Cain in the Land of Nod. After many begats they have remained together in Icarus,
Sisyphus, Prometheus, Faustus, Urizen, Frankenstein, Jekyll, Moreau, and Oppenheimer's
Krishna -"I am become death, the shatterer of worlds". And Oedipus - Oedipus in
all knowing - a mutant, congenitally abnormal, abandoned, surviving, limping, avoiding,
questing, challenging, solving, taking, ruling, polluting, suffering, learning, doing
penance; blind, then looking inward and seeing.
Once again, today we have molecular biology, biotechnology, and genetic engineering.
Natural selection is still scrutinizing, but the scientist and his mentors and employers
are directly selecting, controlling, and selling natural selection. This is the greatest
power and responsibility humanity has ever had or could have - to shape and control life
and its fruits and the meaning of humanity itself. Who shall scrutinize and control
the forces at work on this cultural, socioeconomic, and scientific process? When will we
look deeply enough to see that science embodies values in theories, therapies, and things,
and that that embodiment must always be looked after, outwardly and inwardly?
|
|