SCHOLARSHIP AND THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIOURAL SCIENCES
ROBERT M. YOUNG, Cambridge
University
In the last few years, studies in a number of related fields have achieved a kind of
coherence-and even status-as a scholarly discipline which has come to be called 'history
of the behavioural sciences'. But it is not yet clear just what sort of discipline this is
or what sort of status it merits. It is something like the history of medicine in that its
domain, its practitioners, and its standards are very differently conceived and evaluated
in different quarters. Neither the parent sciences nor the history of science have been
very enthusiastic in fostering this development. This article is an attempt first to
review some recent publications in the field and then to consider the ways in which
professional historians of science and students of the history of the behavioural sciences
can benefit from a greater awareness of one another's activities.The last three years has seen the publication of four general works in the history of
psychology.[1] The autobiography and selected papers of Professor Edwin G. Boring, the
doyen of the field, have also appeared, and he has co-edited a valuable collection of
readings.[2] Finally, since interest and activity in this field of research have reached a
level which justifies a specialist periodical, the Journal of the history of the
behavioral sciences began publication in January, 1965.The editorship of this journal shows that the domain of 'history of the behavioural
sciences' is much wider than psychology itself. It has editors in psychology, neurology;
neurophysiology, psychiatry, psychoanalysis, sociology, anthropology, and history, for
since psychology grew historically out of philosophy, medicine and biology, the boundaries
of the history of the behavioural sciences cannot be firmly fixed. The two main links of
the discipline with traditional science are through the evolutionary continuity of man
with lower organisms and through the fact that the brain is the organ of the mind. Given
these two principles, the catchment area of research in this field is vast. Indeed, if we
restrict ourselves only to works listed in the history of psychology, we find that the Psychological
index and Psychological abstracts had over 328,000 entries between 1894 and 1958. If
we complemented this with similar listings from related fields, we should have some
conception of the wide range of interests represented. The aim of the present review is
not to attempt anything like a comprehensive history of recent work in all these fields,
but to discuss a few books and articles and to consider the light which these throw on the
state of scholarship in this rather nebulously-bounded field.As Watson points out in his preface to The great psychologists: "The
history of psychology from the period of the pre-Socratic Greeks through the Middle Ages
has not been examined for over fifty years". The history of psychology from the
renaissance to the 19th century is less neglected, while the 19th and 20th centuries have
received most attention. Meanwhile scholars in other fields have brought to light new
materials and new interpretations. Watson has in this book attempted a one-volume history
of psychology from Thales to J. B. Watson, which takes account of this research. He has
read much more widely in the secondary literature of the histories of science and
philosophy than his predecessors, and this allows him to make a greater number of
references to the biographies and intellectual contexts of the 'great psychologists'.
Unfortunately he has not referred as often to the primary sources as to these general
works and is therefore at the mercy of authorities whose opinions he usually reproduces
without comment or qualification. There are two obvious ways out of this difficulty. The
first is to undertake new research in the primary literature. In a work of wide scope,
this could be only partially achieved. The alternative is to draw on detailed studies in
the periodical literature. The author could have done this with respect to the histories
of philosophy, science and medicine. But, with rare exceptions, in the history of
psychology the requisite detailed studies do not exist. Indeed Watson largely conceived
and now edits the first journal which is designed to provide an outlet for the studies on
which a general work of this sort necessarily depends. There is therefore no way out of
the inadequacies of this survey but to undertake new research.As its title implies, The great psychologists is based on the 'great man' theory
of history. I must confess that I am so unsympathetic to this view that I cannot abide by
the injunction to evaluate a book in terms of its author's aims. Watson says: "In
emphasising the 'brilliant steps forward' of a few great psychologists, therefore, I have
had to neglect the work of many others who contributed to the steady advance of the field.
A chapter on the work of one man in comparison to a hundred years dismissed in a few
pages, serves as an inevitable, but necessary distortion of history". This is, of
course, the 'whom to worship?' view of the history of science, and its limitations have
been very effectively criticised in a recent monograph by Agassi.[3] Undoubtedly an
important part of the historian's task is to identify the main contributions to his field.
Similarly, he is interested in the biography and intellectual development of important
figures. But having found the ideas and those who have, made important contributions to
their development, he must present and critically examine them. Above all he must consider
their historical development. If the worship of men gets in the way of the history of
scientific ideas, then one would rather see interesting biographical material sacrificed
than to undermine the study of the history of science itself. It would be a radical and
retrograde step to separate biography and intellectual development from the history of
scientific ideas, but a surgical separation of these approaches would be preferable to
hero worship.Watson's plan provides us with extremely interesting biographical essays, but the logic
of problems cannot conform to a 'great man' treatment. He tacitly admits this in his later
chapters, where he is in greater control of his materials: from Fechner onwards he departs
increasingly from his programme. Even so the fundamental plan of the work prevents any
sense of science as a community activity involving traditions, persistent problems and
assumptions, and multiple influences. A sense of the continuity of history is
sorely lacking. Influences are mentioned retrospectively, but not prospectively. An
Alexandrian physician (p. 76) and Spinoza (p. 159) have a "modern ring".
Conversely, later views are sometimes said to be reminiscent of earlier ones. These
statements may exemplify the principle of association of ideas, but they are not helpful
to the historian unless their meaning is analysed in some detail. Above all they fail to
respect the way problems were seen at the time, and the whole approach falsifies the way
history actually happened.The chapters on Greek, Roman and mediaeval psychology suffer from incomplete mastery of
the primary sources, and the footnotes confirm the impression one derives from the text.
It is the chapter on Descartes that provides the first convincing evidence of original
research and independent judgment. The remainder of the book covers familiar-one might say
too familiar-ground, except for the chapter on J. B. Watson, whose shadow is cast over all
current research in psychology. The author gives us the poignant story of J. B. Watson's
later life, after a scandal in his private affairs had led to his dismissal from his chair
at Johns Hopkins and he was unable to get an academic post anywhere else. The discussion
of J. B. Watson's scientific work is also among the best chapters in the book. The
bibliography, though impressive, is marred by inconvenient organisation, lack of page
references, and citations which are often incomplete.Rather than make detailed criticisms (e.g. a confusion about Aristotle's doctrine of
four causes, p. 50), I should like to ask why such prodigious effort has produced such a
disappointing result. In fairness one should stress that this book was initially intended
as a popular account of the history of psychology, and that its aims changed while it was
being written. As a result a book which had been intended for laymen and undergraduates
became, under the author's hand, a work of serious scholarship. Nevertheless one finds
that the discussion is too often cut off as soon as complexities arise; exciting men and
issues become pale and flat. This is true even of the author's rather sanguine treatment
of Freud. The reason most decidedly is not to be found in any failure of care, competence
or dedication of the author. Rather, this book is. symptomatic of the shortcomings of the
history of psychology as it has been written by psychologists in the last four decades. In
a way it is the inevitable result of a number of attitudes and practices which the present
writer hopes that this review may bring under scrutiny. It will quite properly be objected
that I have said that this book should not have been attempted, or, if attempted, should
have been done along entirely different lines. In fact, I understand that Professor Watson
is at work on a book based on trends, not men. For reasons given in this article, I do not
believe that such a book can be successful in the present state of our knowledge. The
obvious question which will be asked about The great psychologists is whether or
not it should be classed with Brett, Boring, and Murphy as a standard general treatment.
The short answer must be 'no', but it should be remembered that the author never intended
that it should be such. A more considered reply would be that the question is
misconceived. It will be some time before the research has been conducted which will make
it feasible to attempt a survey of the history of psychology, unless one is prepared to
continue indefinitely to accept works based on a wholly inadequate corpus of scholarship.
Watson's book must therefore stand as an important justification for the journal which he
now edits. In 1929 Boring remarked sadly that in experimental psychology "The habit
of writing complete text-books in the face of incomplete knowledge still persists".4
This might well serve as a text or injunction in the history of psychology in the present.
Before concluding my remarks on this book, I should stress that one can learn a great
deal from Watson's treatment. My review copy contains many more underlinings and notes for
future reference than indications of the book's shortcomings.5
A short history of British psychology by L. S. Hearnshaw is in some respects the
opposite of Watson's book. Its scope is restricted to British work between 1840 and 1940,
and it is based on a wide reading of primary sources and refrains from perpetuating the
dubious judgments of other commentators, so that it is almost wholly original and is in
fact the only recent study written without heavy reliance on the work of Boring. The
author's aims are modest: "This short history is intended for the general reader as
well as for students of psychology. It is only an outline, and aims in the first place to
bring out broad trends rather than to introduce an excessive load of minute and technical
detail. Enough detail has, I hope, been included to give the book some substance without
being unduly specialised".This is not primarily a history of scientific ideas. Like Watson, Hearnshaw is more
concerned with the importance of men than with the nature of their thought. The book is
written in the form of a series of independent essays of varying lengths: biographical and
intellectual sketches of men and milieux. Although these include lucid critical essays on
Ward, Stout, McDougall and Spearman, one feels that his treatment is usually
insufficiently expository or insufficiently analytical. Hearnshaw is at his best in
discussing the development of the discipline of psychology: societies, fashions,
legislation. It has been said by those who know certain events intimately that he often
errs in matters of detail, nuance and interpretation, but it remains true that he has
provided the most complete account of the profession of psychology in Britain that has
been published. The topical chapters dealing with aspects of psychology related to social
history-social, abnormal and applied psychology are extremely informative, although the
discussions of philosophical matters are less successful.The national restriction allows treatment of some figures whose work is regularly-and
often wrongly-ignored in more general works: William Carpenter, Thomas Laycock, Henry
Maudsley, George H. Lewes, Hughlings Jackson, David Ferrier, H. C. Bastian, Henry Head and
Sir John Lubbock. The introduction of the se and other names into the secondary literature
is one of the main merits of the book. When coupled with Hearnshaw's charming style, each
of his brief essays invites further study. The selected bibliography provides an excellent
introduction to the relevant literature, and one hopes that this book will serve as an
invitation to others to conduct the sort of detailed, circumscribed studies on which the
future of the study of the history of psychology depends.George A. Miller's Psychology: the science of mental life is a modest work of a
different sort. It is an introductory science textbook which treats the subject
historically. He considers topics in the historical order in which they became interesting
and alternates these with biographical essays on Wundt, James, Galton, Pavlov, Freud and
Binet. The book makes no claim to scholarly originality and, as the author acknowledges in
his dedication and preface, it owes heavy debts to Boring for information, encouragement
and criticism. The merits of the book lie in its clarity and in the encouragement which it
may provide to students to pursue historical issues more seriously.Psychology in the making poses special problems for the reviewer. Its sub-title is
misleading: "Histories of Selected Research Problems". Its avowed approach is
that of a series of case histories. Yet the book is neither history nor case studies if
one considers the standard set by Conant's Harvard case histories in experimental
science. Instead we have a collection of extremely interesting review articles which
extend further back in time than is usual. These were composed by a "group of faculty
members of the Department of Psychology at Berkeley who found that they shared an interest
in the historical development of psychological ideas". In order to discuss its
contents here, it will be necessary to defer treatment of one of the most interesting
features of this book: the fact that its authors were under the impression that they were
indulging their interests in "the historical development of psychological
ideas". For the result is an excellent example of the uncertainty about just what
historical scholarship is, which will be discussed below. In particular, the first
chapter, "Some Guides to the Understanding of the History of Psychology",
provides ample evidence for the conclusion that the aims of historical studies in this
field are not at all clearly defined.The chapter on "Cortical Localization of Function" is the only one which
attempts to follow the case-history method and shows conclusively that there is no further
need for articles on cerebral localization which survey developments solely in terms of
the work of Gall, Flourens, Broca, Jackson, Fritsch and Hitzig, Bartholow, Ferrier,
Sherrington, Franz, Lashley and Penfield. Thanks to at least a dozen more or less
interchangeable accounts,[6] we know enough about this over-simplified view of the history
of cerebral localization. Further research should deepen our understanding of individual
figures and broaden the scope of inquiry to include others. In the nineteenth century
cerebral localization became the focus of the problems of relating mind to brain and of
finding a catalogue of functions which could integrate subjective life, physiology, and
the biological study of adaptation. It remains an important topic and deserves new
research, whereas in the past decade articles on this subject have degenerated into
story-telling of the venerable tale.The remaining chapters, though certainly not history, provide very interesting
materials for the future historian. As such they are more valuable than surveys which
merely repeat old knowledge and undertake no new research. Each of the contributors has
presented a review of a circumscribed problem on which he is engaged in active research.
Each chapter is based on a close study of a number of primary sources, usually, beginning
the first experimental work on the problem. References to pre-experimental writing
(except, perhaps, in the case of Hochberg on perception) are desultory and unenlightening.
Since the book is a collection of essays with no unifying theme, the chapters will be
considered in turn.[7]G. McClearn on the inheritance of behaviour is extremely disappointing. There are no
details about the eighteenth-century debate, and the narrative jumps from Linnaeus to a
very crude presentation of Lamarck.8 Erasmus Darwin is ignored, and Herbert Spencer is
mentioned only in passing, although these two provided important contributions to the
history of assumptions on the matter. There is insufficient stress on the significance of
the change in Darwin's views from belief in natural selection to use-inheritance, although
this issue is crucial for psychology. The author has missed an important opportunity to
consider the debate on this issue between 1855 and 1900 in the writings of Spencer,
Darwin, Wallace and Romanes, among others, even though two of the principals have provided
excellent guides to the controversy.[9] Instead of availing himself of an opportunity to
contribute original research, the author provides a lengthy summary of classical
genetics-information which is obtainable in any elementary textbook. The same is true of
his discussion of the intelligence quotient (IQ) and mental defects, as well as his
presentation of the oft-told tale of the Jukes and the Kallikaks.In his discussion of nativism and empiricism in perception, J. E. Hochberg has paid
more careful attention to earlier works. He provides an adequate exposition of Berkeley,
but one still finds evidence of insufficient familiarity with the issues. Locke's theory of
ideas is referred to as "this materialist philosophy" (p. 259), and the
concept of reflex is applied to Descartes without the qualifications necessary to guard
against anachronism (p. 272). James Mill is presented from the 1869 edition, which had
been greatly altered by his son and Bain forty years after the original appeared. The
discussion of the empiricists and associationists on perception is superficial, and these
early sections are written in the style of a bed-time story. The exposition becomes
patronising with Helmholtz, but this is followed by a careful review of a number of
Gestalt experiments. The remainder of the chapter is mainly concerned with perception of
depth or space and is serious and competent. Hochberg argues that the progress of research
has finally made the nature-nurture dichotomy passé (pp. 317-326). He considers the work
before about, 1950 devoid of "full-fledged psychophysical research in human and
animal space perception..."When the study of the history of utilitarianism and hedonism comes to consider the
behavioural theories which were their heirs in experimental psychology, two papers of Leo
Postman (who also edited the whole volume) will provide important materials: his chapter
on rewards and punishments in human learning and his earlier article on the history and
present status of the law of effect.[10] These studies are complemented by an earlier
review by Waters [11] and can be connected with the nineteenth-century British tradition
by reference to Cason, [12] whose study extends back to the theories of Spencer, Bain and
J. M. Baldwin. In this chapter Postman ignores everything written before 1898. We are told
only that "Philosophical discussions of rewards and punishments as regulators of
human conduct have had a long and time-honoured history". (p. 331). We are provided
with an excellent exposition of the classical work of E. L. Thorndike and a close analysis
of selected experiments which influenced the subsequent vicissitudes of his theory, but
Postman devotes less attention to work based on the conditioning paradigm, and a future
historian will need to look further into the work of Skinner on reinforcement and operant
conditioning. He will also need to concern himself with the extensive literature on the
conditioning of verbal behaviour, which has itself recently led to the establishment of
yet another specialist journal.[13]The contribution by D. A. Riley is concerned with work on memory of form. He begins
with the experiments of Friedrich Wulf (1922) and then discusses subsequent
research in the light of Wulf's Gestalt view. (For earlier work a beginning may be made by
consulting the, useful historical compilation of Gomulicki.[14]) A reading of Riley's
meticulous exposition and analysis of experiments bearing on Wulf's theory should help any
layman to develop a very healthy respect for the special problems of experimental control
and isolation of significant variables in psychological research. The particular issue is
one of the least complex in psychology, but the myriad interpretations and objections to
each experiment show just how difficult it is to do science about matters which are
concerned with subjective meaning. Of all the chapters in the book Riley's is the most
limited in scope, but I found it very cogently argued and consistently absorbing in spite
of its initially unpromising subject.After devoting only five pages to the period between Plato and 1890, R. D. Tuddenham
tells a fascinating story of work on the nature and measurement of intelligence. His
account is a clear testimony to the need for new categories of analysis in psychology to
replace the ones inherited from philosophical psychology-reason, memory, imagination,
judgment, etc. The least promising category seems to be the one under review: general
intelligence. The catalogues produced by the multiple factor analysts have the merit of
having been subjected to empirical testing, but the ever-growing list of so-called 'basic
mental abilities' suggests that psychology is still far from having an agreed set of basic
units. Three references are given, which list 59, 40, and 120 basic abilities
respectively. This makes the position of physics enviable, no matter how its table of
fundamental particles grows, while the periodic table of elements of the chemists seems a
very distant analogy indeed. Philosophers must help psychologists to decide if this is a
purely empirical problem or an aspect of a more general issue in the biological sciences,
whereby the analysis of functions may never produce a fixed, final set of variables for
the interpretation of the adaptation of organisms to their environments. Tuddenham touches
on this issue in his concluding remarks. He makes the premise. "that intelligence is
not an entity, nor even a dimension in a person, but rather an evaluation of
a behavior sequence (or the average of any such), from the point of view of its adaptive
adequacy. What constitutes intelligence depends upon what the situation demands, though we
add precision (along with bits of anthropocentrism) by restricting the term to evaluation
of behavior involving the manipulation of symbols" (p. 517).In their discussion of repression, D. W. MacKinnon and W. F. Dukes begin with an
elementary and rather uncritical exposition of Freud. It is surprising to find Rapaport's
classical review of work on Emotions and memory missing from their
discussion and their bibliography; experiments on repression was one of his chief
concerns.[15] Nevertheless MacKinnon and Duke provide an informative study of attempts to
bring repression ("the foundation stone of the psychoanalytic theory") into the
laboratory over the protests of the psychoanalysts. It appears that the topic became
experimentally respectable by changing its name to "perceptual defence" and then
being purged of its defence aspect (p. 273). Attempts are being made to reunite recent
experiments with their psychoanalytic forbears (pp. 730-731). The final chapter by T. R.
Sarbin considers attempts to understand hypnotic phenomena. Its heavy reliance on
secondary sources[16] reminds one that what has been interesting in this volume is not its
historical content but the material it provides for a future historian. Thus Sarbin
provides a useful exposition of Braid's work, but one is more interested in his own
advocacy of the "social-psychological" nature of hypnotic phenomena.The illuminating treatments of the literature given in the chapters of Psychology in
the making are valuable and interesting in themselves. From an historical point of
view, however, their utility lies in the evidence they provide to help one to understand
how active research workers saw these problems in the mid-twentieth century. A future
historiographer may also be interested in what this volume indicates about the status of
genuine historical studies in psychology in the same period. Judging from this book,
history is apparently synonymous with review articles which consider some references that
do not bear directly on the experiments in hand.An earlier reviewer of Boring's selected papers has said that he has given form and
meaning to the growth of experimental psychology, possibly more than any other man in this
century. This is certainly true. As the editors point out, Boring's "monumental History
of Experimental Psychology is the standard text and reference source throughout
the world. Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology is
the most thoroughly documented account of this particular field".[17] The works by
Watson and Miller reviewed above are dedicated to Boring. The invitation to contribute his
autobiography and selected essays to the "Contemporary Men of Science Series"
attests to the distinction of his career, which was further recognized by a gold medal
awarded by the American Psychological Foundation, whose citation mentions seven areas of
contribution to psychology. It was as a tribute to Boring that Watson and Campbell
assembled History, Psychology and science: selected papers. Finally, it is
altogether fitting that Boring contributed the first article to the new journal, which his
own research has done so much to .inspire and to make necessary. Nothing said here should
be construed as diminishing the sense of debt which every beginner in the history of
psychology owes to him: his contribution is nonpareil. But it must be stressed that the
worst way to repay intellectual debts is to repeat the findings of one's mentors rather
than extending, amending, and deepening them.Psychologist at large contains Boring's autobiography, some letters, and 43 pieces
of varying lengths which were drawn from his bibliography of over 500 items. The book
includes scientific, historical, and theoretical articles, plus a number of editorials,
obituaries, and occasional pieces. One might have hoped that Boring's papers would provide
the detailed studies from which his general histories were distilled. Some of these pieces
are the notebooks for his books but most are occasional essays, with the bulk of the
information having been drawn from his books to illuminate their respective topics.
As such, these are all interesting documents in the history of the history of psychology
and are also revealing. Some are original, but most are examples of the perseveration
which seems to afflict this field.Three of the essays are of particular interest to historians.[18] "The Nature of
History of Experimental Control" provides an introduction to an issue which should be
explored more fully. The same is true of the complementary essays on "The Beginning
and Growth of Measurement in Psychology" and "A History of Introspection".
Each of these absorbing but impressionistic pieces could serve as the outline for an
extremely interesting monograph. Boring's papers-like his books-identify significant
issues, figures and works, while none of his studies is ultimately satisfactory. One is
always urged by them to pursue the matter more deeply and systematically. This, of course,
is a great tribute to his role as inspiration and teacher. He has done an immense service
in showing which books are important: now we must study them. His own writings have been
more in the form of essays than critical expositions involving close textual analysis.[19]
His occasional pieces are always informative and entertaining, and it is perhaps unfair to
object to the repetition of examples in papers which have been brought together from very
diverse occasions and only incidentally appear between the covers of one book.
Nevertheless one does tire of references to 1879 and the founding of Wundt's laboratory,
to the Bell-Magendie controversy, to Fechner's inspiration and, above all, to the
ever-present 'Zeitgeist'.The only essay to appear in both volumes is "Human Nature vs. Sensation:
William James and the Psychology of the Present", in which Boring used the centenary
of James's birth as an occasion for a discussion of the issues raised by the dichotomy
between a humanist or phenomenological approach (James) and the reductionist or positivist
one which Boring then advocated. He makes no attempt to resolve the issue between students
of 'human nature' and those of stimulus and response. This essay serves as an introduction
to Boring's theoretical articles on psychophysics and operationism. I find these pieces
more original and more satisfying than his historical work. In the period between 1913 and
1940, experimental psychologists were carrying on a difficult balancing act with
traditional psychophysics, the structuralist-functionalist debate, the aggressive claims
of behaviourism and operationism, and the hypotheses of Gestalt psychology. The basic
problem was what to do about consciousness and 'meaning' in a science which was ostensibly
about objective phenomena which must be measured. Boring was generally on the side of the
reductionists, but he did not share J. B. Watson's, aggressive ignorance and philosophical
naiveté. In this period Boring wrote a series of studies for which one is extremely
grateful. The first is on the physiology of consciousness, and is a summary of his book on The physical dimensions of consciousness which has itself recently been
reprinted.[20] In "Psychophysiological Systems and Isomorphic Relations" one can
almost feel the anguish of Psychophysicists and Gestalt psychologists as they attempt to
be scientific about matters which Cartesian dualism and the doctrine of primary and
secondary qualities preclude from the domain of science. In the following paper Boring
attempts a reductionist solution which involves an abrogation of private consciousness, a
reduction of its function to discrimination which is, in turn, considered in purely neural
terms. I find his proposed solution unclear and unsatisfactory, but it is a useful
document in the history of the debate. The most enlightening of these articles is an
earlier one on "The Stimulus-Error" in which he distils the course of debate on
psychophysics and recalls that Cartesian dualism precludes quantification of mental
events, while scientific psychology necessarily depends on some version of just such
measurement. In general one may say that Boring's theoretical papers on the mind-body
problem are symptoms of rather than solutions to the problems raised by the new methods
and assumptions of behaviourism and operationism. These articles, like those in Psychology
in the making, will serve historians as materials for historical research, whereas
Boring's historical writings are valuable guides to further research.Two of Boring's essays are intensely personal. The autobiographical piece,
"Psychologist at Large",[21] and the story of his brief psychoanalysis are
brutally honest accounts of his "search for maturity". As such they are
sometimes immodest and even embarrassing. Different readers will react differently to his
openness but, whatever their response, it would be difficult not to respect him for making
revelations which few men would be brave enough to place at the disposal of potentially
unkind critics. Freud was careful not to do so in his autobiography, and he resented the
fact that he had found it necessary to reveal much of himself in his psychoanalytic
writings. When Herbert Spencer revealed too much of himself one reader remarked: "It
seems impossible that the opinions of a man who depicts himself as the glorified
quintessence of a prig can be worth anything".[22] William James was no less
unkind.[23] The only document which tempted me to this sort of response was an
unnecessarily tactless and patronising letter to Professor Bartlett about British
psychology.[24]This letter, together with Boring's remarks on his relations with Titchener, leads on
to an important matter of interpretation in Boring's writings. He tells us that Titchener
was his hero and that his "image has always dominated my professional life".[25]
Boring systematically provides a relatively greater emphasis on German influences on
American psychology at the expense of the British. He places heavy weight on the
"founding" of experimental psychology by Wundt and on the introduction of
measurement in psychophysics and introspective studies. He is also concerned with the
training of students, which certainly did owe more to the "new psychology" in
Germany. One feels that Boring is more at home in this tradition and the writings of
Fechner, Helmholtz and Wundt, than in the parallel British work. As he recognizes, the
assumptions of the "new psychology" were derived from British empiricism and
associationism.[26] He also acknowledges the influence of Bain, Spencer and Darwin in
providing the bases of functionalism: associationism, evolutionism and emphasis on
learning as a consequence of what organisms do. But the chapters in his History of
experimental psychology on the period from Locke to Spencer, and his essay on
"The Influence of Evolutionary Theory upon American Psychological Thought", are
among the least original of his contributions.[27] In particular Boring has failed to
grasp the full significance of Bain's emphasis on motion in the history of
associationism. It was a crucial factor in the transition from a primarily sensationalist
view, which grew out of the origins of association in epistemology, to a new interest in
learning as the result of sensations consequent upon motion. The subsequent history
of this view in Thorndike's 'law of effect', the functionalism of James and Dewey,
Watson's behaviourism, and the concept of 'operant' in Skinner is relatively
well-understood. But historians have failed to relate Bain's influence on pragmatism with
the assumptions of functional psychology. As Peirce said, Bain's criterion of belief-
"that upon which a man is prepared to act"-was urged on the members of the
Cambridge, Massachusetts 'Metaphysical Club' by Nicholas St John Green. Peirce continues:
"From this definition, pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary; so I am disposed
to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism".[28] We need a much more careful
study of Bain's influence upon the concomitant development of functionalist psychology.
After all, James was the main inspiration of both functionalism and pragmatism.Bain prefaced his work on The senses and the intellect with a statement of how
far his analysis went beyond the traditional doctrine of the muscle sense: ". . . . I
have thought it proper to assign to Movement and the feeling of Movement a position
preceding the sensations of the senses; and have endeavoured to prove that the exercise of
active energy originating in purely internal impulses, independent of the stimulus
produced by outward impression, is a primary factor of our constitution".[29] As he
developed his argument, he urged that the muscle sense and movement are fundamentally
important: ". . . . action is a more intimate and inseparable property of our
constitution than any of our sensations, and in fact enters as a component part into every
one of the senses, giving them the character of compounds, while itself is a simple and
elementary property" [30] Spontaneous movements, he held, are a feature of nervous
activity prior to and independent of sensations.[31] The acquired linkages of spontaneous
movements, with the pleasures and pains consequent upon them, educate the organism so that
its formerly random movements become adapted to ends or purposes. He defined volition as
this compound of spontaneous movements and feelings .[32] In his theory, the co-ordination
of motor impulses into definitive purposive movement results from the association of ideas
with them. He argued that no previous "writer on the human mind" had put forward
this concept of spontaneous actions and their connection with voluntary actions; "but
the following interesting extracts from the great physiologist, Müller, will show that he
has been forcibly impressed with the one and the other of these views" .[33] If one
traces this doctrine through the writing of Müller, it will be found that his motor
theory is an elaboration of conceptions in Erasmus Darwin's Zoonomia (1894-6) and
that these, in turn, are developed from Hartley's Observations on man (1749). These
developments certainly deserve much more careful study. While the association psychology
retained a bias toward sensation, concomitant developments were occurring in biology and
physiology which, when reintegrated with associationism in the work of Bain, led to a
fundamental change of emphasis which was basic to the emergence of the modern
pre-occupation with behaviour as the primary subject matter of psychology.Why has this issue been ignored? An important reason, one feels, is that readers
(though not Boring himself) consider his History of experimental Psychology definitive.
He says that he does not propose to abstract Bain's systematic treatises.[34] He then goes
on to say of Bain that "It is also probable that he did not know Müller's
psychological physiology". Boring bases this allegation on Bain's ignorance of
German. It was, of course, Baly's translation of Müller that Bain quoted as an important
part of the background of his motor theory.[35] This is the central argument of Bain's
systematic treatise on the will and his most important and influential contribution to the
association psychology. There are innumerable references to Müller in both volumes
of Bain's major work, beginning with table of contents.Enough has been said to indicate that the work of Edwin G. Boring is at the centre of
both the achievements and the limitations of the history of psychology as a scholarly
discipline. Two comments in his writings symbolise the problems involved. When he had
published the second edition of his History of experimental psychology, Boring
tells us that his pet fear was that people would say, "but anyone can write history.
Can he not do research?"36 The introductory chapters of most histories of psychology
echo this defensive view, while the writings of many who do research as their primary
activity and history as a pastime should reassure Boring that his fear has little
foundation. On the other hand, those who have used Boring as a definitive work have done a
great disservice to the historical analysis of the behavioural sciences. The editor's
introduction to the second edition of Boring's History of experimental
Psychology says: "It seems difficult to believe that anyone will again deem it
necessary to undertake as meticulous and definitive a history of experimental psychology's
early period as Boring here gives us. He has steeped himself in his subject as no one else
ever will".[37] There is much justice in this claim. But the study of the history of
psychology has suffered mightily from those who have taken it literally. It may be useful
to give one more example of the sort of 'inverted pyramid' which results from part-time
historical scholars who mistake secondary sources for primary ones.The pseudo-science of phrenology played an important part in the development of
psychology as a biological science.[38] One of the ways in which phrenology helped to
develop a naturalistic interpretation of the mental functions of animals and men was by
challenging the prevailing view of the fundamental variables in behaviour. Philosophical
psychology had passed down the abstract categories of reason, memory, will, intelligence
and so on. Franz Joseph Gall questioned these categories and asserted that the study of
the functions of the brain depended upon the study of animals in their environments and of
men in society. It was only by this method, Gall argued, that we could arrive at a
meaningful set of categories. It is therefore of considerable interest that Gall's
faculties bear a verbal resemblance to those of the Scottish faculty psychologists, Reid,
Stewart and (to some extent), Brown. In 1935, Spoerl wrote an article which considered the
importance of Gall's analysis for contemporary debates on 'faculties versus traits'.[39]
Spoerl shows that the verbal similarity between Gall's faculties and those of Reid and
Stewart is superficial and that they were conceived on an entirely different basis. The
Scots were concerned with mind in general, whereas Gall was only interested in those
faculties which were determinate of individual and species differences. Spoerl goes on to
consider the charge that Gall borrowed his catalogue of faculties from the Scots. He notes
that Stewart published after Gall and argues that it appears that "Gall had no
knowledge of the Scottish faculty psychology".[40] He also shows that Gall did not
borrow from the Wolffian faculty psychology. Indeed, he specifically repudiated it.[41] In
the second edition of his History of experimental psychology, Boring refers
to this article. He says: "Modern psychology has largely failed to establish any such
units, but Gall had ready for use the faculties of the Scottish School. . . . It was from
the lists of Thomas Reid and Dugald Stewart that Gall obtained his analysis of the mind
into 37 power and propensities".[42] He says later that Spoerl ". . . shows how
Gall got his list of faculties from Reid and Stewart in the Scottish School".[43]
This was a simple mistake of memory, and we all make such mistakes. I confess that I have
not made a careful study of the fate of this small point, but in the preparation of this
review I have found it repeated in three places in Boring's writings.[44] It also appears
in two of the works whose authors praise Boring lavishly.[45]One could go on indefinitely citing such simple mistakes, omissions, and
interpretations with which one disagrees. For example, in his history of reflex action,
Boring ignores the contributions of Laycock and Carpenter. More serious is the omission of
the neurological and psychological theories of Hughlings Jackson and their significant
influences on Sherrington and Freud, to say nothing of the whole tenor of modern
neurology. In the same vein he ignores the careful historical research of Henry Head on
Gall and on the subsequent history of aphasia, although he devotes considerable space to
these topics.[46] I have not compared the two editions of the History of experimental
psychology systematically, but it is certainly clear that Boring failed to take
account of a great deal of important historical research in the period which elapsed
between 1929 and 1950. For example, he takes no account of the work of Owsei Temkin on
phrenology, Magendie, or French and German materialism. Nor does he consider the classical
English source on Magendie. The work of this physiologist was basic to the development of
the paradigm which still dominates experimental psychology. Boring has reminded us that
for the scientist accuracy is closely allied to honesty. This is true of the history of
science also, and Boring is far from the worst of those professional psychologists who do
historical research as a part-time activity.[47]It has seemed necessary to give these examples, not because of any feelings we or the
emperor may have about his clothes, but because of the activities of those who admire them
in a completely unqualified and uncritical way. The time has come to insist upon rigorous
standards of scholarship in the history of the behavioural sciences. The field has all of
the trappings of a valid scholarly discipline; like history of science in general, it has
passed through the useful but limited stage of amateurism. The history of physical science
is well beyond this point, and the history of the biological sciences is approaching it.
The history of the behavioural sciences has not yet reached the point where most of its
practitioners have become self-consciously critical. The limitations which were inevitable
in pioneering work such as that of Boring should now be eliminated, for Professor Boring's
achievement is such that his work can easily afford to have such limitations pointed out.
The numerous examples which one could give of the work of others would not leave their
reputations intact. At the moment the standards of scholarship in the history of the
behavioural sciences lie somewhere between those in the history of medicine and those in
the general history of science. Indeed, it may be that the history of medicine is already
beginning to transcend the amateurism which was so prevalent until recently.Studies in the history of the behavioural sciences suffer from two severe handicaps.
The first is the mixed blessing of the available secondary sources. The second is the
apparent inability to decide what sort of enquiry history of the behavioural sciences is.
Is it an adjunct to laboratory work? A charming avocation? Or a research discipline whose
standards must be as high as those practised in the laboratory? The available secondary
sources have limitations about which their authors are quite clear, but those who use them
have not taken them seriously enough. Brett's three-volume History of psychology (1912-21)
provided an excellent survey of the history of psychology, with primary emphasis on its
development within philosophy. Boring was primarily concerned with the emergence of
experimental psychology in the period between 1860 and 1910, and no other historian
has considered as many of the relevant works as he did. His mastery of research on
sensation and perception is unique. Murphy considered his work to be an introductory text,
and as such it is extremely useful. Nevertheless, a scholarly tradition which is based
primarily on textbooks has severe inherent limitations. If one began one's research in the
history of psychology from Boring's footnotes, one would find a very exciting catalogue of
unanswered questions. But the tendency has been to learn from the text and not from the
footnotes. That is, the prevailing mode of analysis in the history of the behavioural
sciences is one of writing expository history and leaving out the loose ends and
provocative questions which stimulate research. Expository history has a justification
after the problems have been examined and the critical debates which study of the primary
sources engender are well along. An excellent example of this is Passmore's work on the
recent history of philosophy.[48] This position is far from having been reached in the
history of the behavioural sciences. The monograph and journal literature is simply of
insufficient volume and quality.Didactic, expository history takes the view that there is a little story to be told.
The problem of the historian is to find the facts and report them in a readable and
accurate fashion. This view is related to an extraordinarily naive positivism which
permeates much of the writing of experimental psychologists when they indulge in
historical inquiries. It is sometimes made explicit when the term 'philosophical' is used
synonymously with 'speculative'. It is implied in the way people write-making a gesture to
the pre-experimental literature as a sort of literary gloss before getting down to the
serious part of an article. Although his work is usually free from this, Boring indulges
in this sort of thinking in seeking to establish when experimental psychology was
'founded'. Kuhn has reminded us just how much we lose when we approach history as
"chroniclers of an incremental process". In the physical sciences this approach
has shown itself to be unfruitful. Indeed, it is clear that this is simply the wrong sort
of question to ask.49 History, like science, is controversy, not story-telling. The
failure to take this point is shown more clearly in the occasional pieces which grace the
beginning of every scientific symposium, and every opening of a new institute. These
pieces are often of bibliographical use, but they are obviously written by scientists in a
hurry. The result is variable-often appalling and occasionally just acceptable. What is
missing, once again, is original research.[50]One has very mixed feelings about the endeavours of experimental psychologists, and
other scientists concerned with brain and behaviour, in writing the history of their
respective disciplines. Such writings provide a sense of relevance to contemporary
research which is of considerable use to historians, and for this one is extremely
grateful. It is difficult to imagine how these scientists can combine historical research
with their experimental work, publications and textbook writing in their fields. For
example, to deride Boring for not being the 'compleat' historian would be to ignore the
500 items in his bibliography. In fact, he wrote his historical volumes in his summer
vacations, and few avocations can have been more fruitful. My argument is not aimed at
working psychologists who make contributions to the history of psychology. Rather is it
aimed at those who think that this is enough. Although professional physicists and
biologists have made significant contributions to the histories of their sciences (and
some have even left science to devote themselves primarily to historical scholarship),
important work in the history of physical sciences has mainly been done by full-time
historians, and the history of biological sciences is slowly approaching this standard.
The same may be said of the history of medicine, though its artificial separation from
general history of science reminds one of the situation faced in psychology. If the
history of psychology is to advance beyond being an avocation with very uneven standards,
those professional psychologists who would contribute to scholarship must grasp the fact
that the standards of historical scholarship are not less rigorous than those of
experimental science. In fact, since historians are usually dealing with 'softer' data,
the standards must in many ways be higher. They can make significant contributions only if
they are prepared to conduct research which thoroughly covers its chosen topic. What are
needed are monographs, articles of definite scope and pieces which are concerned with
important figures, the historical development of concepts (see below) and other limited
subjects. There should be no more general surveys for some time to come: we have reached
the stage where we know enough to know not to write them until we know a great deal more.The main barrier to the approach advocated here is, unfortunately, the attitude of
part-time historians. This is made clear in the prefaces to some of the works which have
appeared recently. The introductory chapter to Psychology in the making, as well as
those to the works by Esper and Murphy, indicate that the writers of these books have a
defensive attitude about being interested in the history of psychology at all. They are
casting about for pedagogic benefits to be derived from a discipline which (if it has any
justification at all) must be justified on its own terms. Having recently read the
standard sources in the history of psychology in a short period, I find that this attitude
permeates much of the writing in this field, giving the impression that the authors have
not really devoted themselves wholeheartedly to their research. The result is surveys
which show a sad absence of the intimate acquaintance with the primary sources which is a
simple, basic requirement for meaningful research. The author finds that he must stop when he reaches complex and subtle issues. As a consequence, the same stories are to
be told time and again, and our understanding is never deepened. Nor are we troubled by
the problems which stimulate the research.Since most books and articles in the history of the behavioural sciences have been
written by working scientists for their colleagues and students, their interests and
viewpoint have naturally led them to stress the history of problems of current interest.
History is thus written backwards from the viewpoint of a modern textbook. It is arguable
that this approach is most useful to these authors and their chosen audience, but the
argument ultimately breaks down for two reasons. First, the result is shockingly bad
history. The writings of other periods are considered completely out of their context, and
the near mention (and often the apparent mentioning based on what is really no more than a
verbal similarity-a pun) of a conception is hailed as a discovery, and history is at once
played false and degenerates into the search for anticipations: 'is A buried in B's
grave?' The second reason is that this approach-arguing backwards from current views
denies the student one of the most valuable helps to be gained from historical reading:
perspective. If we do not understand a problem in its own terms as it was seen in a
different period-if, indeed, we interpret it solely in terms of our own views-then we
shall lose the benefit of transcending our own assumptions and our current vantage point.The main stream of writing of the history of science is beginning to reflect this
point, and the results of this insight have been summarised by Kuhn and identified as
"a historiographic revolution in the history of science, though one that is still in
its early stages.... Rather than seeking the permanent contributions of an older science
to our present vantage, they [historians] attempt to display the historical integrity in
its own time".[51] There is scant evidence that this approach has begun to dawn on
historians of the behavioural sciences. Indeed, the references to historiography in the
works under review leave a very great deal to be desired. Even in referring to Kuhn's
admirable exposition of the new historiography, they betray little grasp of the
implications of the demand that we understand the past in its own terms before comparing
it with our own vantage point. Here, for example, is one current view of history written
by an historian of psychology: "The historian charts a road through the past. He
shows how one event follows another leading toward a particular state of affairs, towards
a destination which he has selected and which, in turn, enables him to distinguish between
important and unimportant events. He thinks backwards, always looking for antecedents,
even though he usually writes forwards so as to simulate the progress of real
events".[52] One could not hope for a better summary of what recent historiography
has attempted to put aside.53 Although one has reservations about aspects of the arguments
of Kuhn and Agassi, a comparison between these and the writings of (for example) Boring
and Watson on historiography is extremely embarrassing for the historian of the
behavioural sciences. There is only one piece which has appeared in recent years which
gives hope for the historiographical sophistication of historians of the behavioural
sciences. A recent editorial in the new Journal of the history of the behavioral
sciences by George Stocking, Jnr. provides an excellent review of the recent debate on
historiography and discusses its relevance to the history of the behavioural sciences.54The remainder of this essay will be devoted to discussing areas of research in which
new work is needed and to indicating some of the sources which may be fruitful for future
work.Much work needs to be done in placing the history of the behavioural sciences within
the context of the development of modern science. We have learned that the history of
modern philosophy cannot be fully understood unless we interpret it in the light of the
progress of science. Thus we read Hobbes, Descartes ' Locke, Hume, Leibniz and Kant in
terms of the Scientific Revolution. Similarly we read Kepler, Galileo, Boyle, and Newton
as scientist-philosophers who provide the essential concepts and the radical views with
which the philosophers were attempting to cope. In the same way, we must learn to see the
same figures as influencing and influenced by a new, approach to psychology. In his
classical discussion of metaphysical foundations of modern physical science, A. E. Burtt
referred to concept of mind as a convenient receptacle, for the refuse, the chips and
whittlings of science, rather than a possible, object of scientific knowledge.[55]'
Twenty-five years later, this point was made again in A. G. A. Balz's sensitive Cartesian
studies, where it was pointed out that psychology had to be whatever the new physics
and the related metaphysics permitted it to be.[56] Modern psychology grew, in fact, from
a synthesis of views of Locke and Newton within the dualistic framework set by Descartes.
But it is not the historians of psychology who have seen this. Rather it has been made
clear by the writings of the scholars just mentioned and by Crombie, Vartanian, Halévy
and Albee, among others, whose writings have been largely. ignored by, historians of
psychology.[57] The problems of modern psychology grew. out of and are continuous with
those of the classical Scientific Revolution. Indeed their origin should be traced to the
natural philosophers from Kepler to Newton and the price which they paid in order to
achieve a world which could be exploited by the physico-chemical sciences. In return for a
physical universe of matter and motion-of extended substances-which could be treated by
geometrical, mathematical means, they pushed their main problems into the concept of mind.
Those that remained were accommodated by the concepts of the Deity and the ether. Thus,
Descartes, Locke, Newton, and Hartley provide the essential framework within which
scientific, philosophic, and psychological problems must be seen. The branch of inquiry
which can be delineated by the phrase 'history of behavioural sciences' finds its
boundaries defined by the principle of continuity on the one hand and Cartesian dualism on
the other, with the problem of final causes as the central issue then as now. The
seventeenth-century problem of primary and secondary qualities plagues psychology in a way
which is more crippling than in any other science. The psychology of perception has been
most directly influenced by this and the related subject-object dualism which were
codified when mind was separated from nature and this separation was made an assumption of
modern scientific metaphysics. Similarly, the Cartesian framework set the boundaries for
mechanistic biology, and both the reflex concept and behaviourism can trace a lineage to
the physical side of Descartes's ontological dualism.Hartley was less original than Descartes, in that his psychology was a crystallisation
of ideas which derive from Locke, Gay and Newton. Nevertheless, associationism was first
formulated as a systematic psychology by Hartley, and the claim that "association is
the only theory of learning that has ever been proposed"[58] is a useful starting
point for qualification. In its philosophic aspects, the study of the history of the
behavioural sciences is the story of attempts to transcend Cartesian dualism, the
doctrine of primary and secondary qualities, and the banishment of final causes from
science. The problems of epistemology and methodology in psychology turn on the ontology
which was codified by Galileo, Descartes and Newton. These are not distant problems for
psychology: they are very near the surface. It is no accident that those who have
struggled most mightily against Cartesian dualism have been psychologists, for example
Lloyd Morgan and later the Gestalt psychologists. Also, the leaders of modern psychology
began their careers by taking a stand on this issue. Freud's psychophysical parallelism
allowed him to pursue his psychological research without committing himself to a
neurological theory which he had attempted to formulate and which he was unable to bring
to a level which was commensurate with his psychological studies; he was indebted to
Hughlings Jackson and Herbert Spencer for the ontology of his theory.[59] J. B. Watson's
methodology-which became an ontology-was based explicitly on a rejection of mental
substances as part of the domain of science. And some of his more polemical writings show
just how seriously he took this problem above all others.[60] Similar statements could be
made about the positions of Wundt, McDougall, Tolman, Lashley, Sherrington, Eccles, and
other major psychologists whose work is still influencing experimental research. The
history of psychology has had to live in a world whose basic substances are the mental and
the physical. When psychology was seen to be a biological science, it therefore had no
basis for its fundamental variables. The physical precluded the essential notions of
pleasure-pain, adaptation, and utility, while the mental world was (it was finally
decided) unmeasurable. Thus historians and philosophers have a common ground with working
psychologists in attempting to develop the basis of a biological science of psychology in
a world of minds and bodies. It is no accident that the characterisation of mental
phenomena has always borrowed its language from the world of matter. As Bain showed, no
other language is available to psychology.[61] The history of psychology, therefore, has
important relations with the history of science, the history of philosophy, and with
current debates in the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science.I have argued that the history of the behavioural sciences must pay much closer
attention to the Scientific Revolution. Conversely, a great deal of work remains to be
done on the history of the problems which have been traditionally associated with
psychology as they influenced the main stream of the history of science. For
example, the influence of the association psychology on the development of theories of
evolution has not, to my knowledge, been explored, except in two brief chapters of a
general work.[62] In fact, Hartley's theory provided the essential mechanism for Erasmus
Darwin's theory of evolution. Similarly, the mechanism of so-called 'Lamarckian' evolution
was associationist, and Herbert Spencer developed it in this form: "The familiar
doctrine of association here undergoes a great extension; for it is held that not only in
the individual do ideas become connected when in experience the things producing them have
repeatedly occurred together, but that such results of repeated occurrences accumulate in
successions of individuals: the effects of associations are supposed to be transmitted as
modifications in the nervous system".[63] Finally, there is a great deal of
fundamental research to be done on the relations between associationism, the
'Philosophical Radicals', and the development of both social legislation and evolutionary
thinking in the nineteenth century. Aspects of this have been considered '[64] but its
full import has not been appreciated.If we look more closely at the history of the association psychology, the works of
Ribot' [65] and Warren [66] remain the best expositions of this tradition. These books
will continue to be useful, but this merit implies an important limitation. Neither makes
a serious attempt at analysing or criticising the books which it is considering. Also they
are only considering the major works of the major figures, and they ignore the
contexts in which men wrote. It would be anachronistic to criticise Ribot and Warren for
writing only about the great books of great men since other branches of historical
scholarship were still in the process of transcending this essentially un-historical
approach. Indeed, Ribot was not writing history; he was translating contemporary British
literature for a French audience. Warren, though purporting to write history, was dealing
with a living tradition which had not yet been successfully absorbed by behaviourism. The
book .was begun in 1903 and completed in 1921, and its final chapters reported
contemporary work. It is a tribute to the authors that these treatments continue to be
useful, but it is also a comment upon subsequent scholarship that their shortcomings have
not been noted, much less corrected, by detailed studies which take account of a wider
range of materials in investigating narrower topics.Even if one accepts the assumptions of the anachronistic historiography which have
prevailed in the history of psychology, it is still surprising that associationism has not
received a more thorough treatment. The continuity between nineteenth-century
associationism and modern psychological research has been amply stressed. In 1930 Brett
developed this point with some care and traced the links between associationism, the
reflex concept, and the conditioned reflex as they were united by the behaviourists. He
saw these developments as "the latest form if associationism". They constituted
the contemporary solution to efforts to justify associationism "by reference to
physiological processes" and bring it into touch with "bedrock of
experience". "Discarding the unnecessary phrase 'of ideas', and broadening both
thought and language to suit the new outlook, it is correct to say that the use of
conditioned reflexes is the most significant way in which the central positions of
associationism are active today".[67] Behaviourism was a fundamental transfiguration
of associationism, but its basic assumptions remain clear. Twenty years later, Murphy
traced the continuity between nineteenth-century associationism and recent research.
"If one had to summarise the main trend as it now exists in the middle of the
century, it would almost certainly have to be to the effect that despite huge continuous
protests of strong and active personalities, the conceptions of Bain and Spencer a hundred
years ago remain dominant. . . . An enormous amount of sophistication has gone into
experimental and quantitative refinement of the theory of association; but the framework
set up by the associationists remains".[68] One might add that the theory of
association is also at the foundation of psychoanalytic theory and therapy.If we set aside the interests of current psychology, and consider the contemporary
context, we find that the significance of the principle of association was appreciated
almost at the outset. It was Hume who pointed out that this theory was the fundamental law
of the mental world, just as gravity was the fundamental law of the material world.
"Here is a kind of Attraction, which in the mental world will be found to have
as extraordinary as in the natural, and show itself in as many and as various
forms".[69] Why, then, has the work of the founder of the associationism received
such scant attention at the hands of historians of psychology? Hartley's theory developed
out of suggestions in Locke and in Gay, which he then synthesised with ideas drawn from
Newton. From these he developed a systematic physiological psychology based on the two
principles of physical vibration in the nervous system, paralleled by mental associations:
"The Doctrine of Vibrations may appear at first Sight to have no Connection
with that of Association; however, if these Doctrines be found in fact to contain
the Laws of the Bodily and Mental Powers respectively, they must be related to each other,
since the Body and Mind are. One may expect, that Vibrations should infer Association as their Effect, and Association point to Vibrations as its Cause [70]
The principles for which Hartley argued became accepted as the basic assumptions of
physiological psychology in the nineteenth century, and they have thus not changed
fundamentally since 1749. The developments which were based on this theory form the most
important aspect of the application of the scientific revolution to the neural,
behavioural and social sciences. Nevertheless, there has been no full-scale study
of Hartley's work and influence. I know of only one paper in the recent literature,[71]
and this is of an expository nature. Among older writings the only paper which I have been
able to find was a brief discussion of one aspect of his earlier thought.[72] The only
monograph which has appeared was primarily expository and popular, and this was published
in 1881.[73]The relationship between Hartley and Joseph Priestley and the development of Hartley's
doctrine in Priestley's hands also deserve serious study. These, together with the
reaction on the part of the Scottish philosophers of 'common sense', form a significant
part of the history of ideas and the relationship between mind and body on the one
hand and the problem of epistemology on the other. The most recent monograph on Priestley
pays scant attention to these issues, and I have seen no other study which treats it
seriously.[74] Such studies should form a small part of a more broadly-based investigation
which could concern itself with the pleasure-pain principle, utilitarianism, and their
influences on social, political, scientific, and philosophical thinking. Aspects of this
problem have been touched upon, for example by Schofield[75] and in the masterly study of
Halévy.[76] These should be complemented with other specialised studies which might form
the basis of a more synthetic work. One could then go further to consider the continuity
between these ideas and those of evolution, pragmatism, functional psychology and modern
psychological theories such as behaviourism and psycho-analysis.The psychological theories of Erasmus Darwin will form an integral part of such an
investigation. The only serious appreciation of his work in this area known to me is a
chapter in Lewes's History of Philosophy. [77] The author of the most recent
monograph on Erasmus Darwin fails to consider the relationship between his theory and that
of Hartley on the one hand and their developments by Priestley on the other. Indeed, he
thinks the associationist basis of Erasmus Darwin's classification of disease fallacious
and describes it only to dismiss it.[78] An important first step in the study of the work
and influence of Hartley and Darwin would be the reprinting of their major works. There
are no signs that Zoonomia may appear, and the promised reprinting of Hartley's Observations has not yet occurred.Utilitarianism and associationism contributed significantly to the background of the
modern theory of evolution. The theory of evolution, in turn, raised issues about the
concept of mind which are not yet resolved. The most important figures in the
nineteenth-century concerned with this debate were Charles Darwin, Herbert Spencer, G. J.
Romanes, Hughlings Jackson and, less importantly, T. H. Huxley and A. R. Wallace. The most
fundamental, though not always explicit, issue in the evolutionary debate was man's place
in nature and the implications of evolution for mind, the concept of responsibility, and
theology. But one finds that historians have paid scant attention to this aspect of the
evolutionary debate. This failure has occurred as much on the side as historians of
biology as that of historians of the behavioural sciences. Thus there is no detailed study
of Darwin's psychological work. The most recent study of A. R. Wallace is primarily
concerned with his contributions to Zoogeography and makes no attempt to provide an
analysis of his writings on mind and evolution. [79] Eiseley's treatment is more thorough,
but it is marred by his advocacy of a separation of man's mind from the laws which control
the rest of evolution and behaviour; his attempt to read Darwin in the light of Wallace's
views reveals the lengths to which one can go in applying personal beliefs to the facts of
history.[80] The writings of Darwin, Spencer, Wallace, Lewes, Romanes, Lloyd Morgan and
later figures on mind and evolution await considered historical study and would provide
the materials for an important contribution to our understanding of the history of biology
and psychology. It is something of a scandal that these have been neglected, while
historians of psychology continue to re-tell the same old stories, and so ignore an
absolutely fundamental aspect of the heritage of modern thought. Each of these figures is
worthy of at least a monograph, but one finds that most of them have not even had so much
as an article devoted to their work. Chapters which appear in the standard
histories are helpful but lack depth. The theories of Darwin, Spencer, and Wallace on the
application of evolution and natural selection to the mind are a self-contained unit which
could itself form the basis of a very important study. Historians have contented
themselves with dismissing Spencer because of his Lamarckism, praising Darwin for his
inspiration, and ignoring Wallace.If one considers lesser figures and influences in the application of evolution to mind,
the curious role of phrenology in contributing to the study of mind and brain and in
stressing the significance of the concept of adaptation to psychology is worth more
careful study than it has yet received. Phrenology significantly influenced the general
movement toward the naturalistic treatment of man in the nineteenth century, including, in
particular, the evolutionary theories of Chambers, Spencer, and Wallace, but these
influences and the more general effects of phrenology have been largely ignored.81
Similarly the seminal influence of Thomas Laycock (who, incidentally, also benefited from
the phrenological movement) has been the subject of only one recent paper, and this was
only concerned with one aspect of his work. 82 Thomas Laycock formulated a theory which
stressed that the nervous system must be seen as one continuous series of structures
obeying one law, that of the reflex. His views came from a pre-evolutionary
traditional.[83] This was combined with Spencer's evolutionary associationism to form the
two major influences on Jackson's psychophysiological theories. These, in turn, were basic
to the work of Ferrier and Sherrington. Laycock's role in such a fundamental aspect of the
history of the study of mind and brain should be given more careful attention than it has
yet received. One concludes that Jackson was certainly fortunate in his intellectual
mentors, since they gave him the best of the old (Laycock) and the new (Spencer) versions
of the principle of continuity as applied to the nervous system. This matter must be much
more closely examined, but it already appears that this parallel development of identical
conceptions based respectively on the old and new philosophy of biology is most remarkable
and interesting.The number of subjects within the history of the behavioural sciences which would repay
intensive study seems to be inexhaustible. We have no history of the concept of adaptation
from natural theology and theodicy to its modern form in evolution and in functional
psychology. We have no history of faculty psychology, nor of the concept of function. Each
of these has important historical bearings, and the last is of fundamental philosophical
significance. Indeed, as Whitehead suggested, the concept of function may be the Achilles
heel of dualistic ontology of modern science. Finally, the concept of behaviour itself has
not been given any sort of historical treatment, although the lineage from physiognomy,
debates on the role of touch in learning and the muscle sense, form an interrelated set of
influences which played an important part in the development of psychological and
philosophical thinking.If we confine our attention to the concept of function within the context of mind and
evolution, the next logical step is a detailed examination of the development of
functional thinking after 1859. Functional psychology was an outgrowth of the
ferment in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in the 1860s and 1870s which led to the
philosophical movement of pragmatism. In fact, James proved the most articulate exponent
of both views. It can be questioned whether pragmatism as a movement (as opposed to Peirce
as an individual philosopher) has made a significant contribution to philosophy. But its
heuristic value in generating psychological, social, and educational conceptions is beyond
question. The pragmatic approach which influenced James's early thinking had its origins
in Darwin, Spencer, J. S. Mill and Bain as interpreted through Peirce, Chauncey Wright,
and Nicholas St. John Green at the meetings of the 'Metaphysical Club'.84 James's Principles of psychology was a synthesis of the evolutionary and adaptive points of view with
James's education in medicine and physiology. It drew most heavily on Spencer, Bain and
Wundt, within the general atmosphere created by Darwin and the discussions surrounding
evolution.John Dewey was inspired by James's work and founded a 'functional' school of thought in
psychology, and it may be useful to be reminded of the transitional position of this
school-between the new evolutionism and behaviourism. Dewey's article on "The reflex
concept in psychology" [85] is usually considered the starting point of the
functional movement. He attempted to free the reflex concept from a simple mechanistic
interpretation and to take account of plasticity and the importance of the environment.
Sensations and motions were not simple variables but should be considered in their
functional context. His talk on "Psychology and social practice"[86] spelt out
the technological and practical applications of functionalism, and his educational work is
shown to follow naturally from his biological, adaptive point of view. His article on
"The influence of Darwin on philosophy" [87] shows how evolution became the
central theme of his life's work: "The influence of Darwin upon philosophy resides in
his having conquered the phenomena of life for the principle of transition, and thereby
freed the new logic for application to mind and morals and life. When he said of species
what Galileo had said of the earth, e pur se muove, he emancipated, once for all,
genetic and experimental ideas as an organon for asking questions and looking for
explanations".[88]James R. Angell was the principal expositor of functionalism. His 1906 Presidential
Address to the American Psychological Association is the classical statement of the
movement. He is quite explicit about its ancestry: "Whatever else it may be,
functional psychology is nothing wholly new. In certain of its phases it is plainly
discernible in the psychology of Aristotle and in its more modern garb it has been
increasingly in evidence since Spencer wrote his Psychology and Darwin his Origin
of Species".[89] This article should be read in conjunction with
Titchener's "The postulates of a structural psychology",[90] since both
structuralism and functionalism owed much of their identities as 'schools' to the debates
that occurred between them.Ruckmich provides a very useful textual analysis of the use of the term 'function' in
this period, and Dallenbach gives some evidence to support the thesis that the
introduction of the term in a psychological (as opposed to a physiological) sense was due
to the influence of phrenology on the nineteenth-century British psychologists from Thomas
Brown to Spencer.[91] If this could be demonstrated in detail, it would provide a powerful
additional argument in favour of the seminal importance in phrenology in converting
psychology into a biological science. Changes in the meaning of the term 'function' are a
crucial indication of the development of biological psychology.Functionalism was characterised by its concern for mind in use, activity as opposed to
contents, and behaviour as the natural outcome of perceiving and knowing. It also had a
greater interest in physiology and the mind-body relationship than other contemporary
schools. It was an evolutionary, biological psychology concerned with adjustment to rather
than representation of reality. Functionalism flourished only briefly as a
recognisable movement; J. B. Watson claimed that "behaviorism is the only
consistent and logical functionalism".[92] This bid for absorption seems to have
worked, and Watson rapidly,[93] overlaid this initial formulation with the reflex concept
as the standard explanatory model and added on a narrow materialist ontology that largely
obscured the biological, adaptive and comparative thinking of the early functionalists.
More particularly, his polemic against the introspective method led him to deny any
significance to consciousness and mental variables. It has been shown that this
philosophic nonsense must be separated from his methodological contributions.[94] The
result was that orthodox behaviourists dealt with the most difficult problem of modern
thought by abrogating it, where the functionalists had held out some hope of putting
mental variables into a biological context.The functional view is still supported in some quarters, but it is not seriously
considered to be among the current 'schools' of thinking in psychology. It would be most
interesting to do a full study of the development of this aspect of psychology from
Spencer and Darwin until behaviourism stole the limelight after 1913, and then to use an
historical approach in an attempt to dig functionalism out from under Watson's
behaviourism, the reflex, and materialism (with its allied operationism) and see what it
can offer to the presents[95] Once again, functionalism could and should eventually be
studied in a broader context, and the main figures for such a study would certainly be
Oliver Wendell Holmes Jnr., G. H. Mead, and John Dewey, at least on the questions of law,
sociology, and philosophy of a democratic society and its educational system.There are many other desiderata in the history of the behavioural sciences: The history
of French sensationalism from Condillac to the Ideologues has received scant attention in
the English literatures. [96] A full history of the reflex concept has not been seriously
attempted since Fearing, although Canguilhem has considered the seventeenth- and
eighteenth-century developments with care. [97] And there is a need for more careful
studies of the work of Prochaska, Whytt,[98] Hall, Carpenter and Sherrington. The history
of the study of personality has hardly begun, although Roback has provided a bibliography
which will prove of some use,[99] and Allport has provided broad outlines.[100] The
history of animal psychology is a topic which has interesting relations with other aspects
of biology and philosophy, but it has not been considered in any detail.[101] The history
of sensory-motor physiology forms a subject in its own right which extends from Greek
science to behaviourism. Professor Temkin may provide us with an aspect of this in his
promised study of the history of the concept of irritability, which has begun with an
article on Glisson.102 It is perhaps invidious to go on listing areas in which research
needs doing, but such lists may possibly have the dual effect of attracting outsiders to
this field and encouraging those who have already written in it to pursue topics which may
be more fruitful than the writing of further textbooks.One aspect of the history of the behavioural sciences which has, until now, beenl
developing independently of both the history of science and the rest of the history of
psychology is the history of psychoanalysis. Every student of the works of Freud and
psychonanalysis owes an important debt to Ernest Jones's definitive biography. But Jones's
self-imposed brief and his closeness to Freud make his work as much a source of data for
historical analysis as it is guide to further research. As soon as the standard edition of
the complete psychological works of Freud is complete, it will be necessary to deepen and
qualify his biographical account by means of more detailed studies based on a wider appeal
to the history of science and the history of ideas. Since Jones's work appeared, a number
of collections of letters, diaries, and minutes have begun to be published, and these
provide indispensable aids to this work. The most important need is to integrate the
history of psychoanalysis with the rest of the history of psychology. Jones has done
something on this subject concerning Brentano, Fechner, Charcot, Bernheim, Liebault, and
the physiological tradition in which Freud was educated. But we still tend to forget that
Freud's language was drawn from 'physicalist physiology' in Germany and that his basic
philosophical assumption was drawn from the English tradition via Jackson's interpretation
of Herbert Spencer's doctrine of concomitance. Thus Freud's theory was dualistic, and the
form of dualism to which he adhered was psychophysical parallelism.[103] The long history
of the principle of association leads directly to Freud's work, and his use of the reflex
paradigm in the locus classicus of his theory of the mind should also be more
closely investigated.[104] Finally, the evolutionary point of view and the concept of
adaptation were central to Freud's thinking and have become significant in later
developments in psychoanalysis. I refer to the movement which was begun by Anna Freud and
Hartmann and has been further developed in America by Rapaport and others.[105] In
addition to the historical interest of these relationships, it could be shown that many of
the limitations of psychoanalytic theory are due to the fact that Freud's biological goals
were crippled by his adherence to psychophysical parallelism. Finally, the relationship
between Freud and broader issues in the history of civilisation have received a great deal
of attention, the most enlightening works on this topic being those of Brown and
Reiff.[106]Some useful articles have appeared on the history of psychoanalysis, but a number of
these lack the essential historical objectivity. Few are free from the tradition of
worship and incantation, or vituperation, which has retarded scholarship on this subject.
One topic which has been treated objectively is Freud's early period. Before the theory of
the mind with which he is identified was fully developed, Freud attempted to base his work
on brain physiology. We are extremely fortunate in having an early manuscript perserved:
"The project for a scientific psychology" (1895). A number of articles have
considered aspects of this period, although it requires further study.[107]The history of ideas about the Unconscious has been explored to some extent, but this
topic awaits a scholar with the requisite linguistic and philosophical training. Whyte has
hinted at some of the issues, and von Hartmann has displayed the philosophical depth
involved.[108]At a more general level, a series of monographs is in progress which makes useful
contributions to historical, theoretical, and philosophical aspects of psychoanalysis.
Sixteen numbers of Psychological issues have been published. To historians the most
interesting of the series are "The structure of psychoanalytic theory; a
systematizing attempt" by David Rapaport, "The influence of Freud on American
psychology" by David Shakow and Rapaport.[109] Any attempt to understand the
structure of the psychoanalytic theory must begin with the seminal articles of Rapaport,
whose tragic death has deprived us of further help from him on this topic.[110] One hopes
that his essay on the history of associationism will, in due course, be translated and
published.[111]Psychoanalysis has provided its own bibliographical apparatus: The index of
psychoanalytic writings continues to appear, as does The annual survey of
psychoanalysis.[112]Research in the history of psychiatry has been helped by the publication of Hunter and
MacAlpine's Three hundred years of psychiatry, 1535-1860.[113] Their
presentation of excerpts from several hundred works gives us some idea of the scope of
this subject, even though they have limited themselves to works in English or in English
translation. This work should help to free us from the systematic Freudian bias which
characterises the standard work in the field, Zilboorg's A history of medical
psychology,[114] which has the further disadvantage of relying heavily on secondary
and tertiary sources. The same limitation applies to the work of Schneck.[115] Indeed the
small volume by Ackerknecht provides the only useful, original and objective introduction
to this field in English. A short history of psychiatry can help the
beginner without instilling second-hand or biased knowledge.[116] The more modest works
of Bromberg and Walker do not attempt to provide standards of scholarship which can serve
as a basis for further inquiries.[117] Some hope for the development of scholarly
standards in the history of psychiatry has been provided by recent articles by Mora on the
historiography of psychiatry, which, incidentally, also shows that the new Journal of
the history of the behavioral sciences may provide an important vehicle for
responsible research in this area.[118]Since studies in the history of the behavioural sciences have not yet developed a clear
appreciation of historical method and historiography, it may be appropriate to discuss
some ways which have been suggested for approaching historical objectivity. One of these
is exemplified by an article by Krantz, which is an extremely interesting attempt to
quantifv Kuhn's hypothesis with respect to publication rates in 'anomalous' (i.e.,
potentially crisis-making) areas in psychology. The author's claims are very modest, but
the attempt is promising.[119] Further uses for quantitative methods in the history of
psychology have been developed by Cardno and Watson. In the preliminary studies which he
has published, Cardno has attempted to find firm criteria for selection of material,
identification of historical changes, and assignment of eminence. These are odd, but
curiously interesting, studies. The application of statistics to historical studies in
this way seem so far to have produced little enlightenment, if one considers the effort
involved. For example, in one article he discusses the possibility that G. H. Lewes's work
on personality has been unfairly neglected. Cardno treats this as an hypothesis, chooses
William James for comparison, and a definition by Allport for a criterion. He then chooses
parallel texts and a number of 'modern' concepts. His detailed classification of instances
and his calculations lead him to conclude that "on balance, the view is justified
that Lewes is a precursor of the modern psychology of personality, has been undeservedly
forgotten".[120] The conclusion is unexceptionable, but one hopes that Cardno will
move on to a critical exposition of Lewes, now that his I modernity' has been
statistically established. Other papers in this series, using the Rand bibliography,
encyclopedia articles, and other quasi-objective measures, may provide much more fruitful
information. Cardno is preparing a history of psychology from 1797 and 1874, and one hopes
that his objective methods will be balanced by critical exposition.Although one may derive some benefit from these quantitative methods, there are more
direct means available to the historian who wishes to place himself inside the
thought of a period. To some extent, of course, the historian of science is inevitably on
the outside, and he therefore searches through lives and letters, book reviews, referees'
reports, and other contemporary documents to try to grasp the nuances of a period and to
immerse himself in the issues as they appeared at the time. This was always good
scholarship, and Kuhn has reminded us that it may be essence of the historical method in
science. Hence one is grateful on behalf of future historians of the behavioural sciences
to learn that efforts are being made to make materials available. Some of these are a
burden to experimental scientists, others provide valuable archives for the future.[121]
Efforts are also being made to gather these materials systematically. In the area of
American psychology, an archive has been established at the University of Akron, and
psychologists are being canvassed in the hope that they may either deposit their papers or
arrange for those of others to be made available for future scholars. The same foresight
was exhibited earlier by Boring when he encouraged his colleagues to write
autobiographical sketches for the series The history of psychology and
autobiography.[122] These are of immense value, and they can sometimes provide
just the right vignette to illustrate a point. For example, the change which British
academic psychology underwent in the period after the main publications of Bain and
Spencer had appeared is perfectly illustrated by a letter from Spencer to Bain in 1902:
"I do not unfrequently think of the disgust you must feel at the fate which
has overtaken Mind that you, after establishing the thing and maintaining it for so
many years to your own cost, should not find it turned into an organ for German idealism
must be extremely exasperating . . . Oxford and Cambridge have been captured by this
old-world nonsense. What about Scotland? I suppose Hegelianism is rife there also".
Spencer withdrew his subscription a few months later.[123]Nonetheless, the historian of science has one immense advantage over his colleagues in
social and political history. On the whole, the nature of science requires that influences
be stated explicitly: science is a public activity. This is, of course, less true for
earlier periods, but as one enters the seventeenth century and progresses to the
eighteenth and then to the periodical tradition of the nineteenth century, one can discern
many influences by inspection. In the twentieth century this has become a reductio ad
absurdum with impossibly long bibliographies which fail in the responsibility to let
nonsense die, but one would still rather sift from too many references than be deprived of
essential ones. The availability of relatively complete information about influences leads
to many hours of perusal of material that turns out to be useless, but this again is
preferable to the kind of speculative, more or less plausible, suggested influences which
form the basis of a great deal of bad literary history. Similarly, the history of science
reveals an explicit continuity, between ideas. Thus, the division between a review article
and history must be arbitrary in one sense, while it is crucial in another. Indeed, review
articles are doubly useful. The professional scientist is in a position to make
contributions which the professional historian could perhaps make but only with great
difficulty. First, the man working day by day in the field, attending congresses and
keeping up with the experimental literature has a sense of relevance which can only come
from working with the issues on the operational level. He knows what is going on. Thus the
best part of Boring's books are concerned with the period in which he lived. One of the
chief tasks of the historian is to convert these raw materials provided in review articles
(and even review articles which call themselves history) into something which the
historian of science can recognise as history. These provide an invaluable guide to the actual history of science as opposed to reconstructed or logical links which are much tidier
than the actual story. This approach also helps to avoid reducing history to the study of
whether or not A is buried in B's grave. An excellent example of this kind of review is
Teuber's article on perception .[124] In the history of neurophysiology, the
nineteenth-century provides a number of helpful works. [125] Postman's Psychology in
the making purported to be history but was in fact a series of review articles: it
will also be useful in this way. [126] The series on Psychology: a study of a science attempts
to review the whole domain of current psychology and its relations with other sciences and
will be an important source for future work.[127] Similarly, as Kuhn has stressed,
textbooks provide essential keys to the norms or paradigms of science in a period. The
works of Woodworth, Hilgard and Marquis, Stevens, and Osgood, fall under this rubric.[128]
The Annual review of psychology provides periodic, exhaustive treatment of the
topics under consideration. Indeed, the topics chosen give a very clear picture of
fashions in investigation in the behavioural sciences. Similarly, 'stock-taking' articles
such as some of those contained in the Koch series, the classical paper on operationism by
Stevens, and some of the pieces in Perspectives in biology and medicine, are
also useful in this context.[129]Some of these review articles show that it is impossible to separate the history of the
behavioural sciences from philosophy. Indeed, the contents of collections of readings in
the philosophy of science and those in psychological theory overlap a great deal. Some of
the pieces which are not included in these collections are of considerable interest, e.
Pribram's "Review of theory in physiological psychology" and Bergmann's
"Theoretical psychology", both of which appeared in the Annual review of
psychology,.[130] Similarly, philosophical issues have been illuminated by reference
to the history of empirical psychology. Bergmanns case study in a philosophical
problem-"The problem of relations in classical psychology"-makes this point by
example.[131]The continuity between the history, of psychology and the history of philosophy is
considered in the standard sources, although (with the possible exception of Brett) the
result leaves a great deal to be desired. Discussion of the relationship between
psychology and the general history of science has received only very superficial treatment
at the hands of both historians of psychology and other historians of science. There is an
explanation, if not a justification, for the way in which authors of the standard
histories of psychology have avoided this issue or dealt with it briefly. Psychology can
be said to be in a 'pre-paradigm' state. That is, it has not reached a level of
development whereby most workers in the field agree on its basic assumptions, method, and
units of analysis. Similarly, prior to Newton there was no period which exhibited a single
generally accepted view about the nature of light. "Instead there were a number of
competing schools and sub-schools, most of them espousing one variant or another of
Epicurean, Aristotelian, or Platonic theory".[132] Psychology is still in this
position: in 1931, R. S. Woodworth wrote an extremely useful review of the state of
psychology which was appropriately entitled, Contemporary schools of psychology. It
is significant of developments since then that a third edition of the same work appeared
in 1964. The book was extensively revised, Woodworth having died after completing the
manuscript with a collaborator, but no one felt that there was any need to alter the title
or even the main divisions of the book. This insecurity is complemented by the fact that
only relatively recently has psychology freed itself from speculation and established the
need for experimental methods. There is an important disjunction between periods and
attitudes. But when associationism introduced introspective and then behavioural
experiments, it did not thereby cease to make philosophical assumptions: it only became
able to test theories based on these assumptions more adequately. In general, science does
not stop making philosophical assumptions when it becomes experimental. This remark would
be jejune if its contrary were not an apparent assumption in many works in the history of
psychology. Those who assume that experimental scientists do not make assumptions are
doomed to write appalling history, because they fail to take so much of it seriously. This
is not the place to discuss a similar naiveté involved in approaching experiments in this
way: 'the confrontation of an unencumbered rational n-find with nature'. The only way to
avoid involvement with philosophical assumptions is to say nothing. If anyone supposes
himself free from philosophy, the result will be that his philosophical assumptions are
held completely uncritically. This has been understood for some time in other branches of
science and its history;[133] there is some evidence that it is being appreciated by
experimentalist psychologists,[134] but the positivistic attitude of Skinner is perhaps
more characteristic.[135], The elevation of a method into a metaphysic is perhaps the
greatest danger of this point of view, as Bergmann has admirably shown in the case of
Watson.[136] Amateur historians, however, apparently have not heard the news. The
reluctance with which American psychology departments accepted historical theses is but
one example of this fear of non-experimental studies, based, though it is, on a category
mistake. Much of this prejudice can be traced to the alliance between operationism,
behaviourism, and logical positivism. This development is now becoming history, while its
effects are still very apparent.[137] A most interesting parallel study could be made of
operationism in physics and psychology, including its continued success in the latter in
contrast to its decline in the former.If we move away from this particular issue to the more general topics of mutual
interest between philosophy and psychology, the whole area of psycho-physics and the study
of the specific energies of nerves should be considered in conjunction with the doctrine
of primary and secondary qualities. Similarly, the limitations of psycho-physics in
achieving a relationship between physically measurable quantities and subjectively
experienced qualities have played a significant part in influencing ideas in subjects as
far afield as anthropology.[138]It is altogether appropriate that philosophers of mind should be directly concerned
with the writings of experimental psychologists, both in their empirical and in their
theoretical works. As Taylor has recently reminded us, "the neo-behaviorist or
stimulus-response (SR) theories ... are, in many ways the descendants of classical
empiricism".[139] Thus, the history of the behavioural sciences properly works hand
in hand with philosophy. This is not merely an underlabourer view of history serving
philosophy which is, in turn, the underlabourer of science. Rather, it is based on the
assumption that the philosophy of science must show its relevance to actual problems in
science. History spells out the assumptions by providing the perspective which is
often unattainable within the science itself. Works like those of Strawson and Taylor
present important philosophical theses which bear upon the reading of the history of
psychology.[140] The books themselves are a-historical to a large extent. To weigh
accurately the merits and applicability of the fundamentally important approach of
descriptive metaphysics, one must do the historical work required. Therefore, the
historian must say to the philosopher of mind that he must become a better historian, just
as the historian of the behavioural sciences must become a better philosopher. Thus,
important works on the philosophy of mind must be brought to bear on historical issues but
must also improve their own history. [141]Given the standards of scholarship which exist in the history of the behavioural
sciences, it is fortunate that the subject has such useful links with other fields.
Related works can serve as examples to those who are at present at work in the history of
the behavioural sciences. For example, Aram Vartanian, a professor of modern language has
provided us with a very sensitive monograph on La Mettrie and an interpretation of the
Cartesian heritage which challenges the traditional view.[142] Owsei Temkin, a professor
of the history of medicine, as already mentioned, has enriched our understanding of
phrenology, the physiology of Magendie, and the concept of irritability. Finally, Sir
Geoffrey Jefferson, a neuro-surgeon now deceased, has shown just how well an amateur can
write the history of neurology in his essays on Descartes, Spencer, and cerebral
localization.[143] Work of an extremely high standard is to be expected from professional
historians of science, but one is, nevertheless, grateful when articles appear such as
those of A. C. Crombie on the development of perceptual studies.[144] It is also
interesting to note that a recent writer in the history of philosophy has taken an account
of both the philosophical and psychological works which were significant in his own
subject.[145] Similarly, helpful background to writing in the history of the behavioural
sciences could be provided if its students would avail themselves of works written from
different perspectives.[146]This review began by noting that the history of the behavioural sciences has received
some sort of status, while most of its text has been concerned with reservations which
must be expressed about recent work and indications of further research which is needed.
The single most important development in the field which gives hope for the future is the
appearance of the Journal of the history of the behavioral sciences. I confess that
I read the first article in the new journal with dismay. It is, of course, altogether
fitting that Professor Boring contributed the piece, and it is a compliment to the new
journal that he was prepared to do so. But its subject-the date of the founding of Wundt's
laboratory-was an unfortunate choice, given the tendency to perseveration which has been
discussed above. It is also unfortunately symptomatic of three limitations from which the
history of psychology has suffered: great men (whom to worship?), great insights, and
great dates. There is not space to review the contents of the journal in detail, although
a reading of the first volume leads one to have mixed feelings. The lack of high standards
of scholarship which has been discussed above is still in evidence, but this is
inevitable. The range of interest in the new journal is one of its most heartening
features. The book reviews are disappointing, and one might suggest that the subject would
benefit immensely from critical essay reviews rather than the extremely polite, though
perfunctory, pieces which have appeared so far. I would like to restrict my detailed
remarks on this journal to praise of one article: "From physics to ethnology: Franz
Boas' arctic expedition as a problem in the historiography of the behavioral
sciences".[147] I should say right away that this is the sort of research which the
history of the behavioral sciences sorely needs. It is a highly original, excellent, and
detailed treatment of Boas's development from physics to psycho-physics to geography and
finally to his work in anthropology. We are shown in detail how his studies in physics led
him to consider the philosophical basis of perception and finally to concern himself with
the problem of adaptation. This is unequivocal demonstration of the continuity of the
problems of knowledge and adaptation from physics to the social sciences-a justification
by example for this journal and a demonstration of the links between the behavioural
sciences, the philosophy of science, and general biology. The problems of knowing and
living are thus continuous, as Spencer saw and Darwin implied. From situational factors
involved in the perception of an experimental physicist to situational factors in
perception of environment of the Eskimos of Baffinland-this article, though written in a
narrower context, rivals Temkin's classical study of the philosophical background of
Magendie's physiology as an exercise in illuminating the philosophical assumptions of
scientists. One. could offer this piece of research by a working anthropologist as
a model for future studies in the history of the behavioural sciences.In closing I would mention two institutional activities which bear on the study of the
history of the behavioural sciences. First, the American Psychological Association has
given formal recognition to these activities by setting up a Division of the History of
Psychology. The group which achieved this is to a great extent the same one which
established the Journal of the history of the behavioral sciences, and it is hoped
that these two developments will help to improve the standards of scholarship in this
field. Secondly, the American National Institutes of Health have established a History of
the Life Sciences Study Section, which makes grants for research in the study of the
biological and related (including psychological) sciences. There are also funds for
establishing departments or institutes of the history of medicine and science and
fellowships for potential teachers. An analysis of the grants given by this organisation
between 1959 and 1963 shows that they approved half of the projects and gave two-thirds of
the fellowships for which applications were completed .[148]REFERENCES1. Postman, 1962; Watson, 1963; Hearnshaw, 1964; Miller, 1964. Two collections of notes
have also appeared: Roback, 1961; Esper, 1964. The standard work by Flugel has also
appeared in an edition revised by West, 1964.2. Boring, 1961; Boring, 1963; Herrnstein and Boring, 1965.3. Agassi, 1963.4. Boring, 1963, p. 80.5. See also Watson, 1953, 1959, 1960[a], 1961. Professor Watson and Dr Eric T. Carlson
were the prime movers in founding the new Journal of the history of the behavioral
sciences, which Watson now edits. He has also been active in the founding of a
Division of the History of Psychology in the American psychological Association.6. Head, 1926; Boring, 1950; Riese and Hoff, 1950-1; Stokey, 1954; Walker, 1957;
Brazier, 1959; Tizard, 1959; Sheer, 1961. I would except from this rather perseverative
study of cerebral localization the original articles of Jefferson, 1960; Meyer, 1960;
Zangwill, 1961; Clarke, 1963; Brazier, 1961; Benton and Joynt, 1960. One should also
mention the rather imaginative historical reconstruction of Ferrier's discoveries by
Thorwald, 1960 (Chapter 1). The bibliographies of Brazier, 1959 and Sheer, 1961 are a rich
mine of sources for original research.7. I make no comments on H. G. Gouch's treatment of clinical versus statistical
prediction or J. P. McKee and M. J. Honsik on the sucking behavior of animals as an
illustration of the nature-nurture question. In his discussion of the mechanism of hunger
and thirst, M. R. Rosenzweig provides a detailed and extremely thorough review of the
literature up to the present.8. Cf. Wilkie, 1959 and Gllispie, 1956, 1959.9. Spencer, 1887. The Preface to the separately printed version of "The factors of
organic evolution" contains material of importance to the history of psychology,
which does not appear in the version which was reprinted in Spencer's Essays. Cf.
Romanes, 1895.10. Postman, 1947.11. Waters, 1934.12. Cason, 1932.13. Journal of verbal learning and verbal behavior. Cf. Krasner, 1958;
Salzinger, 1959.14. Gomulicki, 1953.15. Rapaport. 1942, p. 265.16. Especially for historical material on Binet and Féré, 1887.17. Boring, 1963, p. 109.18. I am treating Boring (1961) and Boring (1963) as a unit. The tables of contents of
these works should be consulted to determine which items are contained in which book.19. If any of his works is to be excepted from this judgement it would be Boring
(1942).20. Boring, 1963[a].21. This is an expanded version of the account published in the 4th volume of the
series A history of psychology in autobiography, Boring, 1952, pp. 27--52. Cf.
Murchison, 1930,1932,1936.22. Mercier, 1925, pp. 42-3.23. James, 1924, pp. 107-8, 111-112.24. Boring, 1961, pp. 95-98.25. Boring, 1961, pp. 110-111, 130. Cf. his obituary of Titchener in Ibid., pp.
246-265 and the dedication of Boring, 1950.26. Boring, 1950, pp. 329-338, 384-385; 1961, pp. 213 and 215.27. Boring, 1963, pp. 159-184.28. Quoted in Wiener, 1949, p. 19.29. Bain, 1855, pp. v-vi.30. Bain, 1868, p. 59.31. Ibid., pp. 64-73.32. Ibid., pp. 296-306.33. Ibid., p. 296. Cf. Bain, 1855, p. 289.34. Boring, 1950, p. 236.35. Müller, 1838, 1842.36. Boring, 1961, p. 15.37. Boring, 1950, p. vii.38. This point has been most clearly appreciated by G. H. Lewes. See Lewes, 1857, pp.
629-645. It was made with more reservations in the later editions: cf. Lewes, 1871, pp.
412-454.39. Spoerl, 1935-6.40. Ibid., p. 224.41. Ibid., p. 225.42. Boring, 1950, p. 53. Incidentally, Gall's theory had 27 faculties, not 37. One of
the arguments used against phrenology was the way its list of 'fundamental' faculties kept
growing.43. Ibid., p. 59.44. Boring, 1942, p. 94; 1963, pp. 171 and 182.45. Watson, 1963, p. 226; Postman, 1962, p. 34.46. Head,1926.47. Boring, 1963, p. 329; Temkin, 1946, 1946[a], 1947; Olmsted, 1944; cf. Olmsted,
1953.48. Passmore, 1957. A comparison of this work with the one by Flugel in the same series
makes my point nicely, and the two revisions Flugel's work has undergone drive it home.49. Kuhn, 1964, p. 2.50. For example, Brazier, 1959[a]; Magoun, 1958; Sheer, 1961.51. Kuhn, 1964, p. 3. Cf. Buchdahl, 1965.52. Herrnstein, R. J. in Contemparary psychology, ix (1964) 195.53. See also Butterfield, 1931.54. Stocking, 1965[a].55. Burtt, 1932, pp. 318-319.56. Balz, 1951, p. 196. See also Whitehead, 1926 and Dijksterhuis, 1961 on the problems
of primary and secondary qualities and final causes.57. Crombie, 1964, Vartanian, 1953, 1960; Halévy, 1952; Albee, 1962.58. Quoted in Murphy, 1949, p. 269.59. Freud (1891) 1953. Cf. the Introduction by Stengel and Stengel, 1954; Riese, 1956,
1958; Jones, l953.60. Watson, 1913, 1925. Cf. Bergmann, 1956. See also R. I. Watson, 1963, p. 376:
"Anything smacking of the mental was anathema to Watson. It was as if to him the
mental was outside this rational world of ours, running in the dark with the other ghosts
and goblins."61. Bain, 1903, pp. 162-188. Strawson has demonstrated the philosophic significance of
this point: material objects are the basic particulars of both ordinary language and of
science. See Strawson, 1959.62. Mason, 1962, Chs. 27 and 28.63. Spencer, 1904, Vol. 1, p. 470.64. Halévy, 1952.65. Ribot, 1873.66. Warren, 1921.67. Brett, 1930, p. 45.68. Murphy, 1949, p. 283.69. Hume, 1738, Bk. I, sect. 4 (Everyman Edition, 1911, p. 21).70. Hartley, 1749, Vol. 1, p. 6.71. Oldfield and Oldfield, 1951.72. Rand, 1923.73. Bower, 1881.74. Gibbs, 1965. Priestley's works on the mind and the controversies surrounding his
psychological and philosophical writings deserve study. His Theological and miscellaneous
works were published (1817-32).75. Schofield, 1963.76. Halévy, 1952.77. Lewes, 1857, and later editions. Lewes added chapters on Hartley, Erasmus Darwin,
Cabanis, and Gall to the second edition (1857) of this work. His reasons for adding these
figures-if they could be discovered should shed light on the development of psychology as
a biological science in the 1850s.78. King-Hele, 1963, pp. 52 and 48.79. George, 1964, pp. 272-273, 235, 243-246.80. Eiseley, 1959[a], Ch. xi. Cf. Eiseley, 1959.81. Some of the evidence which supports this claim may be found in Chambers, 1884, pp.
xxx, 365-368, 373, 379-383; Combe, 1827; Gibbon, 1878, Vol. II, pp. 187-189; [Chevenix],
1828; Lewes, 1857, pp. 629-645; Lewes, 1871, Vol. II, pp. 412-454; Temkin, 1947, pp.
307-313; Davies, 1955; Wallace, 1905, Vol. I, pp. 234-236, 257-262; Wallace, 1898, Ch.
xvi; Romanes, 1895, pp. 20-22; Spencer, 1904, Vol. 1, pp. 200-203, 225-228, 246-247, 297,
378-379, 540-543; Spencer, 1908, p. 40; Spencer, 1851, pp. 75-89; Spencer, 1855, pp.
606-611; Jefferson, 1960, pp. 35-44; Denton, 1921. A similar claim could be made for
French naturalism and positivism: see Greene, 1959 and Temkin, 1947.82. Amacher, 1964. On phrenology, see Laycock, 185983. Laycock, 1840, 1845, 1855, 1860. Cf. Crichton-Browne, 1938, pp. 40-41.84. Wiener (1949) discusses this period very competently. There is additional material
in Perry (1935).85. Dewey, 1896.86. Dewey, 1900.87. Dewey, 1910, pp. 1-20.88. Dewey, 1910, pp. 8-9. Re James and Dewey, see Dykhuizen, 1962; White, 1943;
Hofstadter, 1955, esp. Ch. vii; Perry, 1935, esp. Ch. lxxxi. See also Madden, 1963;
Schilpp, 1939; Mead, 1936, Dewey, 1931, 1930, 1963; Thomas, 1962; Harrison, 1963.89. Angell, 1907, pp. 439-440.90. Titchener, 1898.91. Ruckmich, 1913; Dallenbach, 1915.92. Watson, 1913, p. 463.93. Watson, 1916.94. Bergmann, 1956.95. The primary literature of functionalism is readily available in the textbooks and
journals of the period, while many of the papers await investigation. Important secondary
sources for functional psychology include Heidbreder, 1933, Chs. 4-6; Carr, 1930,
Pillsbury, 1929; Murphy, 1949; Boring, 1950; Hilgard and Marquis, 1940; Hilgard, 1948,
1960; Marx and Hillix, 1963; Woodworth, 1951. The Presidential Addresses to the American
Psychological Association, which appeared in the Psychological review, would
themselves form the basis for an interesting study.96. See, however, Picavet, 1891; Rosen, 1946; Temkin, 1946 and the suggestions
contained in the writings of Vartanian, 1953, 1960.97. Fearing, 1930; Canguilhem, 1955. Cf. Liddell, 1960.98. I have not seen the unpublished doctoral dissertation (Oxford) by R. K. French:
Robert Whytt (1714-66) and the problem of the seat of the soul (1965
or 1966).99. Roback, 1927.100. Allport, 1937.101. A beginning can be made from the works of Guer, 1749; Warden, 1927; Cohen, 1936;
Rosenfield, 1941; Hastings, 1936; Jennings, 1906; Washburn, 1908; Carr, 1927; Romanes,
1882, 1883.102. Temkin, 1964.103. See Riese, 1958; Stengel, 1954, 1963.104. Freud, 1954, Ch. 7.105. Anna Freud, 1937; Hartmann, 1958, 1964; Erikson, 1959; Rapaport (in Erikson,
1959); Rapaport and Gill, 1959.106. Brown, 1959; Reff, 1959.107. Freud, 1954; Bernfield, 1950; Kris, 1950; Riese, 1958; Stengel, 1954; Pribram,
1962; Anderson, 1962; Greenfield and Lewis, 1965; Amacher, 1965.108. Whyte, 1960; Von Hartmann, 1931. Cf. Margetts, 1953; Riese, 1958[a]; Sours, 1961.109. Rapaport, 1960; Shakow and Rapaport, 1964. Other works in the same series are
Erikson, 1959; Gill, 1963; Amacher, 1965.110. See Bibliography (below).111. Rapaport, 1938.112. Frosch and Ross, 1964; Grinstein (in progress).113. Hunter and MacAlpine, 1963.114. Zilboorg and Henry, 1941.115. Schenck, 1960.116. Ackerknecht, 1959.117. Walker, 1957, Bromberg, 1959.118. Mora, 1965, 1965[a].119. Krantz, 1965.120. Cardno, 1962[a].121. Many recent symposia consist of papers followed by discussion, for example,
Jeffress, 1951; Kruse, 1957; Brazier, 1959[a], 1959[b], 1960; Delafresnaye, 1961. The
popularity of symposia in the behavioural sciences has produced something of an
'information explosion'.122. Murchison, 1930, 1932, 1936; Boring, 1952.123. Spencer, 1908, pp. 457-458.124. Teuber, 1959.125. Tenon et al., 1809; Anon., 1824; Carpenter, 1846; Hunt, 1868-69; Dodds,
1878; Bastian, 1887; Mills, 1890; Soury, 1899.126. Postman, 1962.127. Koch, 1959-63.128. Woodworth, 1931, 1964; Hilgard, 1948; Hilgard and Marquis, 1940; Stevens, 1951,.
Osgood, 1953.129. Koch, 1959-63; Stevens, 1939.130. Pribram, 1960; Bergmann, 1953. Cf. Kretch and Klein, 1952.131. Bergmann, 1952.132. Kuhn, 1964, p. 12.133. Burtt, 1932, pp. 225 sqq; Whitehead, 1925, pp. 80-82; Lovejoy, 1960, p. 43;
Hesse, 1961, pp. v, 98, 125, passim.134. Livingstone, 1962, p. 60.135. Skinner, 1959.136. Bergmann, 1956.137. Bridgman, 1927, 1959; Boring, 1933; Stevens, 1939, Pratt, 1939; Brunswick, 1952;
Marx, 1951; Marx and Hillix, 1963.138. See Stocking, 1965, p. 57.139. Taylor, 1964, p. III.140. Strawson, 1958; Taylor, 1964.141. Smythics, 1965; Ramsey. 1965.142. Vartanian, 1953, 1960.143. Jefferson, 1960. See also Keele, 1957.144. Crombie, 1964, 1964[a], 1964[b].145. Randall, 1962.146. For example, see Macintosh, 1860; Stewart, 1860; Lange, 1875; Stephen, 1902; Merz,
1904-12, Boas, 1925; Willey, 1934, 1940; Cassirer, 1951.147. Stocking, 1965.148. Bulletin of the history of medicine, xxxvii (1963) 472-474.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Note:This review makes no claim to comprehensiveness. A full list of primary and
secondary sources in the history of psychology and in some other aspects of the history of
the behavioural sciences can be gathered from the following sources:Baldwin, Dictionary of philosophy and psychology, Vol. III (a bibliography
prepared by Benjamin Rand, which appeared in 1902).Psychological index (to 1935).Psychological abstracts (1927-).Isis annual bibliographies (very incomplete in this area).Recent work in the history of medicine.History of the behavioral sciences newsletter.Contemporary psychology.The following bibliography includes a number of items of interest which are not
mentioned in the text. These include standard references.Erwin H. Ackerknecht and Henri Vallois, Franz Joseph Gall, inventor of phrenology
and his collection, trans. C. St. Léon (Madison: Department of history of
medicine, 1956). Erwin H. Ackerknecht, A short history of psychiatry (N.Y.: Hafner, 1959).Joseph Agassi, Towards an historiography of science, in History and theory: studies
in the philosophy of history, 2 (The Hague: Mouton, 1963).Ernest Albee, A history of English utilitarianism (1901, reprinted N.Y.:
Collier, 1962).Gordon W. Allport, Personality: a psychological interpretation (N.Y: Holt,
1937).M. Peter Amacher, "Thomas Laycock, I. M. Sechenov, and the reflex are
concept", Bulletin of the history of medicine, xxxviii (1964) 168-183.M. Peter Amacher, Freud's neurological education and its influence on psychoanalytic theory (N.Y: International Universities, 1965).O. Anderson, Studies in prehistory of psychoanalysis: the etiology of
psychoneuroses and some related themes in Sigmund Freud's scientific
writings and letters, 1886-1896 (Stockholm, Svenska Bokförlaget, 1962).James R. Angell, "The province of functional psychology", Psychological
review, xiv (1907) 61-91 (reprinted in Dennis, 1948, pp. 439-456).James R. Angell, "The influence of Danvin on psychology", Psychological review,
xvi (1909) 152-169.Anon. "Recent discoveries on the physiology of the nervous system", Edinburgh
medical and surgical journal, xxi (1824) 141-159.Alexander Bain, The senses.and the intellect (London: John W. Parker, 1855; 3rd
ed., 1868).Alexander Bain, The emotions and the will (London: John W. Parker, 1859; 3rd
ed., 1875).Alexander Bain, Dissertations on leading philosophical topics (London: Longmans,
1903). James M. Baldwin (ed.), Dictionary of philosophy and psychology, 3 vols. in 4
(N.Y: Macmillan, 1901; 2nd ed., 1925. Reprinted Gloucester, Mass: Smith, 1940, 1957,
1960).James M. Baldwin, History of psychology: a sketch and an interpretation, 2 vols. (London: Watts, 1913).Albert G. A. Balz, Cartesian studies (N.Y: Columbia, 1951).Gerhardt von Bonin (trans.), Some papers on the cerebral cortex (Springfield,
Ill: Thomas, 1960).Ernst Cassirer, The philosophy of the enlightenment, trans. F. C. A. Koelln and
J. T. Pettegrove (Princeton, 1951 . Reprinted Boston: Beacon, 1955).H. Charlton Bastian, The brain as an organ of mind (London: Kegan Paul, 1880).H. Charlton Bastian, "The 'muscular sense'; its nature and cortical
localization", Brain, x (1887), 1-89.Arthur Benton and Robert J. Joynt, "Early descriptions of aphasia", Archives of
Neurology, iii (1960) 205-222.Gustav Bergmann, "The problem of relations in classical psychology", Philosophical quarterly, ii (1952) 140-152.Gustav Bergmann, "Theoretical Psychology", Annual review of psychology,
iv (1953) 435-458.Gustav Bergmann, "The contribution of John B. Watson", Psychological
review, lxiii (1956) 265-276.Siegfried Bernfield, "Freud's scientific beginnings", American imago, vi (1949) 3-36.Alfred Binet and Charles Féré, Animal magnetism (London: Kegan Paul, 1887).George Boas, French philosophers of the romantic period (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins, 1925).Edwin G. Boring, Sensation and perception in the history of experimental
psychology (N.Y: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1942).Edwin G. Boring, A history of experimental psychology, 2nd ed. (N.Y:
Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1950).Edwin G. Boring (ed.), A history of psychology in autobiography, Vol. IV
(Worcester, Mass,:Clark, 1952).Edwin G. Boring, Psychologist at large: an autobiography and selected essays (N.Y:
Basic, 1961).Edwin G. Boring, History, psychology, and science: selected papers.
Edited by Robert I. Watson and Donald T. Campbell (N.Y. and London: Wiley, 1963). PP. xii
+ 372. 68s.Edwin G. Boring, The physical dimensions of consciousness (N.Y: Century,
1933. Reprinted N.Y: Dover, 1963[a]).George S. Bower, Hartley and James Mill (London: Low, Marston, Searle, and
Rivington, 1881).Mary A. B. Brazier, "Rise of neurophysiology in the nineteenth century", Journal
of neurophysiology, xx (1957) 212-226.Mary A. B. Brazier, "The historical development of neurophysiology", in J.
Field (ed.) Handbook of physiology - neurophysiology, Vol. I (Washington:
American physiological society, 1959) 1-58.Mary A. B. Brazier (ed.), The central nervous system and behavior, 3 vols. (N.Y:
Macy, 1959[a], 1959[b], 1960).Mary A. B. Brazier, A history of the electrical activity of the brain: the first half-century (London: Pitman, 1961).George S. Brett, Brett's history of psychology (3 vols., 1912-21) Ed. and
Abridged by R. S. Peters (London: Allen and Unwin, 1953).George S. Brett, "Historical development of the theory of emotions", in M. L.
Reymert (ed.) Feelings and emotions (Worcester, Mass: Clark, 1928) 388-397.George S. Brett, "Associationism and 'act' psychology: a historical
retrospect", in Carl M. Murchison (ed.), Psychologies of 1930 (Worcester,
Mass: Clark, 1930) 39-58.P.W. Bridgman, The logic of modern physics (N.Y: Macmillan, 1927).P.W. Bridgman,The way things are (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1959).Donald E. Broadbent, Behaviour (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1961).Walter Bromberg, The mind of man, a history of psychotherapy and psychoanalysis (N.Y: Harper, 1959).Chandler McC. Brooks and P. F. Cranefield (eds.), The historical development of
physiological thought (N.Y: Hafner, 1959).Norman O. Brown, Life against death: the psychoanaiytic meaning of history (Middletown,
Conn: Weslevan, 1959. Reprinted N.Y: Random House, 1959).Joseph Brozek "Current status of psychology in the U.S.S.R.", Annual
review of psychology, xiii (1962) 515-566.Joseph Brozek, "Recent developments in Soviet psychology", Annual review
of psychology, xv (1964) 493-594. (Cf. earlier volumes for review on the same subject
by other authors.) Egon Brunswick, The conceptual framework of psychology (Chicago, 1952).Gerd Buchdahl, "A revolution in historiography of science", History of
science, iv (1965) 55-69.John W. Burrow, "Evolution and anthropology in the 1860's: the anthropological
society of London, 1863-71", Victorian studies, vii (1963) 137-154.Cyril Burt, "Gustav Theodor Fechner: Elements der Psychopkysik,
1860-1960", British journal of statistical psychology, xiii (1960) 1-10.Cyril Burt, "Galton's contribution to psychology", Bulletin of the British
psychological society, xlv (ig6i) 10-2I.Cyril Burt, "Francis Galton and his contributions to psychology", British journal of statistical psychology, xv (1962) 1-41.Edwin A. Burtt, The metaphysical foundations of modern physical science, 2nd ed.
(London: Routledge, 1932).Herbert Butterfield, The whig interpretation of history (London: Bell, 1931).Georges Canguilhem, La formation du concept de réflexe aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles (Paris: Presses Universitaires, 1955).Leonard Carmichael, "Sir Charles Bell: a contribution to the history of
physiological psychology", Psychological review, xxxiii (1927) 188-217.J.A. Cardno, "Bain and physiological psychology", Australian journal of
psychology, vii (1955) 108-119.J.A. Cardno, "Bain as a social psychologist", Australian journal of
Psychology, viii (1956) 66-76.J. A. Cardno, "Judgement in the history of psychology: literature, science, or
understanding", Australian journal of psychology, xiii (1961) 175-183.J.A. Cardno, "Natural limits and change of content in the history of
psychology", Psychological record, xii (1962) 289-298.J.A. Cardno, "Personality and self, Lewes and James", Psychological
record, xii (1962[a]) 45-52.J. A. Cardno, "The network of reference: comparison in the history of
psychology", Journal of general psychology, lxviii (1963) 141-156.William B. Carpenter, "Noble on the brain and its physiology", British and
foreign medical review, xxii (1846) 488-544.Harvey Carr, "The interpretation of animal mind", Psychological review, xxxiv
(1927) 87-106.Harvey Carr, "Functionalism", in Carl Murchison (ed.), Psychologies of
1930 (Worcester: Clark Univ. Press, 1930) 59-80.Hulsey Cason, "The pleasure-pain theory of learning", Psychological
review, xxxix (1932) 440-466.Robert Chambers, Vestiges of the natural history of creation, 12th ed.
(Edinburgh: Chambers, 1884).[Richard Chevenix], "Gall and Spurzheim-phrenology", Foreign quarterly
review, ii (1828) 1-59.Edwin Clarke, "The early history of the cerebral ventricles", Transactions
and studies of the college of physicians of Philadelphia, 4th
series, xxx (1962) 85-89.Edwin Clarke, "Aristotelian concepts of the form and function of the brain", Bulletin
of the history of medicine, xxxvii (1963) 1-14.Edwin Clarke and Jerry Stannard, "Aristotle on the anatomy of the brain", Journal
of the history of medicine and allied sciences, xviii (1963) 130-148.L.D. Cohen, "Descartes and More on the beast-machine", Annals of science, i
(1936) 48-61.George Combe, Essay on the constitution of man, and its relation to external objects (Edinburgh: Neill, 1827).James Crichton-Browne, The doctor remembers (London: Duckworth, 1938).A. C. Crombie, "Early concepts of the senses and the mind", Scientific
American, ccx (1964) 108-116.A. C. Crombie, "Kepler: de modo visionis", in I. B. Cohen and R. Taton
(eds.), Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, Vol. II (Paris: Hermann, 1964[a])
135-172.A. C. Crombie, "The study of the senses in Renaissance science", in Ithaca:
proceedings of the tenth international congress of history of science, 1962,
Vol. I (Paris: Hermann, 1964[b]) 93-114.K.M. Dallenbach, "The history and derivation of the word 'function' as a
systematic term in psychology", American journal of psychology, xxvi (1915)
473-484.Erasmus Darwin, Zoonomia: or, the laws of organic life, 2 vols. (London:
Johnson, 1794-6).John D. Davies, Phrenology, fad and science, a 19th century American crusade (New
Haven: Yale, 1955).J.F. Delafresnaye (ed.), Brain mechanism and learning, a symposium (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1961).Wayne Dennis, Readings in the history of psychology (N.Y:
Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1948).George B. Denton, "Early psychological theories of Herbert Spencer", American journal of psychology, xxxii (1921) 5-15.Max Dessoir, Outlines of the history of psychology, trans. Donald Fisher (N.Y:
Macmillan, 1912).John Dewey, "The reflex are concept in psychology", Psychological review, iii
(1896) 357-370.John Dewey, "Psychology and social practice", Psychological review, vii
(1900) 105-124.John Dewey, The influence of Darwin on philosophy (N.Y: Holt, 1910).John Dewey' "From absolutism to experimentalism", in George P. Adams and W.
P. Montague (eds.), Contemporary American philosophy, Vol. II (N.Y:
Macmillan, 1930) 3-27.John Dewey, "George Herbert Mead", Journal of philosophy, xxviii
(1931) 309-314.John Dewey, Philosophy and civilization (N.Y: Minton, Balch, 1931. Reprinted
N.Y: Capricorn, 1963).George Dickie, "Francis Hutcheson and the theory of motives", American
journal of psychology, lxxiv (1961) 625-629.E. J. Dijksterhuis, The mechanization of the world picture, trans. (Oxford,
1961).W. J. Dodds, "On the localisation of the functions of the brain: being an
historical and critical analysis of the question", Journal of anatomy and
physiology, xii (1878) 340-363, 454-494, 636-660.Flanders Dunbar, Emotions and bodily change: a survey of literature on psychosomatic
inter-relationships 1910-1953, 4th ed. (N.Y: Columbia, 1954).George Dykhuizen, "John Dewey and the university of Michigan", Journal of
the history of ideas, xxiii (1962) 513-544.Loren Eiseley, "Alfred Russel Wallace", Scientific American, cc (1959)
70-84.Loren Eiseley, Darwin's century, evolution and the men who discovered it
(London: Gollancz, 1959[a]).Erik H. Erikson, Identity and the life cycle (N.Y: International Universities,
1959).Erwin A. Esper, A history of psychology (Philadelphia: Saunders, 1964).Jay W. Fay, American psychology before William James (New Brunswick, New Jersey:
Rutgers, 1939).Franklin Fearing, Reflex action: a study in the history of physiological psychology (London:
Ballière, 1930).J.C. Flugel, A hundred years of psychology (1933), 3rd ed. revised by D. J. West
(London: Methuen, 1964).Anna Freud, The ego and the mechanisms of defence, trans. Cecil Baines (London:
Hogarth, 1937).Sigmund Freud, On aphasia: a critical study (1891). trans. E. Stengel (N.Y:
International Universities, 1953).Sigmund Freud, The interpretation of dreams (1901), trans. James Strachey
(London: Allen and Unwin, 1954).Sigmund Freud, An outline of psychoanalysis (1938), trans. J. Strachey (N.Y:
Norton, 1949).Sigmund Freud, The origins of Psycho-analysis, letters to Wilhelm Fliess, drafts and
notes.. 1887-1902. Introduction by Ernst Kris (N.Y: Basic. 1954).John Frosch and Nathaniel Ross (eds.),The annual survey of psychoanalysis, Vol.
VIII (N.Y: International Universities, 1964).John F. Fulton, Selected readings in the history of physiology (Springfield,
Ill: Thomas, 1930).H. M. Gardiner, R. C. Metcalf, and J. G. Beebe-Center, Feeling and emotion:
a history of theories (N.Y: American Book Co., 1937).Wilma George, Biologist philosopher, a study of the life, and writings of
Alfred Russel Wallace (London: Abelard-Schuman, 1964).Charles Gibbon, The life of George Combe, author of "The constitution of man",
2 vols. (London: Macmillan, 1878).F. W. Gibbs, Joseph Priestley, adventurer in science and champion of truth (London: Nelson, 1965).Merton M. Gill, Topography and systems in psychoanalytic theory (N.Y:
International Universities, 1963).Charles C. Gillispie, "The formation of Lamarck's evolutionary theory", Archives
inter-nationales d'histoire des sciences, ix (1956) 323-338.Charles C. Gillispie, "Lamarck and Darwin in the history of science", in B.
Glass et al. Forerunners of Darwin: 1745-I859 (Baltimore: Hopkins, 1959)
.265-291.Bronislaw R. Gomulicki, "The development and present status of the trace theory,
of memory", British journal of psychology monograph supplements, xxix
(Cambridge, 1953). Sir Gordon Gordon-Taylor and E. W. Walls, Sir Charles Bell: his life and times (London:
Livingstone, 1958).Kathleen M. Grange, "Pinel and eighteenth-century psychiatry,", Bulletin
of the history of medicine, xxxv (1961) 442-453.John C. Greene, "Biology and social theory in the nineteenth century: Auguste
Comte and Herbert Spencer", in Marshall Clagett (ed.) Critical problem in the
history of science (Madison, Wisconsin: 1959) 419-446.Norman S. Greenfield and William C. Lewis (eds.), Psychoanalysis and current biological thought (Madison, Wisconsin: 1965).Alexander Grinstein, The index of psychoanalytic writings, .5 vols. (N.Y:
International Universities, in progress).Jean A. Guer, Histoire critique de lame des betes contenant les sentimens des
philosophes anciens et ceux des modernes sur cette matière, 2 vols.
(Amsterdam: Chanquion, 1749).Arnold E. S. Gussin, "Jacques Loeb: the man and his tropism theory of animal
conduct", Journal of the history of medicine, xviii (1963) 321-336.Elie Halévy, The growth of philosophic radicalism, trans. Mary Morris (London:
Faber & Faber, 1952).D.W. Hamlyn, Sensation and perception. a history of the philosophy of
perception (London: Routledge, 1961).Ross Harrison, "Functionalism and its historical significance", Genetic
psychology monographs, lxviii (1963) 387-423.David Hartley, Observations on man, his frame, his duty and his expectations, 2
vols. (London: Leake & Frederick. 1749).Eduard von Hartmann, Philosophy of the unconscious (1868), trans. William C.
Coupland (London: Routledge, 1931).Heinz Hartmann, Ego psychology and the problem of adaptation, trans. David
Rapaport (N.Y: International Universities, 1958).Heinz Hartman, Essays on ego psychology (N.Y: International Universities, 1964).Hester Hastings, Man and beast in French thought in the eighteenth century (Baltimore: Hopkins, 1936).Webb Haymaker (ed.), The founders of neurology, one hundred biographical
sketches (Springfield, Ill: Thomas, 1953).Henry Head, Aphasia and kindred disorders of speech, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1926).L. S. Hearnshaw, A short history of British psychology, 1840-1940 (London:
Methuen, 1964). Pp. xii + 331. 35s.Edna Heidbreder, Seven psychologies (N.Y: Appleton, 1933).Richard J. Herrnstein and Edwin G. Boring, A source book in the history of
psychology (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1965). Pp. xx + 636. £5.Mary B. Hesse, Forces and fields (London: Nelson, 1961).Ernest R. Hilgard, Theories of learning (N.Y: Century, 1948; 2nd ed., 1958).Emest R. Hilgard and D. G. Marquis, Conditioning and learning (N.Y:
Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1940); 2nd ed. Revised by Gregory A. Kimble (London: Methuen,
1961).Ernest R. Hilgard, "Psychology after Darwin", in Sol Tax, (ed.) Evolution
After Darwin, Vol. II (Chicago, 1960) 269-287.Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American thought, revised ed.
(Boston: Beacon, 1955).D. T. Howard, "The influence of evolutionary doctrine on psychology", Psychological review, xxxiv (1927) 305-312.W. S. Hulin, A short history of psychology (N.Y: Holt 1934).David Hume, A treatise on human nature (1738) (reprint, 2 vols. London:
Everyman, 1911).James Hunt, "On the localisation of the functions of the brain with special
reference to the faculty of articulate language", Anthropological review, vi
(1868) 329-345; vii (1869) 100-116, 210-214.Richard Hunter and Ida MacAlpine, Three hundred years of psychiatry -1535-1860 (London:
Oxford, 1963).Robert L. Isaacson, Basic readings in neuropsychology (N.Y: Harper & Row,
1964).John Hughlings Jackson, Selected Writings, 2 vols. Edited by James Taylor
(London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1931. Reprinted N.Y: Basic, 1958).William James, Memories and studies (N.Y: Longmans, 1924).Sir Geoffrey Jefferson, Selected Papers (London: Pitman, 1960).Lloyd A. Jeffress (ed.), Cerebral mechanisms in behavior, the Hixon symposium (N.Y:
Wiley, 1951).H. S. Jennings, Behavior of the lower organisms (N.Y: Columbia, 1906).Ernest Jones, The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud, 3 vols. (N.Y: Basic, 1953,
1955, 1957).J. R. Kantor, The scientific evolution of psychology (Granville, Ohio:
Principia, 1963).Abram Kardiner and Edward Preble, They Studied Man (London: Secker &
Warburg, 1962).K. D. Keele, Anatomies of pain (Oxford: Blackmell, 1957).Lester S. King, "Stahl and Hoffmann: a study in eighteenth-century animism", Journal of the history of medicine and allied sciences, xix (1964) 118-130.Desmond King-Hele, Erasmus Darwin (London: Macmillan, 1963).Sigmund Koch (ed.), Psychology: a study of a science, 6 vols. (N.Y:
McGraw-Hill, 1959-63).David L. Krantz, "Research activity in 'normal' and 'anomalous' areas", Journal
of the history of the behavioral sciences, i (1965) 39-42.Leonard Krasner, "Studies of the conditioning of verbal behavior", Psychological
bulletin, Iv (1958) 148-170.David Kretch and George S. Klein, Theoretical models and personality theory (Durham:
Duke, 1952).Ernst Kris, "The significance of Freud's earliest discoveries", Internal
journal of psychoanalysis, xxxi (1950) 108-116.H. D. Kruse (ed.), Integrating the approaches to mental disease (N.Y:
Hoeber, 1957).Thomas S. Kuhn, The structure of scientific revolutions (Chicago, 1962; Phoenix
edition, 1964).Frederick A. Lange, The history of materialism and criticism of its present
importance, 3rd ed., 3 vols. in I (1875), trans. E. C. Thomas (London: Routledge,
1925).Karl S. Lashley, The Neuropsychology of Lashley: Selected Papers of K. S. Lashley. Edited
by F. A. Beach, et at. (N.Y: McGraw-Hill, 1960).Thomas Laycock, A treatise on the nervous diseases of women (London: Longmans,
1840).Thomas Laycock, "On the reflex functions of the brain", British and
foreign medical review, xix (1845) 298-311.Thomas Laycock, "Further researches into the functions of the brain". British
and foreign medical chirurgical review, xvi (1855) 155-187.Thomas Laycock, "Phrenology", in The encyclopedia Britannica, 8th ed.,
Vol. XVII (Edinburgh: Black, 1859) 556-567.Thomas Laycock, Mind and brain, or the correlations of consciousness and organization, 2 vols. (Edinburgh: Sutherland and Knox, 1860; 2nd ed., 1869)George H. Lewes, The biographical history of philosophy from its origin in Greece
down to the present day, 2nd edition (London: Parker, 1857).George H. Lewes, The history of philosophy from Thales to Comte, 3rd ed., 2
vols. (London: Longmans, Vol. I, 1867; Vol. II, 1871).George H. Lewes, Problems of life and mind, 5 vols. (London: Trübner, 1874-79).E. G. T. Liddell, The discovery of reflexes (Oxford: Clarendon, 1960).Robert B. Livingston, "How man looks at his own brain", in Sigmund Koch
(ed.), 1962 pp. 51-99.Arthur O. Lovejoy, The great chain of being, a study in the history of an
idea (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1936. Reprinted N.Y: Harper, 1960).Sir James Mackintosh, "Dissertation second: exhibiting a general view of the
progress of ethical philosophy chiefly during the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries", in The encyclopedia Britannica, 8th ed., Vol. 1 (Edinburgh:
Black, 1860) 309-445.Edward H. Madden, Chauncey Wright and the foundations of pragmatism (Seattle:
Washington, 1963).Horace W. Magoun, "Early development of ideas relating the mind with the
brain", in G. E. W. Wolstenholme and Celia M. O'Connor (eds.), Ciba foundation
symposium on the neurological basis of behaviour (London: Churchill, 1958)
4-27. Horace W. Magoun, "Evolutionary concepts of brain function following Darwin and
Spencer", in Sol Tax (ed.), Evolution after Darwin, Vol. II
(Chicago, 1960) 187-209.Jean M. and George Mandler, Thinking: from association to Gestall.. (N.Y.:
Wiley, 1964)E. J. Margetts, "The concept of the unconscious in the history of medical
psychology", Psychiatric quarterly, xxvii (1953) 115-138.Melvin H.Marx, Psychological theory, contemporary readings (N.Y:
Macmillan 1951).Melvin H. Marx and William A. Hillix, Systems and theories in psychology (N.Y.
McGraw-Hill,1963)Stephen F;. Mason, A history of the sciences, revised ed. (N.Y: Collier, 1902).William McDougall, Body and mind, a history, and a defence of animism (London: Mthuen, 1911).George H. Mead, Movements of thought in the nineteenth century, (Chicago,
1936).Cardinal Mercier, The origins of contemporary psychology, 2nd ed., trans. W. H.
Mitchell (London: Washbourne, 1918).Charles Mercier "Recollections", in J. Hughlings Jackson, Neurological
fragments (Oxford, 1925) 40-46.John T. Merz, .A history of European thought in the nineteenth century, 4
vols.(Edinburgh: Blackwood, 1904-12. Reprinted N.Y: Dover, 1965).Alfred Meyer, "Emergent patterns of the pathology of mental disease", Journal of mental science, cvi (1960) 785-802.Alfred Meyer and Raymond Hierons, "A note on Willis's views on the corpus
striattum and the external capsule", Journal of neurological science i (1964)
547-554.Alfred Meyer and Raymond Hierons, "On Thomas Williss concepts of
neurophysiology" Medical history. ix (1965) 1-15, 142-155George A. Miller Psychology, the science of mental life (London: Methuen, 1964).Milton Millhauser, Just before Darwin. Robert Chambers and Vestiges (Middletown,
Conn: Wesleyan, 1959).Charles K Mills,"Cerebral localisation in its priactical relations", Brain,
xii (1890) 233-288, 358-406.George Mora, "Historiography of psychiatry and its development: a
re-evaluation", Journal of the history of the behavioral sciences, i (1965)
43-52.George Mora, "The history of psychiatry: a cultural and bibliographical
survey", Psycho- analytic review lii (1965[a]) 154-183.Leslie T. Morton, Garrison and Mortons medical bibliography, 2nd ed. (N.Y:
Argosy., 1961).Frederick A. Muckler, "On the reason of animals: historical antecedent,; to the
logic of modern behaviorism", Psychological Reports, xii (1963) 863-882. Johannes Müller, Elements of physiology, 2 vols. (1833-40), trans. William Baly
(London: Taylor & Walton, Vol. 1, 1838; Vol. II, 1842).Carl Murchison (ed.), Psychologies of I925 (Worcester, Mass: Clark, 1925).Carl Murchison (ed.), Psychologiess of I930 (Worcester, Mass: Clark, 1930).Carl Murchison (ed.), .A history of psychology in autobiography, 3 vols.
(Worcester, Mass: Clark, 1930, 1932, 1936. See Boring, 1952).Gardner Murphy, Historical introduction to Modern psychology, revised ed. (N.Y:
Harcotirt, 1949).H.Nunberg and E. Ferden (eds.), Minutes of the Vienna psychoanalytic societyl Vol.
1, 1906-1908 (N.Y: International Universities, 1962).R.C. Oldfield, "Changing views of behaviour mechanisms", in A. C. Crombie
(ed.), Scientific change (London: Heinemann, 1963) 577-589.R. C. Oldfield and K. Oldfield, "Hartley's Observations on Man", .Annals
of science vii (1951) 371-381.J. M. D. Olmsted, François Magendie, pioneer in experimental physiology, and scientific
medicine in XIX century France (N.Y: Schumans, 1944).J. M. D. Olmsted, "Pierre Flourens", in E. A. Underwood (ed.), Science,medicine
and history, Vol. II (London: Oxford, 1953) 200-302.Charles E. Osgood, Method and theory in experimental psychology (N.Y: Oxford,
1953).John Passmore, A hundred years of philosophy (London: Duckworth, 1957).T. K. Penniman, .A hundred years of anthropology, 3rd ed. (London: Duckworth,
1965).Ralph B. Perry, The Thought and Character of William James, 2 vols. (Boston:
Atlantic-Little Brown, 1935).Jean Piaget, Paul Fraisse, and Maurice Reuchlin, Histoire et méthode. Vol. I of
Fraisse and Piget (eds.) Traite de Psychologie expérimentale, 9 vols.
(Paris: Presses, Universitaires, 1963).François Picavet, Les idéologues, essai sur l'histoire des idées et des
theories scientifiques, philosophiques, religieuses, etc. en France depuis
1789 (Paris: Alcan, 1891).W. B. Pillsbury, The history of psychology (N.Y: Norton, 1929).Leo Postman, "The history and present status of the law of effect", Psychological
bulletin, xliv (1947) 489-563.Leo Postman (ed.), Psychology in the making: histories of selected research
problems (N.Y: Knopf, 1962). Pp. v + 785 + xxiv. $9.00.F. N. L. Poynter (ed.), The history and philosophy of knowledge of the brain
and its functions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958).Carroll C. Pratt, "Faculty psychology", Psychological review, xxxvi
(1929) 141-171.Carroll C. Pratt, The logic of modern psychology (N.Y: Macmillan, 1939).Karl H. Pribram, "A review of theory in physiological psychology", Annual
review of psychology, xi (1960) 1-40.Karl H. Pribram, "The neuropsychology of Sigmund Freud", in Arthur J.
Bachrach (ed.), Experimental foundations of clinical psychology (N.Y: Basic, 1962)
442-468.Joseph Priestley, Theological and miscellaneous works, 26 vols. (London:
1817-32).I.T. Ramsey (ed.), Biology and personality, frontier problems in science, philosophy
and religion (Oxford: Blackwell, 1965).Benjamin Rand, The classical psychologists: selections illustrating psychology from Anaxagoras to Wundt (Boston: Mifflin, 1912).Benjamin Rand, "The early development of Hartley's doctrine of association", Psychological
review, xxx (1923) 306-320.John H. Randall, Jr., The career of philosophy from the middle ages to the
enlightenment (N.Y: Columbia, 1962).David Rapaport, "Az asszociáció fogalomtörténete" [The history of the
concept of association of ideas] (Budapest: Royal Hungarian Peter Pazmany University,
1938).David Rapaport, Emotions and memory (Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins,
1942).David Rapaport, "On the psychoanalytic theory of thinking", International
journal of psychoanalysis, xxxi (1950) 1-10.David Rapaport, "The autonomy of the ego", Bulletin of the Menninger
clinic, xv (1951) 113-123.David Rapaport, "The conceptual model of psychoanalysis", Journal of
personality, xx (1951) 56-81.David Rapaport, "On the psychoanalytic theory of affects", International
journal of psychoanalysis, xxxiv (1953) 177-198.David Rapaport, "The theory of ego autonomy: a generalization", Bulletin
of the Menninger clinic, xxii (1958) 13-35.David Rapaport, "A historical survey of psychoanalytic ego psychology", in
Erikson (1959) .5-17.David Rapaport, The structure of psychoanalytic theory: a systematizing
attempt (N.Y International Universities, 1960. Reprinted from Koch, vol. iii (1959)
55-183).David Rapaport and Merton M. Gill, "The points of view and assumptions of
metapsychology", International journal of psycho-analysis, xi (1959)
1-10.Leland J. Rather, "G. E. Stahl's psychological physiology", Bulletin of
medical history, xxxv (1961) 37-49.Th. Ribot, English psychology, trans. J. Fitzgerald (London: King, 1873).Th. Ribot, German psychology of to-day: the empirical school, 2nd ed.,
trans. J. M. Baldwin (N.Y: Scribner's, 1886).Philip Rieff, Freud: the mind of the moralist (London: Gollancz,
1959).Walther Riese and Ebbel C. Hoff, "A history of the doctrine of cerebral
localization", Journal of the history of medicine and
allied sciences, v (1950) 50-71; vi (1951) 439-470.Walther Riese, "The sources of Jacksonian neurology", Journal of nervous
and mental diseases, cxxiv (1956) 125-134.Walther Riese, "Freudian concepts of brain function and brain disease", Journal
of nervous and mental diseases, cxxvii (1958) 287-307.Walther Riese, "The pre-Freudian origins of psychoanalysis", in J. H.
Masserman (ed.) Science and psychoanalysis, Vol. I (N.Y: Grune & Stratton,
1958[a]) 29-72.Walther Riese, A history of neurology (N.Y: MD, 1959).Walther Riese and George E. Arrington, "The history of Johannes Müller's doctrine
of the specific energies of the senses: original and later versions", Bulletin of
the history of medicine, xxxvii (1963) 179-183.A.A. Roback, Bibliography of character and personality (Cambridge, Mass:
Sci-Art, 1927)A.A. Roback, History of American psychology (N.Y: Library, 1952).A.A. Roback, The psychology of character, 3rd ed. (London: Routledge,
1952 [a]).A.A. Roback, History of psychology and psychiatry (N.Y: Philosophical
Library, 1961).E. Romanes (ed.), The life. and letters of George John Romanes (London: Longmans, 1896).George J. Romanes, Animal Intelligence (London: Kegan Paul, 1882).George J. Romanes, Mental evolution in animals (London: Kegan Paul,
1883).George J. Romanes, "The Darwinism of Darwin, and of the post-Darwinian
schools", The monist, vi (1895) 1-27.George J. Romanes, Darwin and After Darwin, 3 vols. Vol. 1, The Darwinian theory (London: Longmans, 1892); Vol. II, Post-Darwinian questions, heredity and utility; Vol. III, Post-Darwinian questions, isolation and
physiological selection (Chicago: Open Court, Vol. II, 1895; Vol. III, 1897).George J. Romanes, Essays (London: Longmans, 1897).George Rosen, "The philosophy of Ideology and the emergence of modern medicine in
France", Bulletin of the history of medicine, xx (1946) 328-339.George Rosen, "Social attitudes to irrationality and madness in 17th and 18th
century Europe", Journal of the history of medicine and allied
sciences, xix (1963) 220-240.L. C. Rosenfield, From beast-machine to man-machine (Oxford, 1941). Christian A. Ruckmich, "The use of the term function in English textbooks
of psychology", American journal of psychology, xxiv (1913) 99-123.Kurt Salzinger, "Experimental manipulation of verbal behavior: a review", Journal
of genetic psychology, lxi (1959) 65-94.Jerome M. Schenck, A history of psychiatry (Springfield, Ill: Thomas, 1960).Paul A. Schilpp, The Philosophy of John Dewey, 2nd ed. (N.Y: Tudor, 1951).Robert E. Schofield, The Lunar Society of Birmingham (Oxford:
Clarendon, 1963).David Shakow and David Rapaport, The influence of Freud on American psychology (N.Y: International Universities, 1964).Daniel E. Sheer, "Brain and behavior: the background of interdisciplinary
research", in Daniel E. Sheer (ed.) Electrical stimulation of the brain (Austin: Texas, 1961) 3-21.Thorne Shipley (ed.), Classics in psychology (N.Y: Philosophical
Library, 1961).B.F. Skinner, "A case history in scientific method", in Koch (1959) 359-379.B.F. Skinner, "Behaviorism at fifty", Science, cxl (1960) 951-958.J.R. Smythies (ed.), Brain and mind, modern concepts of the nature of
mind (London: Routledge, 1965).M. V. Sokolov, "The works of Soviet psychologists in the history of
psychology", in N. V. Anan'ev et al. (eds.) Psychological science in the U.S.S.R., Vol. II (Washington: U.S. joint publishing research service, 1962)
873-960.Jules Soury, Le systeme nerveux central: structure et functions; histoire critiques
des théories et des doctrines, Vol. I (Paris: Carré et Naud, 1899).John A. Sours, "Freud and the philosophers", Bulletin of the history of medicine, xxxv (1961) 326-345.Charles E. Spearman, Psychology down the ages, 2 vols. (London:
Macmillan, 1937).Herbert Spencer, Social statics (London: Chapman, 1851).Herbert Spencer, The principles of psychology (London, Longmans, 1855; 2nd ed.,
London: Williams & Norgate, 1871-2; 3rd ed., 1890).Herbert Spencer, The factors of organic evolution (London: William and
Norgate, 1887).Herbert Spencer, An autobiography, 2 vols (London: Williams and Norgate, 1904).Herbert Spencer, The life and letters of Herbert Spencer, edited
by David Duncan (London:Methuen, 1908).Howard D. Spoerl, "Faculties versus traits: Gall's solution", Character
and personality, iv (1935-6) 216-231.E. A. Stengel, "A re-evaluation of Freud's book on aphasia; its significance for
psychoanalysis", International journal of psycho-analysis, xxxv (1954)
85-89.E.A. Stengel, "Hughlings Jackson's influence on psychiatry", British journal
of psychiatry, cix (1963) 348-355.Leslie Stephen, History of English thought in the eighteenth century, 2
vols., 3rd ed. (1902) (Reprinted London: Hart-Davis, 1962).S.S. Stevens, "Psychology and the science of science", Psychological
bulletin, xxxvi (1939) 221-263.S.S. Stevens (ed.), Handbook of experimental psychology (London:
Chapman and Hall, 1951).Dugald Stewart, "Dissertation first: exhibiting a general view of the progress of
metaphysical and ethical philosophy, since the revival of letters in Europe", in The encyclopedia Britannica, 8th ed., vol. i (Edinburgh: Black, 1860) 1-289.George W. Stocking, Jr., "From physics to ethnology: Franz Boas' arctic expedition
as a problem in the historiography of the behavioral sciences", Journal of history of the behavioral sciences, i (1965) 53-66.George W. Stocking, Jr., "Editorial: on the limits of 'presentism' and
'historicism' in the historiography of the behavioral sciences", Journal of the
history of the behavioral sciences, i (1965[a]) 211-217.B. Stokey, "A note on the early history of cerebral localization", Bulletin
of the New York academy of medicine 59-578. academy of medicine, XXX (1954) 559-578.P.F. Strawson, Individuals, an essay in descriptive metaphysics (London:
Methuen, 1959).C. A. Strong, "A sketch of the history of psychology among the Greeks", American
journal of psychology iv (1891-2) 177-197Charles Taylor, The explanation of behaviour (London: Routledge, 1964)Owsei Temkin, "The philosophical background of Magendies physiology", Bulletin
of the history of medicine, xx (1946) 10-35.Owsei Temkin, "Materialism in French and German physiology of the early nineteenth
century", Bulletin of the history of medicine, xx (1946 [a]) 322-327.Owsei Temkin, "Gall and the phrenological movement", Bulletin of the
history of medicine, xxi (1947) 275-321.Owsei Temkin, "The classical roots of Glisson's doctrine of irritation", Bulletin
of the history of medicine, xxxviii (1964) 297-328.Tenon, Portal, Sabatier, Pinel and Cuvier, "Report on a memoir of Drs Gall and
Spurzheim, relative to the anatomy of the brain. By . . ., presented to and adopted by the
Class of Mathematical and Physical Sciences of the National Institute", (Given at the
Institute 15 April, 1808) Edinburgh medical and surgical journal, v (1809) 36-66.Hans-Lukas Teuber, "Perception" in J. Field (ed. Handbook of physiology,
neurophysiology, vol. i (Washington: American physiological society, 1959) 1595-1668.Milton H. Thomas (ed.), "John Dewey: a centennial bibliography" (Chicago,
1962). Jürgen Thorwald, The Triumph of Surgery (1957), trans. R. and C. Winston (N.Y:
Pantheon, 1960).Edward B. Titchener, "The postulates of a structural psychology", Philosophical
review, vii (1898) 449-465. Reprinted in Dennis (1948) 366-376.E. B.Titchener, "Functional psychology and the psychology of act", American
journal of psychology, xxxii (1921) 519-542; xxxiii (1922) 43-83.Barbara Tizard, "Theories of brain localization from Flourens to Lashley", Medical
history, iii (1959) 132-144.Aram Vartanian, Diderot and Descartes, a study of scientific
naturalism in the Enlightenment (Princeton, 1953).Aram Vartanian, La Mettrie's l'homme machine, a study in the origins
of an idea (Princeton, 1960).A.E. Walker, "The development of the concept of cerebral localization in the
nineteenth century", Bulletin of the history of medicine, xxxi (1957) 99-121.Nigel Walker, A short history of psychotherapy in theory and practice (London: Routledge, 1957).Alfred R. Wallace, The wonderful century, its successes and failures (London: Sonnenschein, 1898).Alfred R. Wallace, My life, a record of events and opinions, 2 vols. (London:
Chapman and Hall, 1905).F. M. R. Walshe, "Contributions of John Hughlings Jackson to neurology", Archives
of neurology, v (1961) 119-131.Carl J. Warden, "The historical development of comparative psychology", Psychological review, xxxiv (1927) 57-85, 135-168.Howard C. Warren, A history of the association pychology (London: Constable,
1921).Margaret F. Washburn, The animal mind, a text-book of comparative psychology
(N.Y: Macmillan, 1908).R. H. Waters, "The law of effect as a principle of learning", Psychology
bulletin, xxxi (1934) 408-425.John B. Watson, "Psychology as the behaviorist views it", Psychological
review, xx (1913) 158-177. Reprinted in Dennis (1948) 457-471.John B. Watson, "The place of the conditioned reflex in psychology", Psychological review, xiii (1916) 89-117.John B. Watson, Behaviorism (1924), revised ed. (1930). Reprinted Chicago, 1959.John B. Watson, Psychology from the standpoint of a behaviorist (Philadelphia: Lippincott, 1919).Robert I. Watson, "A brief history of clinical psychology", Psychological
bulletin, I (1953) 321-346.Robert I. Watson, "Historical review of objective personality testing", in B.
M. Bass and I. A. Berg (eds.) Objective approach to personality assessment (Princeton: van Nostrand, 1959) 1-23.Robert I. Watson, "Historical perspectives on the relationships of psychologists
to medical research", Neuropsychiatry, vi (1960) 51-59.Robert I. Watson, "The history of psychology: a neglected area", .American
psychologist, xv (1960[a]) 251-255.Robert I. Watson, "A brief history of educational psychology", Psychological
record, xi (1961) 209-242.Robert I.Watson, The great psychologists: from Aristotle to Freud (Philadelphia:
Lippincott, 1963). Pp. xvi + 572. $7.50.Morton G. White, The origin of Dewey's instrumentalism (N.Y:
Columbia, 1943).Alfred N. Whitehead, Science and the modern world (Cambridge, 1925).Lancelot L. Whyte, The unconscious before Freud (N.Y: Basic, 1960).Philip P. Wiener, Evolution and the founders of pragmatism (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1949. Reprinted N.Y: Harper, 1965).J. S. Wilkie, "Buffon, Lamarck and Darwin: the originality of Darwin's theory of
evolution", in P. R. Bell (ed.) Darwin's Biological Work (Cambridge, 1959)
262-307.Basil Willey, The seventeenth-century background (London: Chatto and Windus,
1934. Reprinted Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1962).Basil Willey, The eighteenth-century background (London: Chatto and
Windus, 1940. Reprinted Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1962).A.Wolf, A history of science, technology and philosophy in the sixteenth
and seventeenth centuries, 2nd ed. (London: Allen and Unwin, 1950. Reprinted in 2
vols. N.Y: Harper, 1959).A.Wolf, A history of science, technology and philosophy in the eighteenth century,
2nd ed. revised by D. McKie (London: Allen and Unwin, 1952. Reprinted in 2
vols. N.Y: Harper, 1959).Benjamin B. Wolman (ed.), Historical roots of contemporary
psychology (N.Y: Harper, 1965).Robert S. Woodworth, Contemporary schools of psychology (1931) 8th
ed. (London: Methuen, 1951).Evelyn A. Woods and Eric T. Carlson, "The psychiatry of Philippe Pinel", Bulletin
of the history of medicine, xxxv (1961) 14-25.Robert S. Woodworth and Mary R. Sheeham, Contemporary schools of psychology,
3rd ed. (N.Y: Ronald, 1964).Oliver L. Zangwill, "Lashley's concept of cerebral mass action", in W.
H. Thorpe and 0. L. Zangwill (eds.) Current problems in animal behaviour (Cambridge, 1961) 59-86.
Gregory Zilboorg and G. W. Henry, A history of medical psychology (N.Y:
Norton, 1941).