Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social
Theory
by J. W. Burrow. Cambridge University Press. 45s.
Reviewed by Robert M. Young
Social man came to be seen as subservient to the laws of nature by
a very circuitous route, and the hiatus which remains between the biological and social
sciences reflects continuing uncertainties about man's place in nature. In the late
nineteenth century a facade was erected which made it appear that the theory of evolution
provided the necessary conceptual framework for a biological science of man. John Burrow
has made a very important analysis of the history of ideas in this period which shows
convincingly that evolutionary social theory was not in fact a direct extension of
Darwinism to the study of "advanced" and "primitive" societies but
that the invocation of evolution was a symptom of "the confrontation of the ideas
characteristic of philosophic radicalism with realities and systems of ideas which they
were inadequate to comprehend" (99). Evolutionary social theory appeared to provide a
new basis for believing in the essential unity of mankind and for retaining the
troublesome normative aspects of conjectural history and philosophic radicalism while
abandoning choice and artificial sanctions. Evolution forgave the "primitive"
his irrational customs and promised Utopia to all, in due course, by the simple
expedient of "the temporalization of Natural Laws" (272): "what has been
ought (broadly speaking) to have been and what ought to be, will be" (273). In short,
by the end of the century evolution was seen as equivalent to progress, and social theory
could again be unified with moral and political theory.The main strength of the book lies in the juxtaposition of traditions
in historical scholarship which have hitherto been kept in separate compartments
history of anthropology and history of political thought. Burrow shows in detail how much
the development of the former owed to the latter. In particular, he draws on the work of
Duncan Forbes on the Scottish Enlightenment, provides an alternative to the views of Elie
Halévy and Leslie Stephen on philosophical radicalism, and relates these to the work of
three evolutionary social theorists: Sir Henry
Maine, Herbert
Spencer, and E. B.
Tylor. What about Darwin? There are two historical issues here. First, recent
developments in the social sciences have led to a reinterpretation of the histories of
modern sociology and anthropology. The evolutionary tradition has been repudiated and the
organic analogy has largely been abandoned. Since the history of science is the most
Whiggish history there is, the social scientists have dutifully set about rewriting their
historical textbooks. For example, Tylor's use of the "doctrine of survivals" to
account for "primitive" customs as equivalent to evolutionary vestiges a
sort of collection of social vermiform appendixes is now seen as useless
question-begging. His evolutionary language was yet another excuse for identifying the
customs of exotic societies as harmful superstitions which Tylor wanted to mark out for
destruction (258). More recently still, functionalism itself has come under fire. The
second historical issue is Burrow's argument that the social scientists were right to
re-interpret their history. In the nineteenth century Darwin was invoked as a magic
password for a science of man. Burrow attempts to show that Darwin "was certainly not
the father of evolutionary anthropology, but possibly he was its wealthy uncle" (114)
and that he was far away when the cradle of evolutionary social theory was being prepared
(100).
He makes out a very good case, but there are at least three things
wrong with it. First, Burrow has set up the problem as a rather simple dichotomy. He
emphasizes the influence of conjectural history, utilitarianism, German historiography,
comparative philology, and uniformitarian geology; these are placed in one pan and
considerably outweigh Darwin. Of course they do, but the way in which Burrow formulates
the problem obscures the fact that these influences were themselves important in the
development of evolutionary biology. They were part of a common tradition. For example,
Locke and Hartley provided the basic assumptions for the evolutionary theories of Erasmus
Darwin and Herbert Spencer. Charles Darwin's debts to Paley, Lyell, and Malthus cannot be
divorced from the mainstream of the empiricist tradition in English thought. One suspects
that this structural weakness in Burrow's argument is a consequence of a fundamental
conceptual muddle which he took over from Talcott Parsons and Lord Annan the belief
in "the positivist tradition," which Annan identifies with Hobbes, Locke,
Newton, Hume, and so on and calls "the most consistently powerful intellectual
movement in England" over two centuries. I cannot say how much violence this
simplistic conception does to the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, but in the
nineteenth century it is certainly necessary to distinguish the empiricist tradition from
several themes within it: naturalism, associationism, empiricist epistemology, empirical
methodology, and the idea of progress. These are all related to, but separable from, the
specifically nineteenth-century movement called positivism which is associated (in whole
or in part) with the names of Comte, J. S. Mill, G. H. Lewes. Herbert Spencer, and T. H.
Huxley. To let "positivism" stand for all these in the interpretive portions of
the text hopelessly obscures the issues which Burrow has so intelligently raised. He seems
to see this at some points in the text (e.g., pp. 1, 111, 156), but it is littered with
ambiguities (and some crudities) which appear to depend on this vague, anachronistic
concept. For example, the claim that man is a part of nature and therefore subject to law
is called "the authentic voice of mid-Victorian positivism"; Benthamism is
called an older version of positivism (129); evolutionary social theory is a subspecies of
positivism (102), and Engels' Marxism is a subspecies of that (101). On this reckoning the
views of both LaMettrie and Francis Crick on religion should be labelled "the
authentic voice of mid twentieth-century molecular biology".
If these criticisms are fair, it follows that the author's analytic
tools are bound to be too blunt to dissect successfully the intellectual allegiances of
Maine, Tylor, and Spencer. I found these chapters disappointing, while the case study of
The Anthropological Society of London (Ch. 4) was much less marred and provided strong
evidence for Burrow's general thesis. On the other hand, the chapter on Spencer's
intellectual development revealed the weaknesses very clearly. Laissez-faire economics,
the idea of progress, and phrenology provided the basis for the social theory in Social
Statics (1851), and this, as Spencer tells us in the second edition, contained the
earliest foreshadowing of his general theory of evolution. However, after he wrote his
first book, associationism intervened decisively through the influence of Lewes and J. S.
Mill and provided the basis for the evolutionary theory which underlay his Principles
of Psychology (1855). These themes were integrated and generalized in First
Principles (1862) and reapplied to social and moral problems in his later works. To
mix quotations from Social Statics and The Principles of Ethics (1879-93)
helps to show the unifying themes in Spencer's thought while it obscures the important differences between his pre- and post-evolutionary writings.In my opinion, Evolution and Society is seriously flawed.
Nevertheless, I have read only two books on the development of ideas about man's place in
nature which were as consistently absorbing and stimulating: The Great Chain of Being and The Growth of Philosophic
Radicalism. Although Burrow's ability to provide elegant
and succinct generalizations sometimes helps to obscure the issues, his style is the best
of the three. The issues which he has raised must now be integrated with the history of
evolutionary theory in biology and psychology. I understand that Dr Burrow is now at work
on another topic in the history of ideas. I have seen this book on several reading lists
in Cambridge, and I for one wish that he would carry this research further and that he was
here to continue to teach us about evolution and society. This review appeared in Cambridge Review 10 June 1967, pp
409-11.Copyright: The Author
Address for Correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|