Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
THE ROLE OF PSYCHOANALYSIS AND PSYCHOTHERAPY IN THE HUMAN
SCIENCES
by Robert M. Young
What follows is a talk which I gave to the Zangwill Club at the
Department of Experimental Psychology in Cambridge in February 1989. Oliver L. Zangwill
was Professor of Experimental Psychology from the mid 1950's until 1981 and supervised my
doctoral research on 'Cerebral Localization and its Biological Context from Gall to
Ferrier', which was later published as a book, Mind. Brain and Adaptation in the
Nineteenth Century (Oxford 1970). Zangwill was a distinguished psychoneurologist and
held a position at the National Hospital for Neurological Diseases and Blindness, Queen
Square. He was strongly of the belief that psychology is a biological science and insisted
that his department be made part of the biology faculty. His strategy was successful, the
department is highly respected, and he was made a Fellow of the Royal Society.
Before beginning the presentation of the body of my text, I said that
I'd spent about an hour wandering around in Cambridge that afternoon and was struck by the
extent to which it had become a city of boutiques in the fourteen years since Id
left. I feared that in an analogous way the surface of my paper might undermine the deeper
point I was making, just as the surface of the city ran the risk of diverting one's gaze
from the deeper functions of the university. The paper turns on a distinction between
spatial knowledge, which characterizes the official paradigm of explanation of modern
science since the scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries, and evocative
knowledge. 'Spatial' refers to explanation in terms of extension things which can
be seen and measured in a public way. I distinguish the spatial from the evocative
knowledge which is primarily felt, experienced and shared in more intimate ways. Another
way of drawing the distinction is that between knowing about things and knowing
them.
The context in which the lecture was delivered is important, since that
department, like most psychology departments in British universities, has a heavy bias
towards a natural science model of psychology. This helps to explain my emphasis on the
search for a 'natural classification' of human attributes, analogous to the more or less
universally agreed fundamental principles of explanation in the natural sciences
the atoms and particles of physics, the elements of chemistry and the organic compounds of
living systems. I have provided these preliminary remarks rather than rewrite the text,
because I have a certain sense of occasion about the lecture and prefer to leave it as it
stands. I hope that these prefatory words will help to make the lecture accessible to a
wider audience.
It is nearly thirty years since I last gave a talk in this building. It
was on The Psychoanalytic Theory of Memory and Its Relationship to Recent Memory
Theories, especially that of Professor Bartlett. It's pleasant to reflect that I've
come full circle. It is about fifteen years since I last sat in this room. On that
occasion Oliver Zangwill took me aside and said that objections had been made to my
presence in the department, since it was thought that I was stirring up the students. His
way of reminding me that I wasn't to do such things and should be grown-up, was to
persuade me to accompany him immediately thereafter to a meeting of the Faculty of
Medicine. I don't think I even knew that I was a member of the faculty at the time.
I owe a great debt to him. First, he introduced me to Charlie Gross,
one of the great characters of psychology. It was Charlie who gave me, as he did many
others, permission to explore to take one's questions wherever they might lead.
Second, Oliver left me in peace, even when I slept for a time in the lab and especially
when I went my own way in my research. I still think that I remember him saying to me on
the day that we met, 'Hello; Welcome. Charlie will look after you. Come back in three
years and bring your thesis.' In fact, of course, he was available whenever I needed him.
Third, he introduced me to certain English euphemisms which were very valuable to an
American in 1960s. The first was 'If you don't mind my saying so'. Translation: something
horrid coming up. Second, 'I don't think I quite understand you'. A devastating
intellectual point is about to be scored. Third: 'I won't keep you'. Translation: Please
go away now. He was especially good about pretentious people. The story was told that the
students invited Hans Eysenck to give a talk to the Psychology Society. Oliver, with
unfailing courtesy, met the train and found a very inflated Eysenck, who greeted him,
saying, 'Ah, Cambridge; I'm told they burn my books here.' Oliver, whose Wykehamist speech
impediment could wax and wane, depending on the circumstances, looked away in that way
that he did and murmured, 'Books? What books?'
Going back now to that original paper on theories of memory, I was
asking then, as now: what are the roots, the bases, the sources, the foundations for an
understanding of human nature? I want to sketch certain sorts of answers, ending
up, as my title requires, with psychoanalysis and psychotherapy. My remarks will take the
form of an autobiographical narrative, but I hope you won't feel it is merely a
self-indulgent one. The course of this research, like the course of laboratory research,
is directed by an ongoing line of enquiry.
What kind of disciplined exploration is appropriate for gaining
knowledge of human nature the norms, the limitations, the potential? When I began
thinking about this question in the early 1950s I turned to philosophy especially
to ethics and epistemology and, in particular, to the problem of self-reference. How can
we know ourselves? From what vantage point can we reflect on our own natures? If our
spectacles are tinted, from what point of view can we discover this? How can we transcend
our subjectivity?
The answer seemed obvious at the time: we should root our knowledge of
the subjective in objective science. By the time I began graduate work there was a ferment
of ideas around the Limbic System based on the work James Papez, Wilbur Smith, Paul
MacLean, Karl Pribram, Roger Sperry and others, who were tracing the neurophysiological
correlates of emotional functions. It was a very exciting time.
What struck me most and brought me to Cambridge was the conceptual
framework within which most of this research was being conducted: cerebral localization of
function. The basic model was: one function one localization. There was, of course,
a theory at the other extreme equipotentiality and modifications of both
views: schemes of connections, associations, substitutions, inhibitions, etc. But all of
these were deviations from a reigning norm a spatial, correlative one.
This was fundamentally at odds with another set of assumptions about
experience and learning that of associationism, whether in purely psychological
terms or in terms of some version of reflexes and conditioning. Then, of course, there was
the behaviourist model which required neither mind nor reflex, though the conceptual model
was much the same, give or take an operant. Moving on, there were the primary sensory
modalities, maps of motor functions, neuro-endocrine connections, proprioception, and so
on.
In spite of this mixed bag, there was an optimism that functions could
be mapped in spatial terms. Put in more philosophically appealing language, mind could be
thought of as 'functions', which in turn could be correlated in a one to one fashion
(though this might get complex) with physico-chemical science of physiology. Hey presto!
Real science.
This scheme had and as far as I know still has great
appeal. But there are two things wrong with it. First, things turn out to be very complicated.
But second and I think more important there is no natural classification of functions. I want to dwell on this, because I think it makes the attempt
to root mind, i.e., theories of human nature, in basic research a will o' the wisp.
I spent many years asking how the functions are localized or
otherwise represented before it dawned on me that this was not the most important
question. There is a prior one. Which functions? What questions do we bring to the brain?
I won't tax your patience with a potted history of the answers to this
question, but, I do assure you that it has a long and complex history, rooted in Galenical
physiology, medieval ventricular localization, various versions of pneumatic physiology,
physiognomy, phrenology (a discipline in which I was for a brief while the world's leading
expert), aphasia research, sensory-motor physiology. As we move into the modern era we
find the names of Franz Joseph Gall, Pierre Flourens, Gustav Fritsch and Eduard Hitzig,
David Ferrier, Charles Sherrington, who was able to say at the turn of the century, 'We
are all phrenologists'. When we carry the story up to Lashley and the other figures I
mentioned in the 1930s through to the 60s, the beginnings of my own odyssey are reached.
It was a time when psychoanalysis looked like finding a physiological test and
hopefully basis.
But if one looks not at the history of cerebral localization but at the
history of questions, a very different sort of story emerges a very untidy and
multi-levelled one. Since Dalton and Mendeleev and since Rutherford and the discoveries
which led to the postulation of neutrons, omegas, charm and other rather esoteric
particles and features of them, chemistry and physics have had certain relatively settled
terms of reference. I say relatively, because there are various semi-mystical variations
on this orthodox tale.
Something similar is now common in biology. Under the banner of
Rockefeller patronage, a version of living matter in terms of physico-chemical systems,
has led to an increasingly well-understood molecular story which is emerging for our
edification and (though I think we are a bit ahead of ourselves here) modification.
The answers to questions in the physical, chemical and biological
sciences are or should in the long term be given in physical, chemical and
molecular terms. Since humans are physical, chemical and biological organisms the same
long-term goals can be applied to us. I believe this was Oliver Zangwill's deep commitment
to psychology as a biological science. It was certainly the basis of my own doctoral
research on the history of theories of cerebral localization: the search for a natural
classification of functions nature's own language. Yet, I have come to believe that
a different set of terms of reference are at least as appropriate. How did I arrive at
them? More odyssey.
Before embarking on the telling of that tale I want to remind you that
the path I shall tread is in a way that has only recently become fully clear to me
parallel to the one Freud trod. You'll recall that he was doing neurophysiological
research in the 1880's, that his first book, written in 1891, when he was 35, was
entitled, On Aphasia. It attempted to map brain function from clinical cases in the
light of the ideas of Herbert Spencer and Hughlings Jackson. Four years later he sketched
a whole Project for a Scientific Psychology, based on a neurophysiological model
whose terms of reference he drew from the Helmholtz School of Physiology in which his
mentors had been trained. Five years after that he outlined a theory of mind which was
still based on neurophysiological concepts. Chapter Seven of The Interpretation of
Dreams rested on the reflex concept and on a mental scheme of spatially localized
functions, although the space then, as in his later revision in 1921 was a
mental one. He remained true, however, to a metaphorical physiology which he believed
would one day be completed with the parallel story in brain studies.
A philosophical principle he had drawn from Spencer and Hughlings
Jackson allowed him to keep this faith in the principle of psychophysical parallelism
the belief that the mental and the physiological are parallel, that reduction of
the one to the other is not appropriate and that a science of mental phenomena could stand
on its own until neurophysiology caught up.
What Freud did in that parallel realm of a psychology was to ransack culture classical myths, religions, everyday life, dreams, fairy tales and, above all,
the stories of his patients. It is to the language of stories and the ways of
thinking appropriate to them that my own odyssey leads.
The question I asked myself in the years following my research on the
history and philosophy of brain function was: 'Where do the functions come from?', i.e.,
what sort of questions do we ask about mind, about human nature? That path led by
stages, marked by publications to which I could refer you, to the reigning psychological
theories of the nineteenth, eighteenth and seventeenth centuries and to the debate on
man's place in nature which we associate with Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel
Wallace, Charles Lyell and the Victorian milieu. It leads on in two interrelated
directions. The first is to the metaphysical foundations of modern science and how the
biological and human sciences tried and failed to follow the rules laid down for the
physical sciences. By this I mean that explanations in terms of purposes, goals and other
analogies to human intention have never been purged from the biological and human sciences
and persist in the concepts of function in psychology and physiology and in functionalism
across a wide range of disciplines, for example, sociology, anthropology, architecture and
metadisciplines such as systems theory.
The second path leads to the historical context of evolutionary theory
and to notions of nature and human nature, of God and adaptation, in the leading
intellectuals of Darwin's time. I am thinking of Thomas Malthus' ratio between arithmetic
and geometrical progressions in population theory, of Darwin's grandfather, Erasmus, who
applied associationist psychology to evolution, to William Paley who sketched a grand
scheme of adaptation drawn from natural theology. Moving further, we find the origin of
the concept of ideology in the French Idéologues, who wished to trace values to roots in
physiology and inspired much work we associate with modern brain research along one trail
and work we associate with political critiques of knowledge along another. The first path
takes us through the history of science and the philosophy of science, while the second
one takes us via Cabanis and Destutt de Tracy to Hegel, Feuerbach, Marx and Engels and on
to Weber and Mannheim and the modern sociology of knowledge. This is the study of how
evaluative categories persist in all thought, including and especially scientific thought,
setting research agendas, defining acceptable terms of reference for explanations and
reminding us of the historicity of our assumptions, which are more basic than the history
of research and findings. This last path brings one full circle so that the theory of
ideology and the sociology of knowledge come to be applied to empirical research
traditions in science
I grant that these are long and complex paths and ones likely to be
unfamiliar to experimental psychologists, but they lead to a convergence of conclusions:
that nature is a societal category and that it is never free from human purposes. If the
most empirical and empiricist scientific research is the carrying out of a research
programme based on certain selected human purposes, then how can it behove us to turn up
our nose at other serious approaches to human values and purposes those of prose
and experiential accounts? My aim in what follows is to broaden the articulations of human
nature into the rest of culture and to deepen them by giving some vignettes to illustrate
current thinking in psychoanalysis ways of thinking about the inner world.
I want now to appeal to the work of the American philosopher, Richard
Rorty, in an effort to open out what we consider psychology the logos of the
psyche to be. In his searching volumes entitled Philosophy and the Mirror of
Nature and Consequences of Pragmatism he challenges traditional notions of
objectivity and scientific method, with the consequence that 'we shall be able to see the
social sciences as continuous with literature as interpreting other people to us,
and thus enlarging and deepening our sense of community' (Consequences of Pragmatism, p.
203). Disciplines like philosophy and science become something other than 'the name of a
natural kind'; instead they are 'just a name of one of the pigeon holes into which
humanistic culture is divided for
administrative and bibliographical purposes (p. 226). If, as he argues, we take seriously
the notion of 'a culture in which the science/literature distinction would no longer
matter' (p. xxii), we can look at other notions of humanity and grant them equal dignity
with those of that discipline we call science. 'No particular notion of culture would be
singled out as exemplifying (or signally failing to exemplify) the condition to which the
rest aspired' (p. xxxviii). Science is then seen as one way of interrogating ourselves and
nature, but we do not find at its foundations the language in which nature speaks to
itself. Rorty argues that 'there is nothing deep down inside us except what we have put
there ourselves, no criterion that we have not created in the course of creating a
practice, no standard of rationality that is not an appeal to such a criterion, no
rigorous argumentation that is not obedience to our own conventions' (p. xlii).
When he turns specifically to the topic of psychoanalysis in his
Northcote Lecture on 'The Contingency of Selfhood', Rorty argues that at the centre of
selfhood lies the human being as 'the creator of metaphor, rather than the contemplator of
literal truth'. Metaphor becomes 'the paradigm of humanity' (London Review 8 May
1986 p. ll). Rorty follows Nietzsche in defining truth as 'a mobile army of metaphors' and
argues that 'the idea of finding a single context for all human lives, should be
abandoned' (ibid.).
He draws on the concept of 'the blind impress all our behavings bear'
from a poem by Philip Larkin. The context is:
And once you have walked the length of your mind, what
You command is as clear as a lading-list.
Anything else must not, for you, be thought
To exist.
And what's the profit? Only that, in time
We half-indentify the blind impress
All our behavings bear, may trace it home.
But to confess,
On that green evening when our death begins,
Just what it was, is hardly satisfying,
Since it applied only to one man once,
And that one dying.
Drawing, as I said, on this concept he says, 'Strong poetry,
common-sense morality, revolutionary morality, normal science, revolutionary science, and
the sort of idiosyncratic fantasy which is intelligible to only one person, are all, from
a Freudian point of view, different ways of dealing with blind impress: or, more
precisely, ways of dealing with different blind impresses impresses which may be
unique to an individual or common to the members of some historically-conditioned
community. None of these strategies is privileged over others in the sense of expressing
human nature better. No such strategy is more or less human than any other, any more than
the pen is more truly a tool than the butcher's knife, or the hybridised orchid less a
flower than the wild rose' (p. 14). Therefore, in the ancient quarrel about whether truth
is made or found, he comes down on the side of the former 'the final victory of
metaphors of self-creation over metaphors of discovery'. We then become 'reconciled' to
the thought that this is the only sort of power over the world which we can hope to have.
For that would be the final abdication of the notion that truth, not just power and pain,
is to be found "out there"' (p. 14).
We have now reached the turning point of my argument. You may have
noticed that I have allied myself with a certain fashionable trend in philosophy and the
philosophy of science one which argues that we cannot privilege knowledge about
natural processes or the methods and assumptions of experimental science over other ways
of knowing. My aim in doing so is to use this position to open the door to the
psychological depths of psychoanalysis. It pleases me to draw on the work of someone who
was a graduate student and taught me when I was an undergraduate studying philosophy and
psychology at Yale. He is now perhaps the most
eminent philosopher writing in English. (It's a pity that he declined the chair in the
philosophy of science at Cambridge which was recently offered to him.)
There are, of course other doors that could be opened a clinical
one or a hermeneutic one. I could mount a case for clinical psychology in a university
curriculum. I think it would be right to do this, but I'm not doing it today. I could also
take you through recent debates which suggest that psychoanalysis could serve as a
paradigm for all knowledge more basic than natural science. That is to say, we could now go down a road with psychoanalysis on
one side and the philosophy of science on the other where Adolf Grünbaum beats up
Jürgen Habermas' claims for psychoanalysis as a preliminary to his attack on Sir Karl
Popper's philosophy of science, in the name of an enlightened empiricism. I mention this
path only to pass it by as tedious and not on my way to where I want to go. Where I want
to go is to a curriculum, to a sense of psychology that is more personal, more worldly,
more in touch with people's lives, experiences, hopes and fears. So to go back.
If my critique of the sufficiency and basic-ness of the natural science
model of psychology is appealing, why do psychologists eschew the most searching method
for looking into the human heart and soul when they teach and do research on human nature?
How do I know it is the most searching method? Three ways. First, I have reflected on the
alternative traditions in psychology and then searched for that will o' the wisp of
natural classifications during nearly three decades. Second, because I found it
profoundly, and I do mean profoundly, helpful with respect to my students, loved ones,
colleagues, friends and myself. I'm speaking, quite precisely, of very lost people whose
lives have been fundamentally changed by psychoanalysis and various psychoanalytic
psychotherapies, including six and a half years of of my own analysis five times a week.
Thirdly, my own research and clinical work beginning in 1955, and currently involving
about thirty hours a week, plus a full programme of reading, researching and editing, lead
to the same conclusions. What I want to speak about now is not these experiences but,
rather, to go back to the problem of natural classification. What kind of account of human
nature is most enlightening and satisfying? What kind of stories ring true? Which ones
that make experiential sense.
How can I bring this alive for you? The first thing I want to say is
very abstruse. When I began my account of the attractions of cerebral localization, I said
that the reigning tradition in research in human nature was one which put things in
spatial terms. I meant spatial terms of localization, as well as conceptual spaces as the
in theory of id, ego and superego, of conscious, pre-conscious and unconscious. It is also true that the language of physiology that
associationism designated as parallel and this has been true throughout the
associationist tradition, especially in the work of Locke, Hume, Hartley and the great
nineteenth century associationists was, in turn, based on a theory of contiguity,
of impact, all founded on the fundamental analogy of a billiard ball universe, however
subtly this has been modified in more recent theories which rely on a proactive rather
than on a reactive model. The theories of proprioception in the nineteenth century
I'm thinking especially of the work of G. H. Lewes could fully accommodate all of
the terms of reference of operant, as opposed to classical, conditioning.
I suppose you may think it a piece of arrogance for me to say that more
recent developments in cognitive psychology, in cybernetics, in computer modelling and
even human ethology and personal construct theory and symbolic interactionism all lie
within this spatial tradition. We could argue about this, but I don't think there would be
much argument over the fact that people's stories biographies, autobiographies,
fiction, narratives, and yarns get short shift in psychology departments in British
universities. We live with the objection that psychology departments don't teach what
people expect them to. But why don't they? Let's ask this question seriously. One answer
is that science advances only where its methods allow it to, and this can lead to some
fairly esoteric experiments. This is surely the basis for sensory-motor theories in
physiology and their representation in brain research. It is the reason for all of those
extraordinarily meticulous studies in the primary sensory modalities, in perception
research, in the memorization of nonsense syllables, in the union of neurophysiological
research with operant conditioning, and so on. Clinical psychology acts as something as a
bridge between these traditions and the kinds of experiences about which I wish to speak.
However, the goal is still one of correlation and quantification. I want to turn to an
entirely different set of parameters those of narrative, of plot, of told lives,
reflected upon in careful and intimate ways. That is, I want to turn to psychoanalysis.
In the 1950's, I spent a period working in a mental hospital, followed
by two years sitting behind a one-way mirror observing psychoanalytic sessions and
attempting to classify the material. I then spent a number of years doing theoretical
reading and playing particular attention to controlled research on dream material. I then
turned, as I've already told you, to attempts to root psychoanalysis in brain research.
All of these were designed to subject the material and concepts of psychoanalysis to
quantitative and semi-quantitative research. I should perhaps also mention that I spent
some time administering psychotropic drugs, worked for a period in electro-convulsive
therapy, lived for a considerable time with a suicidally depressed person and with a
manic- depressive person and have worked for many years in an out-patient department of a
London psychiatric hospital with both individuals and groups, doing assessments as well as
long-term therapy.
When I used to lecture on psychoanalysis in the Cambridge Social and
Political Sciences Tripos I was primarily concerned with metapsychology the most
abstract level of models of the mind, as it happened, in those lectures, with respect to
Freud, Wilhelm Reich and Herbert Marcuse. I tell you this, because my experience of the
last decade or so was, it now occurs to me, on reflection, very little to do with much of
what I then taught. What I have found relevant, interesting and moving in my recent work
is not easy to explain, because it is not about explanation. It is about evocation.
In technical psychoanalytic language, it is about the central role of counter-transference
in clinical work and it turns out in the psychoanalytic theory of learning
and experience. What I work with in my consulting room and in group therapy is very hard
to grasp and then to think about. I find myself feeling things and have to sift them to
find what is being put into me and evoked from the plenum of possible reactions in my
inner world. Quite often it is the patient's need for me to feel not only know about but be taken over by her or his desperation or spite or inability to think.
Wilfred Bion says somewhere that analysts wouldn't make good generals because they find it
so hard to think under fire. That is what I'm trying desperately to do to think while I'm being nearly overwhelmed by something unconscious which is being conveyed, usually not
stated.
There is, as some of you will know, a burgeoning literature on
counter-transference. In classical psychoanalysis it was something to be purged in order
to provide a smooth mirror for the patient's projections in the transference relationship.
But many of the most gifted analysts especially Independent Group and Kleinians
ones have come to trust it more and more and make it the basis of
interpretive work.
Having survived the patients assault on thinking and linking, one
then has to find a way of interpreting the experience in a useful way. This can be tough,
for example, if the patient is making you
sleepy, impotent, stupid, violently angry, turned on, hungry, claustrophobic, manic or
especially hopeless. I must stress that the experience has the quality of
coming from within of being mine. The discipline lies in interrogating oneself to
learn what the dynamic has been- to interpret the counter-transference. It
is always deeply interactive, dialectical; I/thou, never I/you or I/it (unless reification
is the message).
I had a patient who spent months on the threshold of therapy
sometimes standing at the threshold of the consulting room door. It was an early training
case, and it took me a long time to realise that his message was his not just my
insecurity, but a way of making me inward with his own vertiginous feelings, the imminent
need to flee that was characteristic of his panic attacks. In another early training case
I was made to feel drained, depleted, the way my patient felt when her mother who
had always been preoccupied when my patient was a child used her up and got the
daughter to mother her. Yet another used me as a memory bank and denied any reference to
things I'd quoted from her own stories, so that I felt estranged from her memory, just as
she did, while serving in the very role of linking her experiences when she could not bear
to. She had a mother who put nasty feelings into her while refusing to accept my patient's
projections and look after and detoxify them. In all of these cases, the task is to bear
and contain the experience, holding on to it until the patient can stand to take it back,
hopefully in a bearable form. One does not only 'look after' the feelings. One has them.
My next example comes from a classical psychoanalytic topic, that of
parapraxes or 'Freudian slips'. Sometimes a patient's unconscious will dramatically
advance the therapeutic alliance. I have a patient who has just begun three times per week
psychotherapy. He is ever so willing and co-operative. He turns up on time, tells me his
dreams, confirms my interpretations with, 'I dare say'; 'That may well be so'; 'I have to
allow for that possibility', but I don't feel we're getting anywhere at all. He's affable,
willing. Two weeks ago I gave him his first monthly account. He offered to pay on the
spot. At the start of the next session he gave me an envelope saying, 'I thought of
posting this, but I realised it would get here quicker if I brought it'. He proceeded to
get down to some serious co-operating a dream he'd written down over the weekend.
The envelope was on my lap. My eye fell on it. My name was misspelled, my house number was
wrong and the postcode was also mistaken. I mentioned these facts and said that perhaps he
wanted me to know that he was not what he seemed. Indeed, his whole story of himself and
his family felt like a facade, though I didn't say this. I thereupon opened the envelope
and found the cheque post-dated by a month. So perhaps he's not as grateful as he seems,
either, or as keen to get the money to me as soon as possible.
All this was, of course, quite unconscious. He protested he'd written
it in a hurry and brought it to save time. What he had told me as clearly as
he could was that his co-operativeness was a defence. He also told me in that session and
for the first time, some authentic, highly significant and painful material about his
family relationships. These allowed us to connect to material based in the here and now of
the session, rather than reported incidents about certain areas of his unconscious where
he suffers from brittle and highly punitive guilt, so much so that he has a tendency to
banish people from his life. He had presented me with an envelope displaying unequivocal
evidence of his deviousness, ingratitude and false self.
One of the areas in which recent developments in Kleinian
psychoanalysis have borne considerable fruit on a broad scale is that of projective
mechanisms. I should like to give two examples of these and then to generalize them. The
first is from the clinical work of a remarkable psychoanalyst, Arthur Hyatt-Williams, who
has spent much of his career working with murderers. He tells of a patient who, because of
someone's carelessness, had lost an eye as a child. During the days that preceded the
murder, which happened many years after the accident, he had a temporary job replacing
cats eyes on a main road. The mother of the young woman whom he wanted to marry had
recently managed to estrange her daughter from him and had forbidden her ever to see him
again. Coming back from work by train, the patient found himself alone in a compartment
with a woman whom he experienced and saw as the mother of his beloved. When he begged her
to change her mind about her daughter, she obviously said she knew nothing about it and
was a stranger to him. He then became totally enraged with her, and the discussion became
more of a row. He experienced hatred which became more and more murderous until he killed
her with a knife the very knife that he used to dig out the cat's eyes which he had
to replace on the highway. This was a clear reference to the accident that had caused the
loss of his eye when he was a child. He had total amnesia both of the murder and of the
symbolic equation which had taken place. Hyatt Williams draws on the work of Wilfred Bion
to say that in his distress the patient had evacuated with his eyes the unbearable image
of the woman who had stolen his beloved from him and had stolen the apple of his eyes. He
evacuated the persecutory object into an unknown woman who had perhaps a slight
resemblance with his potential mother-in-law. In this way he attempted to obliterate the
source of persecution. In this instance the patient had psychotically used his eyes not as
a receptive organ but as an organ of projection. (Hyatt Williams, 'Kleinian Work - Post
Kleinian Work', p. 9.)
I draw another example this time of projective processes in
social settings from the work of Tom Main. He says that 'In simple projection (a
defence mechanism) the receiver may notice that he is not being treated as himself but as
an aggressive other. In projective identification (an unconscious phantasy) this other may
find himself forced by the projector actually to feel and own the projected aggressive
qualities and impulses which are otherwise alien to him. He will feel strange and
uncomfortable and may resent what is happening, but in the face of the projector's
weakness and cowardice it may be doubly difficult to resist the feeling of superiority and
aggressive power steadily forced into him. Such disturbances affect all pair relationships
more or less. A wife, for instance, may force her husband to own feared and unwanted
aggressive and dominating aspects of herself and will then fear and respect him. He in
turn may come to feel aggressive and domineering towards her, not only because of his own
resources but of hers which are forced into him. But more; for reasons of his own he may
despise and disown certain timid aspects of his personality and by projective
identification force these into his wife and despise her accordingly. She may thus be left
not only with timid unaggressive parts of herself but having in addition to contain his.
Certain pairs come to live in such locked systems, dominated by mutual projective
phantasies with each not truly married to but rather to unwanted split-off and projected
parts of themselves. Both the husband, dominant and cruel, and the wife, stupidly timid
and respectful, may be miserably unhappy with themselves and with each other, yet such
marriages although turbulent are stable, because each partner needs the other for
pathological narcissistic purposes. (Main, 'Large Groups', pp. 57-8)
I trust that it will be obvious that this model of projection, taken up
and owned by the process of evocation and identification and then reprojected, has
considerable potential for the understanding of how groups and subgroups treat one
another, say, in a university department or laboratory; how tendencies in academic or
clinical disciplines behave towards one another, for example, in the battles of
schools in psychology and social science and the battles of tendencies or
groups in psychoanalysis. Moreover, these processes can be seen to be importantly at work
in racial prejudice and international affairs. I'm thinking of the ways in which people
split-off disowned or forbidden parts of themselves and put them into the Other
whether the Other be a small group, a tendency, a racial group or another nation
and then find justification in the behaviour of the recipient of the projection when that
recipient whether individual or group of any size lives up to the projected
expectations. And so it goes in endless projective and reprojective loops.
I have a patient who had an unresponsive, preoccupied mother (the one
mentioned earlier) who unconsciously put all of her own nasty feelings into the daughter
who now acts as the custodian of these and spews them out into the world. In a recent
session she filled the room so full with expressions of disgust that she experienced
herself as disgusting. Since there was no space in the room she had not filled with her
spew, she fled, lest she have to consume her own vomit, i.e., reintroject these violent
projections.
I want now to say something more general. In my opinion the works of
Donald Winnicott, Melanie Klein and Wilfred Bion offer the potential of a profound,
alimentary view of human nature, of epistemology and of culture. Although their writings
are not always mutually consistent and although the systematic exploration of these ideas
is in an early state, a number of people feel that they have wide applications for how we
think of ourselves, of culture, of knowledge and especially of science.
Let me begin by speaking about something with which many of you will be
familiar: the theory of transitional objects and transitional phenomena of Winnicott. In
two papers in the early 1950's and expanded in a book, Playing and Reality, he drew
attention to the profound significance of the child's first 'not-me', which often takes
the form of a blanket, a bit of rag, a teddy bear, but it can equally be a thumb, a shadow
or the mother herself. What is important about this object is that it is neither objective
nor subjective but partakes of both. Winnicott describes the role of transitional objects
and their gradual relinquishment very movingly.
In the course of his analysis of the concept, he indicates an envelope
and points out that within this space, many other phenomena, including those of play,
culture, religion and science itself are pursued. Ive reflected elsewhere on the
implications of this view for the philosophy of science and for a theory of culture which
articulates with the ideas of Wilfred Bion. The essence of Bion's thinking is that the
primitive is never transcended. Reverting for
a moment to Winnicott's ideas, this means that transitional phenomena persists into adult
life, not only in the broadly-defined domain of culture but also in the ways in which we
relate sensuously to design, to clothes and in my view especially to the
highly enfolding experiences associated with high-fidelity, personal stereos, saunas,
steam baths and the phenomena of the Body Shop. Mountain bikes and Porshes are in the same
emotional domain boys and their toys.
Bion has proposed an alimentary theory of knowledge, whereby we
unconsciously continue to mediate all experience through the mother's body. Rather than
analysing experience in Lockean terms such as sensation, perception, association and
ideas, Bion refers to elements which can either be metabolized or are threatening and have
to be batted away. The experiences can either be food for thought which can be digested,
or poisons. We can learn from experience, or we can avoid doing so: we can attack linking,
i.e., the connectedness of experience. Anxiety and psychic pain, if tolerated, can find a
meaning and bear the potential to be modified and for psychic development to occur. On the
other hand, when psychic pain is evaded, experience cannot be digested and can continue to
be a problem or danger or both (Hyatt Williams, p. 5). Other aspects of the alimentary
theory of knowledge and experience have to do with what we can take in and hold, what we
push out and through which orifices and sense organs; the function of psychic skin and
second skin; the phenomena of splitting and part-object relations and other dimensions
modelled on the symbolism of the digestive tract.
My argument is that there is an important place in the human sciences
for these modes of thinking about human nature. They are not spatial or even about
conceptual spaces. They are experiential stories with narrative structures, layered
meanings. They communicate by evocation, symbolism, metaphors, associations. Furthermore,
I think that such stories articulate with other studies of primitive mechanisms and group
processes so that it behoves us to rethink the categories of psychology, family and social
processes, and the public world in these terms. It also seems to me that, following Rorty,
we should draw into the human sciences disciplines such as biography and social history. I
am thinking, in particular, of the rich light shed on human nature by classical work such
as Victor Wolfenstein's psychobiography of Malcom X, The Victims of Democracy, and
the illumination which that work gives to the phenomena of charismatic leadership and of
racism. The same can be said of Maynard Solomon's psychobiography of Beethoven and John
Sutherland's forthcoming biography of Ronald Fairbairn, Fairbairns Journey into
the Interior, in which Fairbairn's creative contributions to object relations theory
in psychoanalysis are integrated with a detailed understanding of his psychopathology.
Phyllis Grosskurth's biography of Melanie Klein is a flawed example of the same genre.
My argument is that if we cease to believe that we are speaking the
language which nature uses to speak to itself, we open out our sense of disciplined
inquiry and use other methods, including those of the psychoanalyst, the biographer, the
student of culture. Psychology, social psychology, sociology and anthropology become
humanistic studies and are thereby enriched by their articulations rather than drawing
ever-closer the lines of demarcation between disciplines.
I do not wish to be heard to be speaking against brain and bahaviour
research or any other discipline or sub-discipline in the human sciences. I do wish to
say, however, that we impoverish our understanding of our humanity if we erect a criterion
of scientificity which so blinkers us that we cannot complement the spatial with the
evocative and thereby cannot even, to recall Phillip Larkin's words, 'half identify the
blind impress all our behavings bear'.
This is the text of a talk presented to the Zangwill Club at the Department of
Experimental Psychology, Cambridge University, February 1989.
Copyright: The Author
Address for Correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|