THE MIND-BODY PROBLEMby Robert M. Young
There have been, throughout recorded history, representations of a
separation between the corporeal and the spiritual in religion, philosophy,
folklore and myth. On the whole, the incorporeal realm has been seen as more enduring,
efficacious and valued than the corporeal, which is often described as transient of little
value and even illusory.However, this is not to say that the 'mind-body problem' of modern
Western thought has a history stretching back through the mists of time. Indeed, for more
than a thousand years prior to the seventeenth century, the reigning mode of explanation
sorted out reality and causality along quite different lines or, rather, without the sort
of lines associated with a sharp dichotomy between the mental and the physical. Nor were
there sharp distinctions between ideas of causality, of what is ultimately real (ontology)
and of how we can know with certainty (epistemology). All lay within an integrated
Aristotelian (we should now say organismic) framework of causes or 'comings to be': the
material cause (that out of which, or roughly, our concept of matter); the efficient cause
(the source of energy: that which produces or imparts motion or shapes); the formal cause
(that which gives form or plan in the sense of an architect's or craftsman's plan) and the
final cause (the purpose or goal or that for which). All 'comings to be' things,
events, processes were seen as constituted by all four causes, which could only be
separately considered analytically. Debates about philosophy in the Renaissance were
putting this framework under strain, so that the material and efficient causes were
drifting towards one pole and the formal and final ones towards another. However, it would
be anachronistic to treat these imputed poles as recognised extremes in a mind-body
dichotomy. Other notions, such as that of 'substantial form' or ones invoking
pre-Aristotelian, i.e., atomic, concepts also put the form/matter dichotomy under strain.
If we cease to look at the pre-modern formulations and ask when the mind-body problem
became conceptualised in the ways which we can recognise as more or less our own, the
answer lies in the philosophical writings of René Descartes (1596-1650) and in his place
in the so-called 'Scientific Revolution' of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. I say
so-called, because it would be a huge historical oversimplification to trace a single
thread from his Discourse on Method (1637) or Meditations (1641) to the
present. History is always messy, and intellectual history is no exception to this rule.
In the case of the mind-body problem, this means that Aristotelian thinking never died and
was perpetuated, for example, in the study of living phenomena ('biology' is a
nineteenth-century term). Similarly, Platonic ideas of the universality of ideal forms
linked to geometrical and numerical properties continued, as did mystical and alchemical
notions which were intermixed with the persistence of Aristotelian and Platonic notions.
These admixtures persisted in the work of the leading figures of the Scientific
Revolution, for example, Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo and Newton. Moreover, materialist and
atomist philosophies were being advocated, some of them drawn from classical sources, in
the writings of Hobbes and Gassendi. Even so, it is in the writings of Descartes that we find the full-blown
paradox of the mind-body dichotomy. His method of radical doubt led to a single certainty:
'I think, therefore I am' a theory of knowledge based on subjectivity linked to a
theory of ultimate reality based on 'thinking substances' as one class of existence. Mind
was being put forward as a self-contained sphere of enquiry.[1]This pole of the dualism was linked to an equally strongly-held belief
that causality in the material world is based on matter in motion, 'extended substances',
obeying their own material laws. Introspection became the basis of certainty, while
scientific knowledge of the external world depended on the laws of matter and motion. These two bases for knowing opened up two closely-linked chasms in
modern thought: the ontological (between mind and body) and the epistemological (between
subject and object). Matter came to be defined in ways that made it amenable to treatment
in mathematical terms and to the experimental method, leading to the notion that
scientific explanation must be in terms of bodies: extension and shape, treated
mathematically. Although misunderstanding William Harvey's theory of the circulation of
the blood, Descartes utilised it as the key to the comprehension of all of the rest of
nature. This was merely the motion of material substances without a vital spirit or
special causes but simply heat and the motions of the parts. The question of how much this
left unexplained within the study of living nature will be discussed further on. However,
even on its own terms, the formulation of a reality consisting of extended substances and
non-extended substances was fraught with difficulty. The non-extended substances were
defined negatively as partaking of all the attributes that do not apply to body (i.e.,
which cannot be treated mathematically and experimentally). The essence of this was, of
course, free will. We see in the philosophy of Descartes a grand historic compromise in
which the claims of scientific explanation produced a definition of matter, while the
claims of the church and moral responsibility produced a definition of mind. Yet those two
were imcompatible. How do body and mind interrelate in life and in knowing? This puzzle
led to the classical 'problem of interaction', a perennial philosophical conundrum which
still gets dismissed generation after generation until one thinks eventually of
unanswerable questions such as how thoughts can cause actions or how unconscious fantasies
can cause psychosomatic illnesses such as ulcers, asthma and colitis. How do thoughts
impact on particles of matter and how do material impacts cause thoughts, including the
thoughts which lead from sensation to knowing? We are left wondering not only how we know
anything for certain but how we have any experience at all, especially the experience of
other minds. How can two sorts of basic substances which are defined so that
they have nothing in common then have causal relationships in the 'having' of experience
and the 'willing' of action? If the scandalised tone of these questions seems eccentric, here are
the opinions of two eminent philosophers, Whitehead and Burtt, reflecting on the mind-body
problem and the closely-linked problem of knowledge.
The seventeenth century had finally produced a scheme of scientific
thought framed by mathematicians, for the use of mathematicians. The great characteristic
of the mathematical mind is its capacity for dealing with abstractions; and for eliciting
from them clear-cut demonstrative trains of reasoning, entirely satisfactory so long as it
is those abstractions which you want to think about. The enormous success of the
scientific abstractions, yielding on the one hand matter with its simple
location in space and time, on the other hand mind, perceiving, suffering,
reasoning, but not interfering, has foisted onto philosophy the task of accepting them as
the most concrete rendering of fact.
Thereby, modern philosophy has been ruined. It has oscillated in a
complex manner between three extremes. There are the dualists, who accept matter and mind
as on equal basis, and the two varieties of monists, those who put mind inside matter, and
those who put matter inside mind. But this juggling with abstractions can never overcome
the inherent confusion introduced by the ascription of misplaced concreteness to
the scientific scheme of the seventeenth century.[2]
E. A. Burtt spells out the consequences of the doctrine for human
self-knowledge.
...it does seem like strange perversity in these Newtonian scientists
to further their own conquests of external nature by loading on mind everything refractory
to exact mathematical handling and thus rendering the latter still more difficult to study
scientifically than it had been before. Did it never cross their minds that sooner or
later people would appear who craved verifiable knowledge about mind in the same way they
craved it about physical events, and who might reasonably curse their elder scientific
brethren for buying easier success in their own enter enterprise by throwing extra
handicaps in the way of their successors in social science? Apparently not; mind was to
them a convenient receptacle for the refuse, the chips and whittlings of science, rather
than a possible object of scientific knowledge.[3]
Deep within the grand mind-body dichotomy lay the problem of parcelling
out the qualities to assign to the separate realms. When one embarks on this task, new
puzzles abound. The qualities which can be treated mathematically and which are thought
not to vary according to subjective bias are called primary. It is a short list, and items
keep falling off it. Extension and shape are the only enduring ones. Even hardness has a
difficult time keeping its place, and physical theories based on forces and fields compete
successfully with those based on atomic particles. But the realm of colour, odour and
taste the texture of experience gets relegated to the domain of secondary
qualities. These are seen as less real and are the effects of the vicissitudes of matter
in motion. Aspects of this concept of 'primary and secondary qualities' were developed in
the writings of Descartes, Galileo, Newton and Locke.Whitehead is eloquent in his critique of the features and the
consequences of the doctrine of primary and secondary qualities, a doctrine which lies at
the basis of modern thought just as securely as the parent mind-body dichotomy.
Locke, writing with a knowledge of Newtonian dynamics, places mass
among the primary qualities of bodies. In short, he elaborates a theory of primary and
secondary qualities in accordance with the state of physical science at the close of the
seventeenth century. The primary qualities are the essential qualities of substances whose
spatio-temporal relationships constitute nature. The orderliness of these relationships
constitutes the order of nature. The occurrences of nature are in some way apprehended by
minds, which are associated with living bodies. Primarily, the mental apprehension is
aroused by the occurrences in certain parts of the correlated body, the occurrences in the
brain, for instance. But the mind in apprehending also experiences sensations which,
properly speaking, are qualities of the mind alone. These sensations are projected by the
mind so as to clothe appropriate bodies in external nature. Thus the bodies are perceived
as with qualities which in reality do not belong to them, qualities which in fact are
purely the offspring of the mind. Thus nature gets credit which should in truth be
reserved for ourselves: the rose for its scent; the nightingale for his song; and the sun
for his radiance. The poets are entirely mistaken. They should address their lyrics to
themselves, and should turn them into odes of self-congratulation on the excellency of the
human mind. Nature is a dull affair, soundless, scentless, colourless merely the hurrying
of material, endlessly, meaninglessly. However you disguise it, this is the practical outcome of the
characteristic scientific philosophy which closed the seventeenth century. In the first place, we must note its astounding efficiency as a system
of concepts for the organisation of scientific research. In this respect, it is fully
worthy of the genius of the century which produced it. It has held its own as the guiding
principle of scientific studies ever since. It is still reigning. Every university in the
world organises itself in accordance with it. No alternative system of organising the
pursuit of scientific truth has been suggested. It is not only reigning, but it is without
rival.
And yet it is quite unbelievable. This conception of the
universe is surely framed in terms of high abstractions, and the paradox only arises
because we have mistaken our abstraction for concrete realities.[4]
What a mess! Yet is well and truly still our mess. If we look at
the goals of Newtonian explanation, we find him claiming that the whole business of
natural philosophy is that from the phenomena of matter and motion we are to explain all
the other phenomena. If we look at a modern textbook, we find roughly the same terms of
reference. In the Royal Society document on Qualities, Units and Symbols (1975), we
find the following on page 6:
The value of a physical quantity is equal to the product of a numerical
value and a unit. Neither any physical quantity nor the symbol used to denote
it should imply a particular choice of unit, operations on equations involving physical
quantities, units and numerical values, should follow the ordinary rules of algebra.
On page 8 it says,
Each physical quantity is given a name and a symbol which is an
abbreviation for that name. By international convention seven physical quantities
are chosen for use as dimensionally independent base quantities: length (l), mass (m),
time (t), electric current (i), thermodynamic temperature (T), amount of substance (n) and
luminous intensity (Iv). All other physical quantities are regarded as being derived from the base quantities.
This is the bedrock of all explanation, and on it we must, in
principle, erect all knowledge, all explanation. Every attempt to transcend the mind-body dichotomy and the problem of
interaction can be said to fall foul of some deep problem. As Whitehead said, there are
basically three positions: dualists, materialists and idealists. In fact, the
classification is somewhat more elaborate. Classical Cartesian dualism invokes God at the point of interaction.
For Descartes, the physical point of interaction where the miracle occurs countless times
each day was the pineal gland or conarium. Modern interactionists take it as
given that interaction between physical and mental events occurs, though they can in no
sense explain it in causal terms. One way of avoiding this scandal is to say that mental and physical
events occur in parallel, without calling for interaction or a doctrine of mind-body
causality. This approach was adopted by Malebranche (1638-1715), who invoked God to keep
the mental and the physical events in step. Secular versions of psychophysical
parallelism or the doctrine of concomitance have been widespread in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries. For example, they were held by the philosopher, psychologist and
evolutionary thinker, Herbert Spencer, by John Hughlings Jackson, the father of modern
neurology, who adopted it from Spencer, and by Freud, who applied Jackson's ideas in his
first book, On Aphasia (1891) and continued to hold this view until his last
writing, An Outline of Psychoanalysis (1940). A recent exponent of psychophysical parallelism in neurology and
philosophy is Hertwig Kuhlenbeck. The strength of the theory lies in its candour:
psychophysical parallelists simply shrug their shoulders at the problem of interaction
while making full use of the rich languages of mind and body. It can be argued that much
of modern philosophy is parallelist in that elaborate theories of mental causation
the association of ideas have been spelled out in the psychological writings of
Locke, Hume, Hartley, James Mill, John Stuart Mill, G. H. Lewes, Spencer and Alexander
Bain, among others, without, however, any denial of concomitant physiological mechanisms
or commitment to causal explanations. The mental elements have been persistently described
in ways which are closely analogous to concepts involving atoms and their interactions in
physics. For example, in David Hartley's Observations on Man (I749), ideas and
their associations paralleled postulated vibrations and 'vibratiuncles' in the brain.
Similarly, William James commented on the close parallelism between the concept of the
association of ideas and the neurone theory of the nervous system. From this it is, of course, but one step to say consistent with
the doctrine of primary and secondary qualities that the mental realm has no
autonomy or causal effficacy, and that mind is merely an effect or epiphenomenon of
physical and physiological processes. This is materialist monism or materialism, a
doctrine which has had its advocates since antiquity and was assiduously advocated by
Hobbes in the seventeenth century and by numerous philosophers in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries. Examples of this are the Helmholtz School of Physiology in
nineteenth-century France and Germany and behaviourism in twentieth-century American
psychology and British philosophy. There was a group of experimental physiologists in the
mid-nineteenth century including Helmholtz, Brücke and Dubois-Reymond who held that there
are no forces other than the ordinary physico-chemical ones operating in the organism,
although they left room for the positing of, and research on, other natural and measurable
forces. The doctrine of behaviourism was developed in America in the early
decades of the twentieth century. Its leading advocate was John B. Watson, who moved on
from saying that psychology should adopt experimental methods for the study of organisms
to saying that there are no minds, only observable behaviour. Thought became a sort of
implicit speech. Behaviourism was closely linked to objective and operationist movements
in physics and to astringent doctrines in philosophy which attempted to model
philosophical thinking on the natural sciences. This point of view was most eloquently put
in the analytical philosophy of Gilbert Ryle, whose The Concept of Mind (1949) was
influential in the I950s until the vein of psychological and philosophical behaviourism
was played out, and researchers in both disciplines began to look again at meaning and
subjectively in less restricted, though no less disciplined, terms. A persistent problem
with materialist monism from its ancient form to its modern-day advocates in physics,
physiology and molecular biology is that the concept of matter bequeathed to us by the
seventeenth century is simply too impoverished too stripped of the qualities of
lived experience for it to be credible that that matter can produce life and
mind. There is something unutterably bleak at the heart of the doctrine that there is only
matter; foolish, too, as the above passage from Whitehead shows. The classification I have given here is not exhaustive. For example, a
variant of materialism is identity theory, whereby the logically separate domains
of mental and physical are said to be based on an empirical identity: brain states. This
leaves the subject's observations of his or her mental events in an ontological limbo.
Other attempts to transcend the patent difficulties in the existing dualistic and monistic
theories have postulated a neutral monism or have interpreted mind and body as two aspects of a single underlying reality. Those who advocate identity theory, neutral monism or
aspect theory would, of course, argue that they have overcome the absurdities of
traditional 'solutions' to the mind-body problem. And yet the final choice that there is only mind is
equally or possibly even more incredible. There has perhaps never been a consistent
mentalist monist. Indeed, in Individuals (1959) P. F. Strawson went to some lengths
to show that connection to some body in the past or present is essential to the
identification of persons, things and other particulars. Perhaps Berkeley and some mystics
were genuine idealist monists. All of this leads one back to the drawing board. If interactionism,
parallelism, materialism and idealism won't do, a way has to be found to grant matter its
due, yet to give us back a recognisable world at the end of the day. In fact, real and
sensible philosophers and scientists have rarely held pure versions of the above doctrine.
In particular, they have persistently endowed matter with properties that go beyond the
extremely short list of the seventeenth-century purists. For example, as the debate
continued about what aspects of life, including human nature, could be described by the
mechanical philosophy, J. O. de la Mettrie (1709-51) argued that Man is a Machine (1747),
while enriching the concept of 'machine' enough to take the sting of despair out of his
title for those who read his treatise carefully. Similarly, Albrecht von Haller (1708-77)
argued that as long as we could do experiments, we could postulate whatever biological properties
we need, e.g., sensibility or contractility. If one looks at a modern biological or
physiological text, all sorts of properties are invoked without anyone (or practically
anyone) intending to invoke special, vital or purely unmaterialistic forces. Thus
'inherent rhythmicity', 'pacemakers', 'organisers', 'homeostasis' and 'positive and
negative feedback' are all concepts which span the realms of mechanism and purpose which
were so starkly split in Cartesian dualism. Therefore, biological properties in the study
of purposive mechanisms have broken through the strictest version of Cartesian dualism
with its impoverished concept of matter. Some have wished to elevate this transcendence of Cartesian dualism
into a new philosophy and to argue for a doctrine of emergence. When hydrogen and
oxygen combine to produce water, the property of wetness (absent in hydrogen and oxygen
separately) is called an 'emergent'. Similar claims are made for the emergent properties
of life and mind and, by some, spirit. This is an odd view. It is one thing to note what
matter can do and thereby enrich our concept of it. It is quite another to hypostatise
properties and give them a new ontological status and causal efficacy under the title of
'emergents'. It recalls Moliere's Tartuffe, who explains that opium works because it has a
'soporific virtue'. Another path by which the mind-body problem has been transcended is
much trodden by the emergentists. It is the theory of evolution. The key point of
evolution is its gradualism. At what point does mind appear? Animals evidently feel
(though this was hotly debated in the wake of Cartesianism). Do they then think? Do they
have a true language? Are they responsible? What, if any, are their rights? Do plants have
the same rights as slugs, and do cats, dolphins and whales have the same rights as humans?
Are less clever animals as responsible as bright ones? It could be argued that it depends
on how much 'mind' a given creature has. Alternatively, it could be argued and has
been argued that the linkage of mind, responsibility and will misses the whole
point of relations among creatures and their world. Evolutionism undermines sharp
dichotomies and makes a mess of scales of moral worth. The attempt to retain a simple
dichotomy between mind and body is also hard to maintain in the face of recent studies of
psychosomatic symptoms. The title of a collection of clinical and philosophical studies
makes the point nicely: it is The Mysterious Leap from the Mind to the Body.[5] Yet
the messages of the psychosomatic symptom, when unravelled in psychoanalytic therapy, are
perfectly legible in the languages of metaphor, pun and symbol. The crude concept of
'somatic [corporeal] compliance' seems a poor way of hiding our ignorance of how feelings
get manifested physically as a symptom, a way of avoiding thinking about, and consciously
knowing, human distress. In this brief treatment, many aspects of the mind-body problem have
been eschewed for the sake of clarity. If one cast one's net more broadly, one would have
to agree with Feigl: 'It is truly a cluster of intricate puzzles some scientific,
some epistemological, some syntactical, some semantical, and some pragmatic. Closely
related to these are the equally sensitive and controversial issues regarding teleology,
purpose, intentionality, and free will'.[6]Rather than remaining split by the mind-body problem, it would surely
be better to find a way of knowing that (to paraphrase Gilbert and Sullivan) the meaning
isn't matter and never idle patter of a transcendental kind. Nature is a meaningful unity,
of which our philosophies must be seen as a part. Those, like Rorty, who would dissolve
the history of the great questions of ontology and epistemology of mind/body and
subject/object into a moving army of metaphors, seem to me to be appropriately
gentle:
These so-called ontological categories are simply the ways of packaging
rather heterogeneous notions, from rather diverse historical sources, which were
convenient for Descartes' own purposes. But his purposes are not ours. Philosophers should
not think of this artificial conglomerate as if it were a discovery of some thing
pre-existent a discovery which because "intuitive" or
"conceptual" or "categorical" sets permanent parameters for science
and philosophy.[7]
That is to say that what we mean by reality, including minds, bodies,
persons and other dimensions of nature, is inside history and open to historical revision
and reconceptualisation. It is to be hoped that the concepts will be friendly rather than
tyrannical.
NOTES
1. R Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton,
1980), p. 120. 2. A. N. Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (1925;
reprinted London, 1985), p. 70. 3. E. A. Burtt, The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical
Science, 2nd ed. (London, 1932), pp. 318-19. 4. Whitehead, (1985), pp. 68-9.5. F. Deutsch, (ed.), On the Mysterious Leap from the Mind to the
Body (New York, 1959).6. H. Feigl, 'The "Mental" and the
"Physical", in H. Feigl et al., (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science (Minneapolis, 1958), Vol. 2, pp. 370-497, at p. 373. 7. Rorty, (1980), p. 125.
FURTHER READING
R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature (Oxford, 1945).R. Descartes, Discourse on Method and the Meditations (trans. E.
A. Sutcliffe, Harmondsworth, 1968).P. K. Feyerabend and G. Maxwell, (eds.), Mind, Matter and Method:
Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl (Minneapolis, 1966).A. von Haller, 'A Dissertation on the Sensible and Irritable Parts of
Animals', with an introduction by 0. Temkin, Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 4
(1936), 651-99.H. Kuhlenbeck, 'The Meaning of "Postulational Psychophysical
Parallelism"', Brain, 8 (1958), 588-603.G. Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London, 1949).P. F. Strawson, Individuals: an Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London,
1959).A. Vartanian, La Mettrie's L 'homme machine: a Study in the Origins
of an Idea (Princeton, l980).R. M. Young, 'Animal Soul', in P. Edwards, (ed.), The Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (London, 1967), Vol. 1, pp. 122-7.R. M. Young, 'Freud: Scientist and/or Humanist', Free Associations, 7
(1968), 7-35.Reprinted from R. C. Olby et al., eds., Companion to the
History of Modern Science. Routledge, 1990, pp. 702-11.