Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
THE MORAL AND THE MOLECULAR IN THE FUTURE OF PSYCHIATRY
by Robert M. Young
Summary: I want to ask what moral treatment should mean in
the next century. As Kathleen Jones has shown in her Preface to Tukes account of the
York Retreat (Tuke, 1813), there is an ambiguity about this phrase. It connotes common
sense morality in English and the world of emotions in French. I want to ponder both
meanings. In particular, I want to reflect upon what it means for a person who would
formerly have been in an asylum or retreat to be treated morally (Eng.) in the community,
taking full account of his or her moral (Fr.) vicissitudes. This involves philosophical
and political questions about being a person, citizen, member, while, as the same time
being selectively disabled in the sense of recent debates on that concept.
Whatever else these terms mean, they do not mean de-mented. A second strand of
my reflections concerns the relationship between the experiential, on the one hand, and
the psychopharmacological and biological aspects of our humanity, on the other. The
problems associated with dividing the person into mind and body, i.e., into moral and
mechanical, are likely to increase in the next hundred years, and this process is likely
to make the moral issues raised above even more urgent.
I begin with some recent images from the mass media. The first is
Mohammed Ali lighting the Olympic Flame in Atlanta. The second is Christopher Reeve
addressing the Academy Award ceremony and the Democratic Convention. A third is the
publicity given to the Para-Olympics. A fourth is a news item: Margot Kidder was found
wandering and distraught in Hollywood.
What these images say to me is that disability is becoming re-located
in world culture. I want to suggest that it may be helpful to think of mental illness in
terms of the concept of disability and recent developments in our thinking about it.
Several things strike me about the images I have mentioned. First, the huge split between
the able-bodied and the disabled is closing. The connection between the two ends of the
split is being acknowledged, although I would not claim that we have moved from a
paranoid-schizoid to a depressive way of thinking about them. By that I mean that there
is, as yet, no integration, only a juxtaposition, but thats a start. One way the
disability movement refers to this is to say that we are all only temporarily
abled. The chances are that we will almost all become disabled at some
stage feeble, hard of hearing, seriously forgetful. These images say to me that
Superman can meet with profound misfortune and become permanently paralysed and confined
to a wheelchair, something no fall from a horse could have done to him when I was a boy.
Only kryptonite could do it and then only temporarily. Similarly, the man known as
The Greatest, the worlds best known athlete, a man who could dance
like a butterfly and sting like a bee and compose witty doggerel all the while,
could fall prey to Parkinsonism and be hesitant of gait, of speech of gesture this,
too was until recently unthinkable or at least something to keep hidden.
Even more important than acknowledging their vulnerability to human
frailty, it seems to me, is this fact that such people are no longer hidden away. Their
humanity, their dignity, their struggles are bought before a world audience with sympathy,
respect and admiration for their fortitude. It is no longer thought that they have
lost it like pugilists portrayed in sports movies of my childhood, when
punch-drink fighters were portrayed in bit parts on the fringes of sports movies.
Something similar can be said about prowess in the Olympics. The Olympic ideal meant
perfect physique, perfect fitness, when I was a boy. I happened to know an Olympic diving
and gymnastics champion. He was perfect. The whole idea of the Para-Olympics says that
fitness and prowess are relative. There are a number of categories and criteria for
disability. People are encouraged to compete against comparably disabled people. There was
even an advert last summer stressing that the athletes in the wheel chair marathon moved a
great deal faster than the runners.
I grant that there are contradictions in all this and that the motives
for displaying Christopher Reeve and Mohammed Ali are complex and mixed and that there is
awful sentimentality and, arguably, some serious poor taste involved. But never mind. I am
sure this is, on balance and all things considered,. progress.
But what about Margot Kidder, who, you may or may not recall, played
Lois Lane in the Superman movies? The fate which has befallen her has not been displayed
with the same public respect and sympathy. That news item came across to me more
pruriently, voyeuristically, with a sick irony. Becoming mentally ill is in no way viewed
with the same compassion; ones dignity is not retained. It is sordid, tawdry.
Something similar can be said about the stories surrounding the death of Margaux
Hemingway. How the mighty are fallen... A sad end, reminding one of Marilyn Monroes
death.
One of the things I want to suggest today is that we begin to think
about the mentally ill in ways analogous to how we seem to be thinking about the disabled.
It is not a simple analogy, if only because the mentally ill are often experienced as
Other in a way that those otherwise disabled are usually not or not to the same degree. It
has been said that the modern disability movement can be traced, to a significant degree,
to the militancy of returning Viet Nam veterans in wheelchairs as a result of spinal
injuries. They fought for access to public transport, sports events, public buildings.
They said to the rest of us, in effect, Just because I am disabled and in this
chair, Ill be damned if you are going to deprive me of my rights of access and other
dimensions of dignity. We also have subtitles and signing of some speeches on the
television, hearing loops in various public places, large print and audio cassette books.
I could go on in this vein at length, but I think you see the positive
side of the analogy. The physically disabled have insisted that we not add insult to
injury, and their campaigns are making a great deal of headway, even though they have a
long way to go. The same cannot be said about the mentally ill or disabled. Why not? Well,
to put is crudely and obviously, to have a sound mind in a damaged body is not the same as
having a sound body with a damaged mind. We have to find a way of retaining the dignity,
personhood, membership, citizenship and rights of the mentally ill issues which, on
the whole, simply do not arise for the physically disabled (though, of course, they also
have mental damage and recalcitrant administrations to contend with). The part of the
person which is okay with the physically disabled and makes their campaigns work - their
insistence that their personhood is intact is just whats damaged with the
mentally ill. But thats no reason not to pursue the analogy. Indeed, I have recently
seen the following self- description of a mental patient:
If you believe in the inner man and the outer man, if you understand
something about the inner man... Well, thats what breaks and thats why it
makes you less confident, and more difficult and hard to form relationships and the rest
of it. Thats the only way I can describe it.... Thats the thing that happens.
So thats why I just regard it as an internal disability, if you see what I mean
(Barham and Hayward, 1991, p. 10).
This brings me to moral treatment, a helpfully multivalent
phrase which was used to characterize the novel regime at the York Retreat. First and most
obviously and relevant to our presence here today, it meant treating people kindly, in
contrast to the treatment Tuke deplored and set out to improve upon in a way which
constituted a revolution in the care of the insane. Gentle, dignified, retaining contact
with the inner light Quakerism postulates is in every human being. It is deeply ironic
that the history of much of the asylum movement which had its roots in the inspiration of
Tuke and Pinel came to be seen in recent decades as inhuman not usually, of
course inhuman in the use of chains and physical cruelties, but inhuman nonetheless in the
sundering of human dignity. We should not forget, however, that there was a heyday of the
country asylum. It was believed during much of the nineteenth century that these castles
were indeed havens from the degradations of urban, industrial capitalism. People were
thought to be cured by the very act of going to such places, which were thought of as
something like the twentieth-century health spas came to be regarded, veritable
Wellvilles, and they came to have equally arcane modes of treatment. But that was later. I
well remember being told as a medical student that the statistics for cures in
nineteenth-century asylums went up and up until, at last a Doctor Awl was able to announce
a one hundred per cent cure rate. He was thenceforward known as Dr Cure-Awl.
Somehow, during the ensuing decades, these large institutions changed from being
instruments of regeneration to dustbins for the incurable (Roy
Porter, quoted in Barham, 1992, p. 68). A century later I worked in such an institution in
Arizona (as part of a Quaker project in Arizona) at a crucial turning point in the
mid-1950s when the back wards had become places without hope, while the admission ward was
about to open its doors, and the highest hopes were attached to the new tranquillisers,
hopes which we did not yet know were exaggerated.
As we all know, the writings of subtle and courageous people from the
Author of The Mentally Ill in America (Deutsch, 1948, 1948a; Wright, 1947) to The
Snake Pit (Ward, 1946) and on to One Flew Over the Cuckoos Nest (Kesey,
1973) (both made into films which had huge impacts - see Shortland, 1987), coupled
with the critiques of Goffman (1961, 1971), Schiff (1966, 1971) and other theoreticians of
labelling and deviance (Pearson, 1975) and others, e.g., Ronald Laing, 1960; Laing and
Esterson, 1964), led to a discrediting of the old, large custodial mental hospitals which,
with hindsight, we are coming to see was only partly appropriate when compared to what has
been put in their place. I am thinking now of places like Fulbourn Hospital, near
Cambridge, which under the leadership of David Clark (1996), re-established and embodied
many of the ideals of the York Retreat. It was not unique. Other therapeutic communities
could make similar claims, for example, The Henderson Hospital, the Cassel; you will have
your own nominees.
We all know that the next step was pretty awful, and people like Andrew
Scull (1979, 1984, 1989) and Peter Barham have provided us with insightful accounts of the
unholy alliance between the critics of the old asylums and the misguided and opportunistic
cost-cutters who used care in the community as a slogan for closing the
institutions without putting anything approaching adequate facilities in their place.
This brings me to the second meaning of moral, the French
sense of moral as the realm of the emotions. The truth is that the mentally ill are not in- sane, any more than they are de-mented.
They are something in between. No, thats not it. There is no
simple way of expressing what I mean. Their difficulties are highly-textured. Their
personalities have complex coastlines, sometimes with fissures which go deep, sometimes
almost all the way across, rather like the one extending from the Moray Firth to the Firth
of Lorn and includes Loch Ness (where there may be a monster) and nearly cuts Scotland in
two. While people were in custodial settings, a terrible enforcement of uniformity was
imposed. I vividly recall being instructed not to help a slow person feed himself, since
it took too much time. Simpler to shovel it in. On a ward of severely mentally handicapped
people, it was deemed easiest to let them eat any way they liked and hose down the lot at
the end of each meal. All dignity sacrificed on the alter of staff shortages.
When the mentally ill were turfed out into the community it was not
properly realised that a certain minimal cosseting would be lost which occurred in spite
of that inhuman blunting . My view is that the task for the future is to find ways of
catering for the profoundly craggy and individual and highly-textured and changing
(sometimes dramatically changing) coastlines of the individuals who have been, are and may
again become mentally ill. This is a tall order, given the way our family patterns have
developed. How can we care for the mentally ill when we are so uncaring about our other
fellow humans?
You may recall that one of the way Foucault (1967) characterised the
people who ended up in asylums was that they were not reliable employees. He referred to
them as those who will not work. This phrase can stand for all sorts of
aspects of the idiosyncrasies of the recovering and intermittent mental patient. Peter
Barham and Robert Hayward have made a special study of this issue in their fine book, From
the Mental Patient to the Person (1992) recently re-issued as Relocating Madness. I want to say here that Barhams work strikes me as the best single guide through the
labyrinth I am trying to thread today. His Schizophrenia and Human Value (1984)
posed the problem of the humanity of the mentally ill, while his Closing of the
Asylums: The Mental Patient in Modern Society (1992) is the best short account of the
history of the present policy and the problems it poses. I have said before and repeat
here that Schizophrenia and Human Value is one of the best books I have ever read.
Not just best in this field. Best full stop. The reason is that it poses in terms of
philosophical reflections and political and cultural theory the problem of what it means
to be a person in a society and a culture and how hard it is to place the mentally ill
person in this framework as a fully human being or, as he puts it, as a person and a
citizen. That, I suggest, is our task for the future. But it is posed in the face of a
community which is in many ways uncaring of all of us and in the face of a fashion in
psychiatry which is, in the main, turning its face away from the humanistic and toward the
biochemical. As Barham says, Deinstitutionalization implicates rather more than the
administrative substitution of one locus of care for another, and invites also a drastic
reshaping of the ways we think about, describe and, in particular, relate to people with a
history of Mental Illness (Barham, 1992, p. 151).
The task of a proper policy of care in the community is not one which
we approach de novo. Positive models of care in the community was a theme in this
years biennial conference on Psychosis at the University of Essex,
optimistically subtitled this time Integrating the Inner and Outer Worlds. We
heard about the dramatically improved statistics obtained by Dr Lawrence Ratna and his
team with an attentive and meticulous crisis intervention team which has been in existence
for over a quarter of a century. An equally carefully worked out approach has been
developing for the past eight years under the rubric of Psychosicial
Intervention, which has so far involved more than thirty NHS trusts and which can be
studied as a postgraduate course at the Centre for Psychotherapeutic Studies of the
University of Sheffield, where I work. Moving further back, there is the inspiring story
of Trieste, generalised into Law 180, passed in 1978, which led to the closing of the
Italian psychiatric hospitals, and the development of a careful scheme of community care,
story which Dr Tim Kendall (1996) brought up to date at the Psychosis conference. But
there are even more venerable ways of accommodating the mentally ill in communities. There
has been a scheme in Ainay le Château since 1900 (Jodelet, 1991) and a system of boarding
out in Scotland for even longer. The longest-established programme is in Geel, Belgium,
which has been operating since the eleventh century. People came to the shrine of St
Dymphna, the patron saint of the mad, and then hung about in the community and were
integrated into it. There has been a scheme operating there ever since. There are now
about 800 patients in a community of 30,000. When the BBC (1992) filmed there recently,
what was most striking was the sheer tolerance of the host families, who treated the
patients symptoms and preoccupations as eccentricities and made emotional space for them.
This latitude for the expression of symptoms seems to me to be of the essence of what is
needed. It is the emotional equivalent of the achievement on behalf of the physically
disabled of special toilets with access for wheelchairs which we see in more and more
public places or the special rails or chair lifts at swimming pools and in community
centres. It allows people to move about without being in constant fear of being blocked or
caught short. It is the opposite of what Foucault observed. Instead of hiding away
those who will not work, we need to revamp the community and the interfaces
between the mentally ill and the rest of us in whatever ways turn out to be necessary to
make them user-friendly for those who are periodically in mental distress.
I am not suggesting that the loonies should take over the
asylum, as the reactionaries might put it. Even in Geel, patients were quite clearly
told, in a way some viewers of the BBC documentary found patronising, that if they went
beyond certain limits with their behaviour, as a punishment they would have to spend a
period back in the custodial mental hospital which remains open in the city. When they
learn to behave acceptably, they can return to their adoptive families. Pure anarchists
might not like this, but I found it reasonable in a rough and ready way. As St Paul
reminded us, it is not the letter but the spirit of the law that matters, and the families
I saw seemed to me to be admirably commonsensical about the boundaries which had to be
drawn and enforced from time to time with the help of hospital liaison nurses.
I am not suggesting that London or York should just adopt the Geel,
Ainay or some similar scheme wholesale. I am suggesting that we put our imaginations to
work in creating spaces in which those of intermittent disability of mind and spirit can
remain as fully human and participant in culture and society and the polity as they can
manage at any given time once again, personhood and citizenship. As I said earlier,
Peter Barham and Robert Hayward have in their fieldwork carefully delineated how complex
and subtle a problem this poses. Their quotations from discussions with a goodly number of
mental patients in remission and in the grip of current difficulties make it painfully
clear that negotiating life on the streets and conducting relations with the health and
welfare authorities is a daunting labyrinth, full of snakes and precious few ladders. My
point is that it should be addressed in as commonsensical a way as the problems of other
disabled people. One group which strikes me as pointing part of the way is the Hearing
Voices group, which seeks to make this symptom seem less extraordinary and not to be
denied or suppressed. Indeed, it turns out that a majority of people in Holland who hear
voices never come in contact with the psychiatric services at all. Im not saying
that its fun or ordinary; I am just saying that it can be borne and tolerated, like
many other forms of behaviour which strikes one as odd, eccentric or even mad.
As I have implied, I believe that these are philosophical issues as
well as social, cultural and political ones. We have to be clear about what it means to be
a person, member, citizen, even while being limited and very unusual at times and in
certain ways. Id like to share some of Barham and Haywards findings, since
they are so evocative of what I am trying to convey. They suggest that for a mentally ill
person personhood in not a tenured accomplishment (p.71); it is
constantly on probation (p.14). Mental patients often no longer feel
themselves to be agents with a life to live (p. 92). After a breakdown, the
task was nothing less than to start "establishing" herself "as a
person" all over again (p. 97). Mental patients have to learn from hard
experience to become active strategists in the reconstitution and negotiation of their
lives ...a severe schizophrenic breakdown typically wreaks havoc upon the agents
sense of his own biographical continuity and telos, upon the narrative coherence of his
life (p. 91).
The task of achieving some kind of biographical reconstruction is
fraught and full of pitfalls. A word which recurs again and again in Barham and
Haywards account is demoralised.
Not infrequently, the person finds himself in a field of forces in
which he is made to feel demoralised about his own prospects, about what he can
realistically hope for, and his demoralisation may then impact upon his ability to care
for himself, which in its turn, may demoralise him still further. For the person to ask
for help in this situation even to admit to himself that he is in need of help
may seem to confirm the feelings of incompetence and humiliation that have already
been borne upon him (p. 53).
Barham says in Closing the Asylum, ...if we are not to
fuel the demoralization of people with mental illness, and stigmatize them still further,
we... stand badly in need of psychiatric theories that try to grapple with what users of
mental health services themselves want (p. 62).
The social and the diagnostic location of such people are mutually
reinforcing. Here are some remarks about two interviewees. Sallys statement,
"I feel Im a psychiatric patient" functions here not as
a description of what she actually is, or of a role to which she has been assigned, but as
a negative definition of what she feels about herself as a person and of the life
prospects that she judges to be available to her.
In Henrys usage "schizophrenia" is not so much
the name for an illness as for a social predicament to which the experience of illness has
given rise. For Henry coming to "accept" the illness and coming to
"accept" an impoverished conception of what he can reasonably do and hope for
of his significance and value have been brought to merge in a painful
experience of exclusion and worthlessness. In what they say about themselves Henry and
Sally illustrate not the natural consequences of mental illness, but the social consequences of becoming mentally ill in society as they enter into the persons most
intimate sense of who he or she now is (p. 77).
Another challenging philosophical problem about personhood brings us to
my closing point. With the rise of more and more drugs and the likely addition of
intracranial electronic and surgical manipulations of increasing complexity and precision,
it is becoming more and more difficult to speak of a clear split between natural and
artificial or mind and body. Indeed, the relationship between speaking of ourselves as
persons and doing so in terms of minds and bodies has been an unresolved issue at the
heart of the modern world view at last since René Descartes Discourse on Method, published in 1637. (cf. Strawson, 1959 and Young, 1990 and 1994). I am not
going to waste our time making dire predictions, but I am sure that developments are in
train which will profoundly challenge our concept of personhood from genetic,
psychopharmacological and neurophysiological points of view. The likelihood that more and
more of us will be cyborgs part organism, part cybernetic systems is very
great (Harway, 1990). I am not at all sure I welcome these developments in our present
socio-economic order, since I hold he view that the profit motive will be likely grossly
to distort their development. In this daunting future, I believe that something else which
Peter Barham said should be our guiding principle. Whatever may turn out to be the
biochemical or genetic causes or other aspects of mental illnesses, the subjective
experiences and the civil rights and the dignity of the mentally ill the
meaningfulness of their experience should be respected and nurtured, cultivated
and protected, according to political and cultural values which must not be in any way
reified (Ingleby, 1970) down to the pseudo-neutrality and falsely conscious value free
stance of reductionist science. The values of humanity moral in focus and moral in
the full appreciation of the emotional gamut of our humanity must be husbanded.
I began by following Kathleen Jones in pointing to two senses of the
moral moral treatment as civilised and humane and the moral as the vicissitudes of
emotions. I end with two senses of the molecular. The first is the focus on genetics and
molecular interactions, for example, involving the metabolism of substances like the
enzyme monamine oxidase in relation to serotonin, dopamine and noradrenalin. I have simply
said that the moral should never be superseded by the molecular. Where are the Professors
of Care in the Community? Their numbers and resources should be on a par with Professors
of Psychopharmacology and Molecular Biology in our psychiatry departments. The second
meaning of molecular, however, takes me back to the complexities of care in the community:
the need to create facilities and user-friendly interfaces which can fit or accommodate
all the inlets and outlets of the textured idiosyncrasies of the mentally ill person. In
politics, this careful mode of alteration of bad practices is called molecular
change, change which suits the tiny individual features of individuals, in contrast
to the conformity-requiring changes which have been too characteristic of recent policies
of care in the community, where defensively devoting scarce resources to compiling lists
or people at risk of being violent seems to be a higher priority than individual
consideration in, for example, living accommodation. I shall never forget a television
image in a recent BBC television week on mental health in which a patient was told he
could have a bus pass if he would just sign here that he was permanently incapacitated.
These are the ways of thinking of people in the mass, without regard for their
sensibilities and hopes, which rightly led to the downfall of nominally socialist regimes
in Eastern Europe.
If we can develop a truly molecular policy of care in the community,
making full allowance for the emotional range of mentally distressed people, which never
ceases to treat them as moral beings, the tradition of moral treatment begun
exactly two centuries ago in this building will remain unbroken. I want to close on a note
about Margot Kidder who youll recall was found wandering around, dishevelled in the
California capital of idealised personhood, just as the Olympics (both able-bodied and
para) represent the ideal of athletic prowess and marriage to Lois Lanes hero
which occurs this month in Superman comics and on television represents
idealisations of personal relations. Perhaps one day it will be appropriate, dignified and
respectful for us to see Margot Kidder lighting some care in the community equivalent of
the Olympic Flame. I hope so. She seemed such a nice woman in the Superman movies.
I wish to acknowledge with thanks the influence on my thinking about
disability of ongoing discussions with Dr Deborah Marks. She has developed the MA in
Disability Studies at the Centre for Psychotherapeutic Studies at the University of
Sheffield.
REFERENCES
(Place of publication is London unless otherwise specified.)
Barham, Peter (1984) Schizophrenia and Human Value. Oxford:
Blackwell; reprinted Free Association Books, 1993
______ (1992) Closing the Asylum: The Mental Patient in Modern Society. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
______ and Hayward, Robert (1991) From the Mental Patient to the Person. Routledge; reissued as Relocating Madness: Free Association Books, 1985.
BBC2 (1992) Mutual Aid. Everyman television documentary.
Clark, David H. (1996) The Story of a Mental Hospital: Fulbourn, 1858-1983. Process Press.
Descartes, René (1637) Discourse on the Method of Properly Conducting Ones
Reason and of Seeking the Truth in the Sciences, in Discourse on Method and The
Meditations. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968, pp. 25-91
Deutsch, A. (1948)The Mentally Ill in America. N. Y.: Doubleday.
______ (1948a) The Shame of the States. N. Y. Harcourt Brace, 1948.
Foucault, Michel (1967) Madness and Civilization. Tavistock.
Goffman, Erving (1961) Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients
and Other Inmates. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
______ (1971) Appendix: The Insanity of Place, in Relations in Public. London:
Allen Lane, pp. 335-90.
Haraway, Donna (1990) Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of
Nature. Free Association Books.
Hunter, Richard and Macalpine, Ida (1963) Three Hundred Years of Psychiatry:
1535-1860: A History presented in Selected English Texts. Oxford.
Ingleby, David (1970) Ideology and the Human Sciences: Some Comments on the Role
of Reification in Psychology and Psychiatry, The Human Context 2: no. 2;
reprinted (abridged) in T. Pateman, ed., Counter Course: A Handbook for Course
Criticism. Harmondsworth: Penguin Education, 1972, pp. 51-81.
Jodelet, Denise (1991) Madness and Social Representation (1989). Harvester
Wheatsheaf (re: Ainay-le-Château).
Kendall, Tim (1996) Trieste: The Current Situation, paper presented to
Third International Conference on Psychosis: Integrating the Inner and Outer
Worlds, University of Essex.
Kesey, Ken (1973) One Flew over the Cuckoos Nest. N. Y.: Viking.
Laing, R. D. (1960) The Divided Self: An Existential Study of Sanity and Madness. Tavistock;
reprinted Penguin, 1965.
______ and Esterson, A. (1964)Sanity, Madness and the Family: Families of
Schizophrenics. Tavistock; reprinted Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Pearson, Geoffrey (1975) The Deviant Imagination: Psychiatry, Social Work and Social
Change. Macmillan.
Schiff, Thomas J. (1966) Being Mentally Ill: A Sociological Theory. Chicago:
Aldine.
______ (1971) Reason and Sanity: Some Political Implications of Psychiatric
Thought, in H. P. Dreitzel, ed., Recent Sociology No. 3: The Social Organization
of Health. Collier-Macmillan, pp. 291-301.
Scull, Andrew (1979) Museums of Madness. Allen Lane.
______ (1984) Decarceration, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Polity.
______ (1989) Social Disorder/Mental Disorder. Routledge.
Shortland, Michael (1987) Screen Memories: Towards a History of
Psychiatry and Psychoanalysis in the Movies, Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 20: 421-52.
Strawson, P. F. (1959) Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive
Metaphysics. Methuen (re: mind-body and persons).
Tuke, Samuel (1813) Description of the Retreat, an Institution near York for Insane
Persons of the Society of Friends, Containing an Account of Its Origin and Progress, The
Modes of Treatment, and a Statement of Cases. York.
Ward, Mary Jane (1946)The Snake Pit.
Wright, F. L., Jr. (1947) Out of Sight Out of Mind: A Graphic Picture of Present-Day
Institutional Care of the Mentally Ill in America, Based on More than Two Thousand
Eye-Witness Reports (Philadelphia: National Mental Health Foundation).
Young , Robert M. (1990) The Mind-Body Problem, in R. C.
Olby et al., eds., Companion to the History of Modern Science Routledge, pp.
702-11.
______ (1994) Mental Space. Process Press.
Paper presented to Conference on the Bi-centenary of the Founding of
the York Retreat, The Retreat, York, 4 October 1996.
Copyright: The Author
Address for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|