THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF
SCIENCE
by Robert M. Young
In the second of our series on science and ideology Robert
Young discusses the relations between science and personal, social and political
values. There are two aspects to this problem; philosophical and ideological. Dr
Young suggests a framework of thinking which may overcome the prevailing
fragmentation of debate.It is worth recalling at the outset that this debate is
occurring in a new atmosphere. In the course of the nineteenth century, the
development of science and technology became synonymous with belief in unlimited
material and social progress. It is only in the course of the last generation
that we have become critical about the meaning of progress and fully ambivalent
about the role of science and technology. For example, in the space of my
lifetime (thirty-six years) the whole range of antibiotics and of effective
insecticides have been discovered, leading to control of bacterial infections
and of malaria. But in the same period we have seen the development of virulent
bacteria which are resistant to antibiotics and their spread has led to the
closing of hospitals. Similarly, the worldwide use of DDT has virtually wiped
out malaria, dramatically cutting the death toll from that disease, but leading
to increased population, malnutrition and starvation in the Third
World. We have
come a long way since the 1930s, when people of all political persuasions were
united in the belief that science was a progressive force, that what was needed
was more and more of it, and that the problems of man and society would also
yield to the application of the magical methods of science.The question is not merely that of the specific uses and
abuses of science and technology. The debate is much wider. On one side it is
being argued that we have entered a new age — the cybernetic one — in which
advanced industrial countries can, for the first time, implement the dreams of
abundance and egalitarian democracy which science has always promised, and the
same hope is held out for the distant future of the Third World. On the other
side, many of the members of the New Left and the counter-culture of young
people argue that science and technology have robbed people of their dignity and
have created a society devoted to the acquisition of goods and gadgets in place
of human relationships. People have become objects in the scientific-industrial
complex; their role is to produce goods which they then devote their earnings to
purchasing. Many of the anti-rational aspects of youth culture — dropping out,
the appeal of mysticism and drugs, the return to simple communal life on the
land — can be seen as forms of protest against the alienation of the person from
his or own labour, from its products and from fellow humans. This protest is
against science and technology as governing the relations of production at work
and our social relations. Our lives are dominated by technological rationality.
'Things' and the organization of industry to produce them have made human
relations thing-like: they have become reified. So, in addition to our concern over the uses and abuses of
science, there is a much wider issue about the role of science in society and
culture. The particular problems make direct contact with general debates on
politics and the philosophy of civilization and the hopes and fears raised in
analysis of advanced technocratic societies, both East and West. Radicals argue
that science and technology are the key to the elitist forms of social
organization in which the division of labour produces hierarchies in which the
experts are in alliance with the owners of the means of production. And
government — with its advisers and experts — mirrors the anti-democratic
structures based on science. In this situation, it is not surprising that on one
side the radicals try to opt out or become wreckers or Luddites, while on the
other politicians and scientists defend their methods and their integrity. These are some of the issues raised by science and technology
in the social and political arenas. Now I want to go to another extreme to some
very basic philosophical problems about science. It may sound at first as though
I am changing the subject, but the key point in my argument is that I am not.
The lesson which I draw from what I have said so far is that the growing number
of scientists who are concerned about the social and political context of their
work will have to act as political persons if they are really serious about
having any impact on these issues. But as they do so, we find them behaving in
one of two ways. They either take off their scientists' lab coats and enter the
political arena purely as laypersons, or they attempt to bring their scientific
roles and prestige with them and to address themselves to social and political
problems as scientists. The public has two main reactions to scientists
who enter their arena. In some cases, when scientists speak on social and
political issues, the press and public — and especially the politicians — remark
on their naiveté and their utopianism in believing that the neat
categories of the laboratory and the ivory tower can be transferred to the murky
world of politics. They are gently led back to their havens and warned not to
meddle. The other reaction of the public is to defer to the
scientist, rather as they used to do to the clergy, and latterly to pop stars,
but the fantasies we attach to the scientists have an extra strength: they are
'experts' in 'rationality'. The media regularly consult these experts who
pronounce in scientific terms on the political and social problems of the day.
The tele-psychiatrist has been joined by tele-biologist, physicist, sociologist,
ethologist, psychologist, and even the tele-psephologist. An extreme version of
this sort of deference toward scientists was the recent call by Lord Ritchie
Calder for the United Nations to bring together a panel of 'wise men' from all
over the world, to sort out the moral and ethical problems raised by science,
technology and medicine. In the same vein, a host of books has appeared in
recent years in which ethologists, geneticists, anthropologists, and
psychologists make extrapolations on the basis of science, which purport to tell
us what is possible in social and political life, in education, race relations,
city life, foreign relations, war, and so on. I am advocating a healthy
scepticism about such claims. Now I would like to return to what I said was the key point
in my argument. I believe that the conflicting reactions of both scientists and
the public on the problems of relating science and values rest, in the first
instance, on a set of distinctions which are at the heart of the methods and
assumptions of modern science. They are also at the heart of modern social and
political theory. Since Descartes’ Discourse on Method and Locke's Essay on The Human Understanding, philosophical and social theory has
defined rationality on the basis of models drawn from science. There are certain
fundamental assumptions which are so basic to our whole way of thinking about
humanity and nature that they set limits to the available ways of conceiving of
the relationship between science, on the one hand, and social and political
issues on the other. I want to argue that until we scrutinize these assumptions,
the problems have no hope of solution. Indeed, they cannot even be coherently
formulated. The distinctions which I want to scrutinize have permeated
everything I have said so far. That is, we automatically separate science
both from values and from social and political issues. Every schoolchild knows
that facts are one thing and theories another, that facts and theories are
separate from values, that the psychological and social origins of a theory must
be distinguished from its validity, that science is one thing and its use or
abuse in technology quite another. These distinctions provide the basis for our
belief that the methods and assumptions of science can produce objective truth
which is value-neutral. So we are led into making demarcations between the origins, the substance and the role of scientific findings.
These distinctions were the main achievement of the
fundamental philosophical and methodological shift which occurred in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in what is known as the Scientific
Revolution. This period produced a new definition of what would qualify
as an explanation in science. Explanations in terms of uses and values were
banished and replaced by explanations in terms of the fundamental categories of
matter, motion and number. No one was to be prevented from asking questions of
nature in terms which included subjective, or value laden concepts, but he could
not call the answer scientific unless it was expressed solely in terms of
physical processes.
Advancing Objectivity
Beginning in astronomy and moving on to physics and
chemistry, the widely accepted account of the history of science is one of the
advancing edge of objectivity into ever-widening domains. In the nineteenth
century, it embraced the history of the earth and then the history of life in
evolutionary theory and went on to embrace psychology and the social sciences.
The fusion of biology and psychology in research in genetics and molecular
biology is now being applied to the problems of memory and learning in the
nervous system, while biochemists are seeking to provide chemical explanations
of normal and pathological behaviour. The trouble with this picture of the advancing age of
objectivity is that it is becoming increasingly undermined by research in the
history of philosophy of science and in some branches of the human sciences. The
closer historians of science look at the great achievements of science, the more
difficulty they find in distinguishing science from pseudoscience and from the
political, economic and ideological contexts. Scientists' philosophical views
about nature, humanity and society appear to play a very important part in
formulations of the substance of major scientific ideas. The official
distinctions between context, substance and applications simply cannot be
maintained. Historians of science are, therefore, beginning to employ the
interpretive approaches of historians of art and literature and are also finding
that their investigations have much in common with those of anthropologists.
Similarly, as philosophers of science scrutinize the concept of ' fact ' more
closely, they conclude that facts are irreducibly theory-laden. And their
studies are conducted in the supposedly safest domains of physics and chemistry.
Finally, psychologists are adding their voices to this breakdown of the official
story and they are concluding that perception is itself a process which cannot
be separated from expectations and evaluations. The common theme in these
studies is that science is much more like the messy world of social and
political intercourse than working scientists care to believe, or are willing to
concede. These investigations have not, on the whole, been carried out
according to conscious political approaches, but they fit in very neatly with
arguments coming from the New Left in critiques of politics, and from the human
sciences. The concepts which link these disciplines with the natural sciences
are being turned around. Instead of arguing that biology is a complex version of
physics and chemistry, people are approaching the problem from the opposite
perspective. It is being pointed out that evaluative concepts from political and
social philosophy penetrate deeply into the human and biological sciences. Attempts to make the study of humanity scientific have
started out with biological terms — 'structure' and 'function’, 'adaptive' and
'maladaptive'. They have linked these with medical ones — 'normal' and
'pathological' — and they have gone on to the social, such as 'adjusted' and
'deviant'. You can tell the story in one of two ways, and people will
disagree about whether the choice of how you tell it is itself a scientific or a
political one. Let's look at some of the pairs of concepts used in the human
sciences and consider their relations with the natural sciences. Social scientists study and write about conformist vs. non-conformist behaviour — about people who are obedient or rebellious, adjusted
or deviant. Are these just conventional categories involving praise or blame? Or
can we link them to science by making them analogous to normal vs. pathological behaviour, as treated by a psychiatrist?
These psychiatric terms
are extensions of the medical concepts of normal = healthy, and pathological =
diseased. And medical concepts in turn are based on the supposed objective
biological ideas of adaptive vs. maladaptive structures and functions.
Thus, psychological, social and political categories can be seen as extensions
of scientific ones. The rebellions of youth are, for example, not adapted to the
social organism, and are said to need treatment. The part of San Quentin prison
from which the black activist George Jackson was trying escape when shot was
called the adjustment centre. Or — as radicals and even some
conservatives are doing — you can tell that story the other way round and argue
that biological categories are inescapably value-laden and that the analogies
which are made to psychological, social and political phenomena show that
evaluative concepts penetrate deeply into the categories of science. Concepts
like adaptive, maladaptive, survival and fittest are — it's
obvious as soon as you say it — evaluative concepts, not purely objective
ones. At first glance these analogies are merely extensions of that
advancing edge of objectivity. Beginning in the nineteenth century, important
findings and theories linked biology with the physico-chemical sciences in the
study of organs, tissues and cells. This led to a greater understanding of
physiological processes, and to the development of genetics and molecular
biology. At a more general level, the theory of evolution implied that ’man and
all his works’ were, at least in principle, the products of natural
processes and could, therefore, be analyzed objectively. Students of humanity
and society turned away from theology to biological — especially evolutionary —
ideas in order to place their own disciplines on a firm scientific foundation
and thereby reduce the understanding of personal, social and political phenomena
to natural categories. As a result, a whole family of concepts was developed
which has collectively been called 'functionalism'. They have the common
characteristic that explanations were made in terms of biological analogies,
like those I've just mentioned. There have always been protests against this movement, and
especially against those who argued that ethical judgments could be based on
scientific findings. For example, T. H. Huxley opposed this reduction in his
lecture on 'Evolution and Ethics' in 1893, and philosophers such as G. E. Moore continued to do so in their arguments against what came to be known as the
'naturalistic fallacy'. They pointed out that science and evolutionary theory
could provide no guidance for how people should live. These liberal
protests against reducing ethics and politics to science have some things in
common with radical and revolutionary views. Karl Marx was vehement in his
protest against the reduction of the human to non-human. This is what Marxists
mean by reification. In fact, the whole Marxist tradition can be described as
one long battle against the economists and others who have tried to claim that
existing social relations are based on the laws of positivist science.
Functionalist tradition
In spite of this, the functionalist tradition continued to
develop in the works of psychologists and social scientists, especially in
Britain and America. It has recently come under fire in the wake of severe
criticisms of the status quo in the fight for civil rights, the student
movement, protests against the Vietnam war, and the political critique of
advanced technocratic societies. The writings of the German-American
philosopher, Herbert Marcuse, and the activities of, for example, the German
student leader, Rudi Dutschke, have been based on this analysis. Functional
theory equated the concept of normal with the prevailing norms of behaviour, and
people's deeply-held social and political views were described as abnormal or
deviant. Their convictions were dismissed as symptoms of psychopathology. As the differences between young and old, left and right,
critics and apologists, became more and more acute, the role of the accepted
concepts was thrown into sharp relief. The conventional categories were
criticized for playing an important part in justifications of oppression,
exploitation, capitalism and imperialism. Having become suspicious about these
rationalizations of the status quo, radicals began to ask how far they
penetrated into the domain of science itself. The sharp distinctions between the
socio-political role of science and its supposedly objective substance was thus
brought into question from an explicitly political point of view, and it was
argued that the distinction served to mystify people and lead them to accept the
prevailing social order as natural and therefore inescapable, if not desirable.
Before moving on to another level of analysis, I want to
summarize this part of the argument. I began by saying that the problem of
relating science and values rests, in the first instance, on a set of
distinctions which are at the heart of the assumptions of modern science. In
tracing a continuum of disciplines extending from general biology and
physiology, through psychology, sociology and anthropology and embracing such
areas as economics and town planning, which use the same or analogous concepts,
I have tried to show how these concepts are now being argued to be evaluative
and, in many cases, political. The distinctions between fact and value, between
the substance and the role of scientific statements, are very debatable. Notice
that I have not said that there are no facts. Rather, I have said that
philosophers, historians, psychologists, and radicals have found it difficult to
separate facts from theories, theories from values, and values from covert or
overt social and political beliefs. I believe that we ought to take these developments seriously,
both as scientists and as people. Instead of seeing biology and the human
sciences as falling short of the purity of physics and chemistry, we should see
them as the norm and the so-called pure sciences as relatively unattainable
extremes.
Physics and biology
But I can just hear — as you may, in the course of this
series — a physicist saying, 'But physics isn't biased, and I'm not biased.' He
would be joined by chemists and molecular biologists in claiming vehemently that
although the applications of their theories may be part of the domain of values
and politics, the substance of their sciences is objective, that is,
value-neutral. I think that their case is a strong one at this level of
analysis, but not if we look deeper. However, in order to raise the relevant
issues I have to introduce an approach to the problem which I have carefully
avoided making explicit so far. I have done this because its basis is strange
and unpalatable to many, and I wanted to show how far we could get before
appealing to a more profound wrench to our scientific assumptions. I think that there is a fairly large group of people who
would accept that there is a continuum of disciplines which are more or less
impregnated with value-laden and political concepts. Ten years ago, people were
arguing about the natural sciences as the model for the behavioural sciences.
Now they are talking about a critical approach to the human sciences.
They would grant that not only the role and the substance are so influenced, but
would also add that the origins of the ideas are importantly related both to
their substance and to the beliefs of certain interest groups in society. The
study of the relations among the social origins, the substance and the role of
ideas, is known as the ' sociology of knowledge'. The legitimate domain of the
sociology of knowledge is normally sharply demarcated from mathematics and from
parts of the natural sciences. I have already suggested that it is no longer as
easy as was once thought to decide where to draw that line of demarcation. There
may be a distinction between value-laden and value-free science, but it is not a
lot of use to people who want to ferret out bias and be purely 'objective', if
we don't know where to make the separation between them. If I am right in suggesting that we are in the realm of
values and politics wherever functional concepts are used, I cannot see where we
can draw the line in biology. The role of such concepts may come somewhere near
the will-o-the-wisp of value-neutrality, but since one cannot draw the line with
any certainty, it seems best to approach the findings and theories of biologists
with a very critical and politically self-conscious eye. If we do this, we are
left only with the sceptical physicist. It seems to me that the only way to
shake his complacency is to suggest a research programme which extends beyond
the sociology of knowledge into one of its parent traditions, that is, to
Marxist views of nature. But, in addition, he ought to couple these with some of
the recent anthropological speculations of Professor Mary Douglas. The Marxist
and anthropological approaches come from opposite ends of the political
spectrum, but they are united in suggesting that all thought including
all scientific thought, is in large measure a function of the concepts of human
nature and society. This is equally true of the definition of a scientific
explanation as developed in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries and of the
views of nature of so-called 'primitive' tribes and, indeed, it is true of the
debates about pollution and the environment going on in so-called advanced
societies. People's philosophies of science are a function of their philosophies
of nature, and their philosophies of nature are, in turn, a function of their
fundamental beliefs about man and society. If the sceptical physicist is to transcend his complacency,
he will have to dig very deeply into the nature of modern society to find the
ideological roots of his assumptions about nature and science. Obviously, if
he's relatively content with the way things are in society, he probably would
not feel that this is a dig worth making. In order to decline the invitation, he
need not be dishonest or biased in any self-conscious sense. On the contrary, he
need only be normal. The phrase 'the way things are' is a useful pun in this
context, suggesting acceptance of deeply-held views about science and about
society. Some of us want to change the way things are, and I am
suggesting that in order to get much further toward this goal, science must be
demystified. One partial way of doing this is for scientists to become overtly
political. We must at the same time become philosophical and consider the
metaphysical assumptions of modern science, especially the fact/value
distinction. The next step — the hardest one — is to relate these metaphysical
beliefs to their ideological context. Instead of particularizing the concept of
ideology, calling it distortion and attempting to absorb ideology into science,
we might attempt to view science in the context of people’s ideological beliefs.
Instead of the physicist saying 'I'm not biased', he might be helped to see the
ways in which modern science reflects the social and economic order of modern
society in very complex and subtle ways. The difficulties involved in doing this
are immense, but the consequences of making the attempt are essential to any
hope of creating a democratic society. If we can manage to learn to think in these new ways, we will
begin to see that the problem is fundamentally anthropological, not in the sense
of structural and functional anthropological theory, but in the sense of
knowledge of human nature and society as the most basic knowledge that we
require. My contention is that this knowledge is the foundation on which our
approach to nature depends. More than this, the stones from which we build these
foundations are ultimately chosen from deep convictions about how we should
treat each other and about what social order is compatible with different
beliefs about these values. Facts and values are inextricably intermingled
throughout thought and life, but in the beginning was the value. If this
approach is convincing to morally concerned persons, political discourse can't
be reduced to science any more than ethical discourse can. Indeed, moral and
political discourse may well be more fundamental than scientific discourse. And
our views about science may well be expressions of our social and political
beliefs. Science is, therefore, no escape from the conflicting ideologies in the
world, but is a mediation of them. The Marxist critic and philosopher, Georg
Lukács, put the fundamental point very clearly when he said, ' Nature is a
societal category. That is to say, whatever is held to be natural at any given
stage of social development, however this nature is related to man and whatever
form his involvement with it takes — i.e., nature's form, its content — its
range and its objectivity are all socially conditioned.' What are we to call this approach? There are several possible
ways of labelling it. Many would call it 'the new sophism' (and we could all
look again at the wisdom of the Sophists), but we could just as well call it
'the anthropology of nature', 'social metaphysics', or 'the ideology of nature'.
Whatever we call this framework for enquiry, our understanding of these issues
will be fragmented and mystified until we begin to see nature and society in a
coherent, totalized framework. If we attempt to do this, without at the same
time striving to transform the basic structure of society, we will only lead
ourselves into further mystification. This is the text of a talk in a BBC Radio Third Programme
series on ‘Science and Ideology’. It was reprinted in New Humanist 88
(no. 3), July 1972, pp. 102-105.Copyright: The AuthorAddress for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Rd., London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
4337 words