This passage had a big impact on my
thinking, as did the following one from Joan Riviere's classic Kleinian essay 'On the
Genesis of Psychical Conflict in Early Infancy' (1952):
I wish especially to point out... that from the very beginning of life,
on Freud's own hypothesis, the psyche responds to the reality of its experiences by
interpreting them or rather, misinterpreting them in a subjective
manner that increases its pleasure and preserves it from pain. This act of subjective
interpretation of experience, which it carries out by means of the processes of
introjection and projection, is called by Freud hallucination; and it forms the foundation
of what we mean by phantasy-life. The phantasy-life of the individual is thus the
form in which his real internal and external sensations and perceptions are interpreted
and represented to himself in his mind under the influence of the pleasure-pain principle.
(It seems to me that one has only to consider for a moment to see that, in spite of all
the advances man has made in adaptation of a kind to external reality, this primitive and
elementary function of his psyche to misinterpret his perceptions for his own
satisfaction still retains the upper hands in the minds of the great majority of
even civilized adults.) (Riviere, 1952, p. 41).
In claiming that experience is characteristically misinterpreted at
source and that distortion to the point of hallucination is at the very foundation of
experience, Riviere is saying that there are no uninterpreted experiences, and there is no
neutral observation language in everyday life. You don't start with pure sense data which
then get subjectively distorted. The very act of having experience is coloured by
irrational processes. Looking more broadly, by the way, the same claim about there being
no neutral observation language is made of science in recent work in the philosophy of
science.
Another way of putting this point about the role of primitive processes
was said to me one Saturday morning in the early 1980s at the intersection of Baker Street
and the Marleybone Road: All knowledge is knowledge of the mothers body.
I remember that moment vividly. It is connected to a broader claim, that we continue
throughout life unconsciously to experience all of life and thought in an alimentary way.
Meltzer (1992) makes this very vivid in his critique of careerism in the concept of the
claustrum. Not only is the ego at bottom a body ego; the same is true of the mind more
broadly conceived. The general form of these claims from Bion, Riviere and Meltzer is that
the primitive is never transcended. Indeed, Riviere and Isaacs claim that unconscious
phantasy is the sine qua non of having a mind and is at work at the foundations of
all of thought, no matter how sophisticated on the surface.
Well, thats a far cry from what I had been taught in medical
school and had experienced in my first analysis. Indeed, I remember the child
psychotherapist of one of my children saying to me on several occasions that Miss
Freud was fond of saying, "Reality must be our first hypothesis". She was
also fond of describing the analytic process as one of education, of replacing maladaptive
ideas with realistic ones. That way of thinking is a long way from distorting experience
to the point of hallucination in the very having of experience. Another stark assertion I
took in somewhere about this point in the development of my psychoanalytic orientation was
a droll comment of Meltzers. Klein described schizoid mechanisms as occurring 'in
the baby's development in the first year of life characteristically... the infant suffered
from states of mind that were in all their essentials equivalent to the adult psychoses,
taken as regressive states in Freud's sense' (Meltzer, 1978, part 3, p. 22). Klein says in
the third paragraph of her most famous paper, 'Notes on Some Schizoid Mechanisms', 'In
early infancy anxieties characteristic of psychosis arise which drive the ego to develop
specific defence-mechanisms. In this period the fixation-points for all psychotic
disorders are to be found. This has led some people to believe that I regard all infants
as psychotic; but I have already dealt sufficiently with this misunderstanding on other
occasions' (Klein, 1975, vol. 3, p. 1). Meltzer comments that 'Although she denied that
this was tantamount to saying that babies are psychotic, it is difficult to see how this
implication could be escaped' (Meltzer, 1978, part 3, p. 22).
In case these examples are not self-explanatory, I am mentioning
moments in my own psychoanalytic studies which led me to a growing conviction that
Kleinian psychoanalysis is tough, scary and far from straightforward. Ill put that
more starkly and say that it sacrifices objectivity for truth. The reassuring scientistic
language and models used by Freudians go out the window, as does the sensible civility of
the Independents. Kleinianism, you might say, affects the parts of the inner world other
beers do not reach, and by placing the emphasis on the inner world which it does, it loses
the appearance (for it was never a reality) of conforming to the traditional relationship
of observer and observed with science posits and which leads us to believe that we are
here observing, as if with an optical instrument, and the patient is over there, being
observed. In fact, we are inside each other and often unsure who is having which thought
or feeling, and primitive processes are much more present and influential that we like to
believe (Young, 1997).
I want now to offer three parallel stories, one about projective
identification, another about the Oedipus complex and a third about countertransference
(each is drawn from a more extensive study).
Projective identification is probably the Kleinian concept which has
been most widely influential, but it is my experience that most people do not grasp or
accept how radical it is. It is hard to hold on to the fact that it is an unconscious
process, and people too easily collapse it into projection. In doing so they miss out the
impoverishment involved in putting a part of oneself into an other and the symbiosis which
is thereby created and which is quite literally inescapable unless one can take back the
projection (a synonym for improving psychological health). Moreover, many people,
particularly Americans who write about projective identification, mistakenly believe that
an external other who is affected by the projection, is invariably the second moment of
the process. In fact, for Klein and the British Kleinians, we can project into another,
who may but need not be actually affected. For example, in Joel Chandler
Harris famous parable, The Wonderful Tar Baby Story, the Tar Baby does
nothing except be sticky, and the rabbit becomes progressively enraged at its
unresponsiveness and rudeness and loses the use of each of his limbs in turn, as a result
of winding himself up and thwoping the Tar Baby. The unconscious mental mechanism involved
here is projective identification, set up by wily Brer Fox (Young, 1996a). Moreover and
very importantly, we can project into another part of our own minds; no external other
need be involved. Once again, we are, in Kleinian theory, not able to find reliable
signposts in external relations. The power of the inner world over experience and
behaviour is awesome.
The other thing to be said about projective identification is that it
is ubiquitous. Klein says of the processes involved, almost laconically, This leads
to a particular form of identification which establishes the prototype of an aggressive
object-relation' (Klein, 1946, pp. 7-8). Note carefully that we have here the model
the template, the fundamental experience of all of the aggressive features of
human relations. Six years later Klein adds the following sentence: 'I suggest for
these processes the term "projective identification"' (ibid.). I have
elsewhere spelled out the range and power of this concept in its benign and malignant
manifestations, including its place in knowledge, love and hate, religion and science,
racism and virulent nationalism. After reviewing the development of the concept, Torras de
Beà writes,
These authors consider that projective identification is the basic
mechanism of empathy and primitive communication and also of the defence mechanism which
consists of dissociating and projecting anxiety in order to be rid of it. I agree with
this and think also that what we call projective identification is the active element in
every communication from empathy to the most pathological and defensive (Torras de Beà,
1989, p. 266).
He concludes that it is 'the mechanism basic to all human interaction'
(p. 272). As if that was not grand enough, Bion takes the concept of projective
identification and expands in into the notion of container/contained and offers it as the
basis of a whole theory of human nature, as Hinshelwood says, of the relationships
between people, and between groups; of the relationships between internal objects; and of
the relationships in the symbolic world between thoughts, ideas, experiences, etc.
(Hinshelwood, 1991, p. 191).
What I have to say about the Oedipus complex is parallel. Kleinianism
takes something relatively straightforward and makes it messy, albeit more profound. In a
footnote added to the 1920 edition of Three Essays on Sexuality, Freud made it
clear that the Oedipus complex is the immovable foundation stone on which the whole
edifice of psychoanalysis is based:
It has justly been said that the Oedipus complex is the nuclear complex
of the neuroses, and constitutes the essential part of their content. It represents the
peak of infantile sexuality, which, through its after-effects, exercises a decisive
influence on the sexuality of adults. Every new arrival on this planet is faced with the
task of mastering the Oedipus complex; anyone who fails to do so falls a victim to
neurosis. With the progress of psycho-analytic studies the importance of the Oedipus
complex has become more and more clearly evident; its recognition has become the
shibboleth that distinguishes the adherents of psycho-analysis from its opponents (Freud,
1905, p. 226n).
I dont think Klein intends to challenge this, but she does
introduce a notion called the Oedipal situation which is very likely to cause
confusion. According to the traditional developmental account as it appears in the libido
theory, the superego is heir to the Oedipus complex, but Klein famously has the child
suffering from intense guilt feelings at a scandalously early age in relation to the first
introjected object, the breast. Moreover, she claims that ...emotional and sexual
development, object relations and super-ego development interact from the beginning
(p. 82). Indeed, a close look at her writings leads one to believe that all of the
developmental landmarks of the chronology developed by Freud, Abraham and others have been
taken away (rather as the road signs were in England In World War II in order to confuse
the Germans), so that we are left slip-slidin around. Ruth Stein has gone further
and has argued that Klein has no theory of mental structures, only sets of paired
emotions, love & hate, envy & gratitude, etc., with movement back and forth
between two basic positions, paranoid-schizoid and depressive, as the basic parameters of
mental attitude. In any case, this Oedipal situation turns out not to be the developmental
milestone of the classical libido theory but to be a moveable feast. Ronald Britton sees
'the depressive position and the Oedipus situation as never finished but as having to be
re-worked in each new life situation, at each stage of development, and with each major
addition to experience or knowledge' (p. 38).
Here we have a useful cross-over between Kleinian and Freudian theory.
Projective identification lies at the heart of the paranoid-schizoid position, in which
splitting, projective mechanisms and part-object relations predominate. Once again, this
configuration is in a dynamic relation with the depressive position, in which whole-object
relations, concern for the object and integration predominate. What has happened in
subsequent research is that these ways of thinking have been brought into relationship
with one another. As David Bell puts it,
The primitive Oedipal conflict described by Klein takes place in the
paranoid-schizoid position when the infant's world is widely split and relations are
mainly to part objects. This means that any object which threatens the exclusive
possession of the idealised breast/mother is felt as a persecutor and has projected into
it all the hostile feelings deriving from pregenital impulses (Bell, 1992, p. 172)
If development proceeds satisfactorily, secure relations with good
internal objects leads to integration, healing of splits and taking back projections.
The mother is then, so to speak, free to be involved with a third
object in a loving intercourse which, instead of being a threat, becomes the foundation of
a secure relation to internal and external reality. The capacity to represent internally
the loving intercourse between the parents as whole objects results, through the ensuing
identifications, in the capacity for full genital maturity. For Klein, the resolution of
the Oedipus complex and the achievement of the depressive position refer to the same
phenomena viewed from different perspectives (ibid.).
Ronald Britton puts it very elegantly: 'the two situations are
inextricably intertwined in such a way that one cannot be resolved without the other: we
resolve the Oedipus complex by working through the depressive position and the depressive
position by working through the Oedipus complex' (Britton, 1992, p. 35).
This provides us with something like Rosetta Stone, a key to
translating between the Freudian and Kleinian conceptual schemes. In the recent work of
Kleinians this way of thinking has been applied to broader issues, in particular, the
ability to symbolise and learn from experience. Integration of the depressive position
which we can now see as resolution of the Oedipus complex is the sine qua
non of the development of 'a capacity for symbol formation and rational thought' (p.
37). Greater knowledge of the object 'includes awareness of its continuity of existence in
time and space and also therefore of the other relationships of the object implied by that
realization. The Oedipus situation exemplifies that knowledge. Hence the depressive
position cannot be worked through without working through the Oedipus complex and vice
versa' (p. 39).
This way of looking at the Oedipal situation also offers a way of
thinking of self-knowledge or insight:
The primal family triangle provides the child with two links connecting
him separately with each parent and confronts him with the link between them which
excludes him. Initially this parental link is conceived in primitive part-object terms and
in the modes of his own oral, anal and genital desires, and in terms of his hatred
expressed in oral, anal and genital terms. If the link between the parents perceived in
love and hate can be tolerated in the child's mind, it provides him with a prototype for
an object relationship of a third kind in which he is a witness and not a participant. A
third position then comes into existence from which object relationships can be observed.
Given this, we can also envisage being observed. This provides us with a capacity
for seeing ourselves in interaction with others and for entertaining another point of view
whilst retaining our own, for reflecting on ourselves whilst being ourselves (Britton,
1989, p. 87).
I find this very helpful, indeed, profound, but it is far from
straightforward. I should add that Ron Brittons new book, Belief and Imagination (1998), develops these ideas much further. I regard his writings as the most interesting and
original psychoanalytic work which I have recently encountered.
I turn now to the third example I promised you
countertransference. I have written about this at length elsewhere (Young, 1994, ch. 4),
as I have about projective identification (1994, ch. 7) and the Oedipus complex (Young,
1994a). Concepts in psychoanalysis have histories just like concepts in other disciplines,
and we would do well to think of them in historical terms. Freud became aware of
countertransference as an interference, a threat to the analysts objectivity, and
recommended more analysis as the treatment of choice. This was the received position until
the late 1940s and the 1950s when Winnicott, Little, Searles, Money Kyrle, Heimann and
others came to question the idea that countertransference was just something to be got rid
of and suggested that it be attended to. However, except for Searles, this group strikes
me as opening the door only to close it again, lest things become too unstraightforward.
In her first paper on the topic Paula Heimann claims that 'the analyst's
countertransference is not only part and parcel of the analytic relationship, but it is
the patient's creation, it is a part of the patient's personality' (Heimann,
1949-50, p. 77). When she returns to the topic a decade later, Heimann reflects at length
on how to handle countertransference material and takes up a cautious position. In her
conclusion, she reverts to the early view of Freud. In so doing, it seems to me, she
fails, after all, to see the larger potential of the concept. She says, in her last
paragraph, 'In conclusion, Freud's injunction that the countertransference must be
recognised and overcome is as valid today as it was fifty years ago. When it occurs, it
must be turned to some useful purpose. Continued self-analysis and self-training will help
to decrease incidents of countertransference' (Heimann, 1959-60, p. 160). For her,
countertransference was still a lapse from analytic purity something to learn from
when it occurs but preferably to be got rid of. Current Kleinian thinking is very much
more bold. To reduce the incidents of countertransference is no longer a goal
among many therapists.
A paper by Irma Brenman Pick takes the normality of countertransference
to its logical extreme, without a trace of seeing it as something to be got rid of. She
carefully considers it as the basis of understanding throughout the session: 'Constant
projecting by the patient into the analyst is the essence of analysis; every
interpretation aims at a move from the paranoid/schizoid to the depressive position'
(Brenman Pick, 1985, p. 158). She makes great play of the tone, the mood and the
resonances of the process: 'I think that the extent to which we succeed or fail in this
task will be reflected not only in the words we choose, but in our voice and other
demeanour in the act of giving an interpretation...' (p. 161). Most importantly, she
emphasises the power of the projections and what they evoke countertransferentially:
I have been trying to show that the issue is not a simple one; the
patient does not just project into an analyst, but instead patients are quite skilled at
projecting into particular aspects of the analyst. Thus, I have tried to show, for
example, that the patient projects into the analyst's wish to be a mother, the wish to be
all-knowing or to deny unpleasant knowledge, into the analyst's instinctual sadism, or
into his defences against it. And above all, he projects into the analyst's guilt, or into
the analyst's internal objects.
'Thus, patients touch off in the analyst deep issues and anxieties
related to the need to be loved and the fear of catastrophic consequences in the face of
defects, i.e., primitive persecutory or superego anxiety (p. 161).
As I see it, the approach adopted by Brenman Pick takes it as read and
as normal that these powerful feelings are moving from patient to analyst and back again,
through the processes of projection, evocation, reflection, detoxification, interpretation
and assimilation. Moving on from the more limited formulations of an earlier period in the
writings of Winnicott, Heimann and even Money-Kyrle, these feelings are all normal, as it
were, in the processes of analysis. More than that, as Brenman Pick puts it, they are the
essence.
In my opinion, the person whose work most consistently exemplifies this
approach was working largely independently and in another country and is not a Kleinian.
Even so, his work is deeply consistent with the position advocated by Brenman Pick. In a
series of profoundly evocative papers which he began to write as early as the late 1940s
(but could not at first get published) and extending to his latest writings, Harold
Searles has argued that the therapist is much more at risk and much more perturbed,
sussed or rumbled by the patient than traditional models of the analytic
relationship would allow us to believe. I have written about Searles work at length
elsewhere. My point in the current context is that we are dealing not only with what the
patient puts into us, but what he or she evokes in us our own stuff. The basic raw
materials which it is our task to interpret are not what the patient says but our
countertransferences. When it was first argued that the countertransference should be
taken seriously, there was an outcry, the point of which was that if you cannot sort out
your feelings from the patients, you are in deep trouble. In Brenman Picks
vivid examples and in Searles writings, in particular, in his concept of therapeutic
symbiosis, it is clear that we are, indeed, in just that selfsame very deep trouble. That
is where we work, and we have no scientistic concept of objectivity to fall back on.
Searles is scathing and says that to the extent we are orthodox in this matter, we are
mad.
Just to confuse things even further, I should add that Klein was
herself very sceptical about positive conceptions of countertransference, while Bion did
not stress the term at all, even though it could be said that his work is about little
else. Being a Kleinian, as I say, is not straightforward.
I now come to the character of the therapist or analyst. In earlier
times my sense was of a person with an inner stillness, a person of equanimity, that kind
Dr Wik in Snake Pit who helps Olivia de Havilland to get to the top ward. I no
longer think that way. Instead, I think of someone personifying containment, someone who
can bear experience, including profoundly toxic experience, without being sundered by it.
I am sometimes reeling after a session with certain patients and have even been heard, I
regret to say, to emit a rather heavy sigh when I thought a patient was safely out of
earshot. I no longer think that Im in the business of dredging, as Freud famously
put it in The New Introductory Lectures: 'Where id was, there ego shall be. It is a
work of culture not unlike the draining of the Zuider Zee' (Freud, 1933, p. 80).
That is, I no longer believe myself to be reclaiming territory from the sea of emotions to
the dry land of rationality and putting dikes between the two realms. I do not expect my
interpretations to substitute rationality for irrationality. Instead, I hope, little by
little, by demeanour and tone as well as formulation, to bring feelings and actions within
the boundaries of civilization, of civility. I am pleased when a patient says she has the
same feelings but is not so likely to act on them or be reduced to despair. I try to
operate on the right side of the risks of bursting or banalizing. I tend to think of the
mind as a cauldron, containing a complex mixture of all sorts of feelings, many very bad,
some bizarre, some hopeful and loving. My job is to create a space where it is safe to
stir it, to help it simmer, to foster enriched flavours and nourishing qualities and to
help to moderate the temperature so it will not to boil over.
I also think, quite routinely, that the psychotic anxieties with which
I work on an hourly basis are forms of nameless dread, the harbingers of death itself. In
that sense Klein was, unlike those who turned away from the full poignancy of the human
condition, the true heir to Freud on Civilization and Its Discontents, where he
wrote that the constitutional inclination to aggression is the greatest hindrance or
impediment to civilization (Freud, 1930, pp. 129, 142). It is in this context that the
space within which civilization occurs is described as bounded by the great opposition
between love and destructiveness. 'Civilization is a process in the service of Eros, whose
purpose is to combine single human individuals, and after that families, then races,
peoples and nations, into one great unity, the unity of mankind... But man's aggressive
instinct, the hostility of each against all and all against each, opposes this programme
of civilization' (p. 122). The aggressive instinct is derivative of the death instinct.
'The history of civilization is the struggle between Eros and Death. It is what all life
essentially consists of' (Ibid.).
This sobering quotation brings me to my last topic, the social
relations of the Kleinian community. It will not be news to you that Klein and Kleinianism
have been and remain controversial. Just how controversial was not widely known until two
volumes made it so, Phyllis Grosskurths biography, Melanie Klein: Her World and
Her Work, which appeared in 1985, and The Freud-Klein Controversies 1941-45,
edited by Pearl King and Ricardo Steiner, published six years later. Perhaps I can plunge
straight into what I have to say by quoting Grosskurths inscription in my copy of
her book: To Robert Young with warm wishes and thanks for your support. What
support? Well, in fact, practically all of the eminent Kleinians boycotted the launch
party, which devastated Grosskurth, and I publicly deplored this fact. What this
illustrates is that Kleinians tell us about just how awful people can be and forcibly draw
our attention to just how deeply intermixed the good and bad features of human nature are
and yet proceed, in their own social relations, to create tremendously idealised heroes,
actually usually heroines, and will hear nothing said against them. I find this
strange, inconsistent and embarrassing. Grosskurth showed Klein, warts and all, as did
Nicholas Wright, in his play, Mrs Klein, which evoked the only breach of
analytic neutrality, the only breach of boundaries, I experienced from my Kleinian
analyst. He said, Okay, if you want an opinion, its shit. I can think of
several people in the Kleinian world who have done truly admirable work, but the reverence
in which they are held is really distressing and inconsistent with the advocacy of balance
of the mixed nature of reality and sanity as characterised in the depressive position. I
am thinking, in particular, of the hagiography of and deference to Bion, Hanna Segal,
Martha Harris and Donald Meltzer, and I suspect that some younger people are coming to be
revered in the same way. At the risk of sounding priggish or even envious, I want to say
that this is inappropriate in a psychoanalytic culture. Give people their due, but their
feet should continue to touch the ground and their admirers knees should not touch
the ground.
But we do not only have one side of the split, idealisation. We also
have denigration within the Kleinian community and between it and other approaches. There
have recently been a number of Bion celebrations. I attended two. At the first I was
struck by the absence of all of the interpreters of his work whose writings I had
found helpful, and at the second they were there, as was Bions daughter (tragically
recently killed in an automobile accident), but none of the people who had been prominent
at the first conference were present. Sectarianism within sectarianism. Similarly, it is
said that if one is not in favour with the Melanie Klein Trust, one is forever an outsider
in Kleinian circles. I know of at least one prolific and insightful author of whom this is
true and who has decamped to a different base. I know of another, a foreigner and a
Kleinian, who has had more than half a dozen articles rejected by Kleinian referees of the IJPA.
I could go on at length in this vein about relations inside the
Kleinian subculture, but I want to speak about its external relations, as well. It is
commonly known in the present that the Independents peck the Contemporary Freudians, and
the Kleinians peck both of the other groups. As for the past, we have all of the evidence
of the Controversial Discussions, the ferocity of which many put down to two conflicting
and powerful personalities. This must have been a factor, but it would not have operated
in a setting thirty years on when Kleinianism was found attractive by Bernard Brandchaft
and a few others in the Los Angeles institute. The result was uproar which became so
intense that the American Psychoanalytic Association repeatedly threatened to close down
the institute unless they got rid of the Kleinian influence. Of course, part of this is
explained by the defensiveness of the Freudian orthodoxy, qualntly referred to as
traditional American psychoanalysis in the internal memoranda, meaning ego
psychology. But, as Douglas Kirsner (1999) has shown in an insightful story of this
conflict, among others he has studied in American psychoanalytic history, another
important factor was certainly the militancy, contempt and intolerance of the nascent
Kleinian group, inspired or at least catalysed by the leading British Kleinians whom they
invited to teach them. Herbert Rosenfeld was described as pretty autocratic. He made
pronouncements like Moses receiving the tablets on the Mount. He had that character of
stating something as the real, ultimate truth, stating as a fact what could not have been
more than a speculation. Meltzer was similarly experienced as arrogant and made a
remark which polarised the atmosphere. He is said to have equated Kleinian analysis
with contemporary psychoanalysis and classical analysis as belonging to the early part of
the century. Hans Thorner, Hanna Segal and Betty Joseph also visited. Bion lived
there for seven years in this period and, for example, analysed James Grotstein, but (on
Kirsners evidence) he seems not to have been directly involved in these conflicts.
Their ideas were taken up by a group of Young Turks who became, as James Grotstein later
reflected, unreasonably obnoxious, certain, omnipotent: "We have the
truth". I know I felt that. The trouble is I think we all did ourselves in. We were
right but we were wrong. Grotstein felt that... the visiting British Kleinians made
him feel like a naughty colonial. In Grotsteins view,
While the Los Angeles Kleinians were no doubt scapegoated, the
Kleinians also reacted very provocatively and became more strident as the polarisation
continued. The polarisation resulted in a decreasing middle ground the leaders of
the institute were seen by many (the Kleinians included) as enemies of the Kleinians whom
the leadership purportedly viewed as a threat to psychoanalysis (quotations from Kirsner,
1999, ch. 4).
It was a very rough encounter, indeed, recalling the most abrasive
episodes in the earlier Controversial Discussions in London, where, on one occasion,
someone had to point out that there was an air raid going on, so intense was the internal
warfare in the Institute building. The Los Angeles episode, like the Controversial
Discussions, tells me that there is a problem at the heart of Kleinian assertiveness.
I have seen this militancy, splitting, intolerance and contempt at
first hand. I belong to a psychotherapy organization in which key figures say and do
breathtakingly alarming things. For example, when it was suggested that the training had
become too Kleinian, the head of the training said that this could not be so, since
Kleinianism is now synonymous with psychoanalysis (shades of Meltzers comment in the
1970s). Moreover, this person opined that ours is the only training which still teaches
people to work in the transference, since it had recently become apparent that the other
most highly regarded psychotherapy training no longer did so. The preceding head of
training had made it a condition of certain candidates continuing on the course that
they enter Kleinian analysis. Some who had been in another sort of therapy under the
previous regime were required to change to Kleinian analysis.
This kind of thinking also touches on the ongoing difficulties between
the UKCP and BCP, about which I have written extensively (Young, 1996, 1997a). The facet
of it which touches on Kleinianism is that certain (though not all) key figures in the
organisation to which I belong have done deeply undemocratic, manipulative, secret and
devious things. They are Kleinians. I cannot be sure that there is a connection, but I
offer you a hypothesis which I hold strongly. They believe that the BCP is a bulwark,
holding out for the highest standards. They also appear to believe that the end justifies
the means or they would not have, for example, refused to accede to three successive votes
to rejoin the UKCP, from which they had removed us without consulting the membership. On
the third occasion, the chair announced that they would not accede to the vote and that no
discussion of this decision was to be permitted at the AGM. The connection in my mind is
that if you are certain that you have a pipeline to the truth, you are justified in
behaving in ways which others might consider to be wrong in a higher
cause. The chair, the subsequent chair and the two successive heads of training are
all Kleinians, part of a self-perpetuating oligarchy benefitting from a gerrymandered
constitution. Shaky logic, you may say, but inside the context of the organisation there
is a widely held perception that these matters are related.
But, of course, my general argument does not depend on any particular
example. I venture that everyone here has a strong sense of the two basic points I am
making in this talk. The first is that the richness and depth of Kleinian theory and
practice lead into territories where one has to rely on a strong belief that intuitive
certainty is a surer path to truth than either the scientistic metapsychology of
Freudianism, the warm remothering of some other approaches or the more humanistic
approaches favoured by some orientations. My own reaction to some of the methodological
criticisms of psychoanalysis which are abroad these days is that I am more sure of certain
of my interpretations than I am of the laws of physics and chemistry. As I said earlier,
we go for truth as more important than objectivity. Kleinianism is not straightforward,
but it is profoundly helpful and therefore true in the sense of clinically fruitful. I
think that it also gives us a richer and more true to life picture of human nature for
good and ill. On the other hand, this same intuitive certainty is widely associated with
forms of behaviour by Kleinians which include idealisation, preciousness, denigration and
contempt, undemocratic behaviour, manipulativeness, deviousness, bullying, dogmatism and
other forms of unattractive behaviour which I do not want to be associated with my
clinical orientation.
Let me put my point another way. The view of human nature offered by
Kleinianism is, in my opinion, that of a mixture; it is in the depressive position.
However, the sectarian and institutional behaviour I have indicated in this last portion
of my talk is in the paranoid-schizoid position. It is crooked, wrong, full of extreme
splits, lack concern for the object, employs persecutory guilt. One conclusion we might
draw is that, as the Good Book says, By their fruits shall ye know them. I
have certainly drawn that conclusion about Lacanianism from the behaviour of Lacan and of
the Lacanians I have known, as well as my experience of the impenetrability of the theory.
Inconsistently, you may say, I am, to put it mildly, reluctant to judge the priesthood of
Kleinianism by its priests, but I am deeply troubled by the sorts of behaviours I have
sketched (and could do much more if I was not trying to remain impersonal).
I will have to leave it here. I have, however, one thought to leave you
with. One of the things I like about being a psychotherapist is that it is, on a good day,
deeply fulfilling. What I find fulfilling about it is that something so good can come out
of an activity and way of being which is in its essence ordinary. Ordinary is an
undervalued word. I think the depressive position is ordinary. I think the splits at the
bottom of the untoward behaviours I have mentioned are paranoid-schizoid and, in a
fundamental sense, extraordinary. I think the misbehaving people call themselves Kleinians
but in the activities I am criticising are going for the extraordinary, and thats
their mistake. I dont want to settle for that.
A picture comes to mind. Jack Nicholson gave an inspired performance as
an utterly selfish, obsessive-compulsive person in the film As Good as It
Gets. If you have seen it, you will know that the title is picked up in a hilarious
moment. When the impulse to change first starts to operate on him he bursts impulsively
into his shrinks office, only to be firmly told that he will have to make an
appointment and wait his turn. He exits via the waiting room, which is filled with
desperate looking patients. As he passes through, he makes a throwaway crack: What
if this is as good as it gets? Well, we are told by Kleinian theory that the
depressive position is as good as it gets. For a long time I found this hard to accept.
However, this stoicism overlooks the potential fruits of an ongoing process. In that
position Nicholson goes on changing, albeit by fits and starts. He tell the heroine
(Hellen Hunt) that meeting her had led him to get back into treatment. She impatiently
says this piece of information is not the compliment she needed to hear at that moment.
His reply is devatstatingly moving: You make me want to be a better man. Well,
I want ordinary Kleinianism to make our practitioners willing to apply it reflexively, to
give up their idealising and denigrating projections and to strive to be better people
both as individuals and as a group of practitioners operating in the subculture of
psychoanalysis and psychotherapy.
This is the text of the Seventh Annual Public Lecture delivered to the
Severnside Institute of Psychotherapy, Bristol, 10 October 1998.
REFERENCES
Bell, D. (1992) 'Hysteria - A Contemporary Kleinian Perspective', Brit.
J. Psychother. 9: 169-80.
Bion, W. R. (1955) 'Group Dynamics - a Re-view', in Klein et al, eds.
(1955), pp. 440-77.
______ (1961) Experiences in Groups and Other Papers. Tavistock.
Brenman Pick, I. (1985) 'Working Through in the Counter-transference', Int. J. Psycho-anal. 66: 157-66; reprinted in Spillius, ed. (1988), vol. 2, pp. 34-47.
Britton, R. (1989) 'The Missing Link: Parental Sexuality in the Oedipus
Complex', in Britton et al. (1989), pp. 83-102.
______ (1992) 'The Oedipus Situation and the Depressive Position', in
R. Anderson, ed., Clinical Lectures on Klein and Bion. Routledge, pp. 34-45.
______ et al. (1989) The Oedipus Complex Today: Clinical
Implications. Karnac.
______ (1998) Belief and Imagination: Explorations in
Psychoanalysis. Routledge.
Freud, S. (1953-73) The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud., 24 vols. Hogarth. (S. E.).
______ (1905) Three Essays on Sexuality. S. E. 7, pp. 125-245.
______ (1930) Civilization and Its Discontents. S. E. 21, pp.
59-145.
______ (1933) New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis. S. E.
22, pp. 3-182.
Grosskurth, Phyllis (1986) Melanie Klein: Her World and Her Work. Hodder
and Stoughton.
Heimann, Paula. (l949-50) 'On Counter-transference', in Heimann (1990), pp. 73-9.
______ (l959-60) 'Counter-transference', in Heimann (1990), pp. 151-60.
______ (1990) About Children and Children No Longer: The Work of Paula Heimann. Routledge.
Hinshelwood, R. D. (1991) A Dictionary of Kleinian Thought, 2nd
ed. Free Association Books.
Isaacs, Susan (1952) The Nature and Function of Phantasy, in Klein et
al. (1952), pp. 67-121.
King, Pearl. & Steiner, Ricardo, eds. (1991) The Freud-Klein Controversies
1941-45. Tavistock/Routledge.
Kirsner, Douglas (1999) Unfree
Associations: Inside Psychoanalytic Institutes. Process Press.
Klein, Melanie (1928) 'Early Stages of the Oedipus Conflict', Int.
J. Psycho-anal. 9: 167-80; reprinted in Klein (1975), vol. 1, pp. 186-98
______ (1935) 'A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States',
reprinted in W. M. K. II, pp, 262-89.
______ (1945) 'The Oedipus Complex in the Light of Early Anxieties', Int. J.
Psycho-Anal. 26: 11-33; reprinted in Klein (1975), vol. 1, pp. 370-419 and in Britton et
al. (1989), pp. 11-82, esp. summary, pp. 63-82.
______ (1946) 'Notes on Some Schizoid Mechanisms', Int. J.
Psycho-anal. 27: 99-110, reprinted in Klein (1975), vol. 3, pp. 1-24.
______ (1975) The Writings of Melanie Klein, 4 vols. Hogarth. Vol. I: Love,
Guilt and Reparation and Other Works, 1921-1945. Vol. II: The Psycho-Analysis of
Children. Vol. III Envy and Gratitude and Other Works; 1946-1963. Vol. IV: Narrative
of a Child Analysis. all reprinted Virago, 1988. (W. M. K. )
______ et al. (1952) Developments in Psycho-Analysis. Hogarth.
______ et al., eds. (1955) New Directions in Psycho-Analysis: The
Significance of Infant Conflicts in the Patterns of Adult Behaviour. Tavistock;
reprinted Maresfield, 1977.
Meltzer, Donald (1978) The Kleinian Development Part I: Freuds
Clinical Development; Part II: Richard Week-by-Week; Part III: The Clinical Significance
of the Work of Bion. Strath Tay: Clunie.
______ (1992) The Claustrum: An Investigation of Claustrophobic
Phenomena. Strath Tay: Clunie.
Searles, Harold F. (1976) 'Transitional Phenomena and Therapeutic
Symbiosis', in Searles (1979), pp. 503-76.
______ (1978-9) 'Concerning Transference and Countertransference'. J. Psychoanal. Psychother. 7: 165-88 (written in 1949).
______ (1979) Countertransference and Related Subjects. Madison,
CT: International Universities Press.
______ (1986) My Work with Borderline Patients. Aronson.
Spillius, Elizabeth (1988) Melanie Klein Today, 2 vols.
Routledge.
Stein, Ruth (1990) 'A New Look at the Theory of Melanie Klein', Int.
J. Psycho-anal. 71: 499-511.
Young, Robert M. (1994) Mental Space. Process Press.
______ (1994a) New Ideas about the Oedipus Complex, Melanie
Klein and Object Relations. 12 (no. 2): 1-20.
______ (1995) The Vicissitudes of Transference and
Countertransference: The Work of Harold Searles, J. Arbours Association, 9:
24-58, 1992; also in Free Assns. (no. 34) 5: 171-195.
______ (1996) The Culture of British
Psychoanalysis.
______ (1997) Phantasy and Psychotic Anxieties, in B.
Burgoyne and Mary Sullivan, eds., The Klein-Lacan Dialogues. Rebus Press, pp.
65-81.