Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
The Human Limits of Nature
Robert M. Young
I find it worrying that an Institute for Contemporary Arts is turning
deferentially to science for social and cultural wisdom and guidance. Presumably the
people to whom these essays are addressed believe that this is a project worth pursuing.
It seems to me that the contributors and their audience are gathered in the name of
science, but that we are at the same time gathered as symptoms of some sort of social,
cultural, political and indeed ideological malaise. We seek a basis in science for our
goals and for the ordering of society. Scientists and other related experts are becoming
secular priests, who are supposed to help us order our conduct, our work and the world
that we live in.I would like to begin by discussing the phrase 'human nature' and to
attempt a critical examination of the moral, political and ideological positions which are
bound up with that concept. My first point is to suggest that we scrutinize the phrase.
The juxtaposition of the term 'human' with that of 'nature' is part of common language. We
all mean something by 'human nature'. We do not think it is silly, or deeply problematic,
to combine the two words. But the commonsensical juxtaposition of humanity with nature, if
we reflect on it, conceals very deep issues. Its usual meaning is in the area of 'What is
man like? What is characteristic of man? What regularities of what people do, think and
feel can we employ as guides in our relations with our fellow men?' That is all fairly
clear, although imprecise. But the juxtaposition of humanity with nature is not really so
straightforward. In many ways, we think of our humanity as something different from, as
over against, the concept of nature. This 'over-against-ness' is one of the pervasive
trends in the Western and other intellectual traditions. Humanity, we like to think, is
not merely a natural phenomenon. Yet we believe deeply, if we take science seriously, that
there is nothing about man which is not, at least in principle, explainable by the
concepts and methods of the natural sciences.This assumption that scientific naturalism applies to man and to all of
his works is fundamental; it is the sine qua non of psychology and of the social -
or some would say the 'behavioural', and others would say the 'human' - sciences. The
assumption has become fundamental as a result of four interrelated phases in the history
of thought, at least since the eighteenth century. The first phase was the attempt to take
the corpuscular and mechanical physics of the Mechanical Philosophy, deriving from the
Scientific Revolution, and apply it to the mind: the development of the so-called
'association psychology'.[1] Then this psychology interacted in complicated ways with the
development of the modern theory of evolution.[2] Then associationism and evolutionism and
related neurological conceptions combined with ideas from romantic philosophy to produce
the psychoanalytic theory in the work of Sigmund Freud.[3] I think the vogue of
psychoanalysis as a cultural philosophy is past, and we are now in a period in which many
people are seeing these naturalistic assumptions in terms of the disciplines of ethology
and genetics. These, of course, are related to other aspects of the social and human
sciences, and indeed to demography, social statistics, and other disciplines. They are all
founded on the further assumption that the aspects of man which are most significantly
human, that is, his mental functions, are based ultimately on natural processes: to put it
in its simplest form, that the brain, as a physiological system, is the organ of the mind.III want to spend a bit of time considering the gap between this general
principle of scientific naturalism as applied to man - i.e., scientific naturalism and
determinism - on the one hand, and particular specifications of it on the other. One of
the themes which I shall develop concerns the ways in which our acknowledgement of
determinism as applied to man plays a socio-political role in inducing a kind of fatalism.
That is to say, I intend to examine the project of searching for the limits of human
nature, and to attempt to lay bare what seem to me to be some of its goals and some of its
latent functions. In doing this I hope to bring moral and political criteria to bear on
that project. In the end, I shall stand it on its head, or perhaps turn it inside out, and
suggest that we might just as fruitfully search for the human limits of nature as for the
limits of human nature. I am not just playing with words in suggesting that the project of
searching for the limits of human nature is itself problematic. In conducting this
critique, I shall touch briefly on ethology and talk quite a bit about biology and
psychology and the sociology of knowledge from a Marxist perspective. My aims are to show
that there is an implied fatalism in the project itself, that it plays a role in treating
men like things (i.e., that it reifies men), and that it is an important aspect of our
alienation from our own belief that we can shape the world - or at least that we can try
to shape the world - as we wish.Now to consider the project itself: the limits of human nature are
presumed to be natural. That is, according to the theory of evolution, man's origins and
his nature are the results of, and are controlled by, the uniform laws which govern all
natural processes. To fly in the face of these laws in setting goals for ourselves and for
society is at one level quixotic and at another strictly impossible. So, if we would know
how men should live, it is certainly prudent to inquire about the constraints on how they
can live. Since nothing transcends the laws of nature, the relevant scientific findings
and generalizations will show us how men must live. The limits of human nature are, once
again, presumed to be natural. The investigation of natural processes is the domain of
science. Therefore science will, if anything can, teach us how men should, can, and must
live. Science is done by scientists, men who are highly-trained experts. It is to them
that we must turn for sciences of behaviour, of ethics, of society and of politics.This may sound crude. I think it is. But I also think it conveys the
assumptions underlying this series of essays. If we look at the Prospectus to the original
ICA lecture series we are told that the series 'aims to ask what are the irreducible
foundations of human nature on which culture builds, and whether there are limits within
which human nature develops or evolves'. Four specifications of this project are spelled
out: first, 'in what sense is it meaningful to talk of "constraints" or
"limits" on human nature'; second, 'what limits have been defined in the past';
third, 'what such limits could be suggested in the light of modern science'; and fourth,
'what are the ideological implications of differing theories about human nature'. My
contribution falls under the last heading, the ideological implications of differing
theories about human nature, but I intend it to reflect back on the other specifications.First, I want to notice two features of these formulations. Our
attention is drawn to the ideological 'implications' of differing theories about
human nature, and it is elsewhere said that 'Science is often pressed into service to
justify models of political and economic behaviour'. It is often pointed out that power
lies with the person who defines the situation or the question. These formulations, it
seems to me, tacitly assume that science is one thing and its ideological implications
quite another, and that the findings and theories of science are neutral. Particular
interest groups then come along and use or abuse them - they 'press them into service' to
justify models of political and economic behaviour. If we accept these formulations our
task is very clear: be vigilant in preventing the employment of scientific ideas as
justifications for models of political and economic behaviour. If we do this, the argument
runs, science will have no ideological implications. The reason is that the same
view which separates science from ideology, defines ideology as 'an inverted, truncated,
distorted reflection of reality'.[4]It seems worth while to spend a little time looking at the concept of
ideology, and in doing so I shall be guided by Lefebvre's useful essay, 'Ideology and the
Sociology of Knowledge'. 'Ideologies', by this account, 'come down to false
representations of history or to abstractions from history. Every ideology, then, is a
collection of errors, illusions, mystifications, which can be accounted for by reference
to the historical reality it distorts and transposes.[5] 'Ideologies operate by
extrapolating the reality they interpret and transpose.[6] This is not to say that
ideologies reflect no reality, but that they attempt to represent all of
reality in terms which reflect the interests of particular groups. Ideologies
generalize 'special interests - class interests - by such means as abstraction, incomplete
or distorted representations, appeals to fetishism'.[7] 'Once ideology is related to the
real conditions that gave rise to it, it ceases to be completely illusory, entirely
false.[8]The reality it conveys is real, but partial. 'Ideological
representations invariably serve as instruments in the struggle between groups (peoples,
nations) and classes (and fractions of classes). But their intervention in such struggles
takes the form of masking the true interests and aspirations of the groups involved,
universalizing the particular and mistaking the part for the whole.[9] 'In setting
out to answer all questions, all problems, they create a comprehensive view of the world.
At the same time they reinforce specific ways of life, specific behaviour patterns,
"values".[10] 'Thus every ideology represents a vision or conception of the
world, a Weltanschauung based on extrapolations and interpretations.[11] Ideologies
'refract (rather than reflect) reality via pre-existing representations, selected by
dominant groups and acceptable to them [12]This analysis of ideology, and indeed the modern conception of the
term, is derived from arguments which Marx and Engels developed in their work, The
German Ideology. [13] The basic assumption is that 'Those who wield material (economic
and political) power within the established social and juridical order also wield
"spiritual" power. The representations, i.e., the consciousness of society, are
elaborated into a systematic idealizing of existing conditions, those conditions which
make possible the economic, social and political primacy of a given group or class.'
Individual theorists and activists 'play an important part in forming the general
consciousness and in excluding representations contrary to the interests of the ruling
group. As a result, " their ideas are the dominant ideas of their epoch".[14]
This is not to say that such people are self-consciously deceptive. On the contrary, the
strength of ideological representations lies very much in the extent to which people
reflect and propagate views which they may not themselves self-consciously or
self-critically hold. The analogy to psychology is a good one. 'From everyday experience
we know that ideas serve often enough to furnish our actions with justifying motives in
place of the real ones. What is called rationalization at this level is called ideology at
the level of collective action. In both cases the manifest content of statements is
falsified by consciousness' unreflected tie to interests, despite its illusion of
autonomy.[15] Attempts to analyse ideologies seek to replace the alleged whole with
a clear and demystified picture of the part of society whose interests are being served.Now, let us recall how this discussion of the concept of ideology began
- with the assertion that science can have no ideological implications. The
relationship between science and ideology is said to be that between truth and error, or,
more accurately, between partial truths and special pleading. We must simply unmask the
attempts to press the findings and theories of science to the service of particular social
and political theories.Unfortunately, the situation is not so simple. The problems with which
we are concerned exist in two sorts of conceptual space where the terrain and boundaries
are very uncertain indeed. There are two extremely important gaps which reveal our
problem. The first lies between the general principle of scientific naturalism - as
specified in the theory of organic evolution - and particular findings which may or may
not be relevant to man in complex societies. Thus, for example, in the nineteenth century
when Herbert Spencer attempted to generalize the theory of evolution as a justification
for his own laissez-faire economic theories, Thomas Henry Huxley was able to come
along and say, 'That's all very nice, but the general theory of evolution does not imply
that - or any other - specific interpretation.'[16] The second gap lies between our
very limited knowledge of animal behaviour and the very complex issues which arise because
of human communication by language and by other cultural artefacts. We know that man is an
animal and that he has a great deal in common with other organisms, but we cannot with any
confidence directly apply findings from apes or rhesus monkeys - much less from pigeons
and rats - to human social situations. These are the reasons why one must treat the
arguments of people like Desmond Morris and B. F. Skinner with extreme caution - not that
they have no relevance, but that we are in no position to assess their relevance.These gaps - between the general principles and particular findings and
between other organisms and man - do not merely define our ignorance. They also indicate a
wide area within which speculation and ideological extrapolations can and do operate. But
the problem does not end here. It is relatively - I should say only relatively -
simple to guard against extrapolations from science in the service of particular
ideological positions. What is not so easy is the assessment of the role of ideology in
the assumptions and substance of perfectly reputable and cautious findings and theories in
science. If we take seriously the assertion that all thought is highly constrained by the
social and political context in which it occurs and that it is, in fundamental
ways, a mediation of that context, then why make an exception of scientific thought? If we
dig our heels in and make relative exceptions of some aspects of science - for example
physics and chemistry - we are still faced with a continuum of disciplines whose
fundamental concepts are more or less impregnated with social and political assumptions.
And if we are as cautious as we can be about reading in such assumptions, we will still
have to grant that the concept of human nature - of all concepts - is a happy hunting
ground for social and political preconceptions, especially in the hands of eminent
biologists.Thus, our problems lie in three domains: the relationship between
particular findings and the general principle of scientific naturalism, the relationship
between other organisms and man, and the foundations of particular scientific findings and
theories about other organisms and man. The nearer we get to what really interests
us as men in society, the more our debates - both as scientists and as laymen - reflect
our social and political contexts and assumptions, whether or not we are aware of those
influences. [17]What I am saying is not only that science is pressed into service to
justify models of political and economic behaviour, but that these models are constitutive
of the project of inquiring into human nature and society. Furthermore, the models deeply
influence the more basic biological sciences to which we turn for guidance. When the
participants in social and political debates turn to ethology, to genetics or to
psychology or evolutionary theory for guidance, what they hear is, to a considerable
extent, the echoes of their own debate, mediated and mystified in the form of science.As we attempt to find our way through this sparsely-charted territory,
we are uncertain about the boundaries, the landmarks and the possibility of the mapmaker's
being disinterested. This is not a fact about his intentions, but about the relationship
between thought and society, the relationship between knowledge and interest. One of the
most cautious and eminent of men who have reflected on biology, Professor René Dubos,
says this about scientific objectivity:Despite our pathetic attempt at objectivity, we as scientists are in
fact highly subjective in the selection of our activities, and we have goals in mind when
we plan our work. We make a priori decisions concerning the kinds of facts worth
looking for; we arrange these facts according to certain patterns of thought which we find
congenial; and we develop them in such a manner as to promote social purposes which we
deem important. [18]If this can be said of the goals and purposes of which scientists are aware, it is
likely to be even more relevant to the ones which they hold without self-conscious
awareness. IIII have deliberately dwelt at length on the general problems of science
and human nature before turning to particular examples. I want now to consider some
historical and current cases in the light of the approach which I have outlined, beginning
with some examples from this series of essays. Alan Ryan said in his discussion 'The
Nature of Human Nature in Hobbes and Rousseau', the concept of human nature sets 'a limit
to political possibility' [19] The sort of approach which I am proposing would say that it is
just as likely to be the case that political and ideological perspectives set definitions
to the limits of human nature - definitions which then lead men to despair of certain
political possibilities. In 'The Limits of Man and his Predicament', Arthur Koestler
argued that the trouble with our species is not what the ethologists say - aggression or
territoriality - but, rather, an excess of devotion to words, beliefs and groups. He also
pointed out the bad effects of language on our social and political lives, and touched on
the poverty of our perceptual apparatus and the split in evolution between the thinking
and the feeling parts of the brain .[20] Once again, it is just as arguable that our
problems are due in no small measure to an excess of deference to science in its
extrapolated form of scientism, alienating us from the belief that we can achieve a just
society. The alienation takes the form of saying that it's not on, because of our brain
structure, because of our language, because of the poverty of our perceptual apparatus.Turning now very briefly to ethology - which I will not discuss in
detail, because I want to treat it by analogy to another argument I am mounting - Michael
Chance discussed the concept of instinct, the role of fixed action patterns, patterns of
social organization. He offered us an analysis which is presumed to be relevant to man,
because it was included under the title 'The Dimensions of our Social Behaviour'. He
discussed 'hedonic' versus 'agonistic' bases for group cohesion among primates. (Lest it
be forgotten, we are primates.)[21] We have already got four terms, four conceptions,
which set some kinds of limits on what seems possible in man. The first is the concept of
instinct, the second that of aggression, which has wide currency in popular literature,
the third that of territoriality, and finally there is that of the hierarchical
organization of biological and bio-social systems. I want to address these putative limits
of human nature by considering a related concept, the analysis of which will shed light on
the others: that is, the psychoanalytic concept of the unconscious, which is based on a
theory of human instincts. If there were space, I would like also to go deeper into the
biological sciences and discuss some more fundamental ideas - the concept of function, the
concept of adaptation, the concept of equilibrium - three conceptions which are alleged to
be non-controversial, and which are seen as the coinage of discourse in the discipline.
All of these conceptions fall under a certain approach to the study of human nature.The limits of human nature are, once again, the limits of nature. But
the way that we approach those limits is in terms of refractoriness - the refractoriness
of nature, in spite of man's best efforts, compounded by the refractoriness of man's own
nature. In the period which gave rise to the modern versions of the conceptions with which
we are working and with which we have been conjuring in this series, there also arose a
continuous tradition of using science as a rationalization of existing economic and social
relations in society. This tradition extends from Adam Smith and Robert Malthus to the
present, all in the name of the relations between nature and human nature. I will not have
time to consider Adam Smith, but his own 'scientific' analysis of the economy was a
justification of laissez-faire and of the hierarchical division of labour. [22] If
we turn to Thomas Robert Malthus, and if we read a late edition of his work, as Darwin
did, we find that the clear ideological assumptions behind his argument are overlaid by
ever-growing masses of statistical data. (It is one of those books which accreted as it
went through editions.) But if one looks at the first edition, one finds that it was a
polemic, and avowedly so, against revolutionary utopian and anarchist views, addressed
specifically to Rousseau, Condorcet and Godwin.I want to quote a few passages towards the end of his argument, just to
give some idea. Malthus's Essay on the Principle of Population is supposed to be
the foundation of the modern mathematical treatment of man's relationship to nature.
Malthus says that 'The savage would slumber for ever under his tree unless he were roused
from his torpor by the cravings of hunger or the pinchings of cold, and the exertions that
he makes to avoid these evils, by procuring food, and building himself a covering, are the
exercises which form and keep in motion his faculties, which otherwise would sink into
listless inactivity.' 'Necessity has with great truth been called the mother of
invention'.[23] A little later, he says:As the reasons, therefore, for the constancy of the laws of nature seem, even to our
understandings, obvious and striking; if we return to the principle of population [the
principle that population will grow geometrically while man's ability to feed himself can
only grow arithmetically] and consider man as he really is, inert, sluggish, and averse
from labour, unless compelled by necessity (and it is surely the height of folly to talk
of man, according to our crude fancies of what he might be), we may pronounce with
certainty that the world would not have been peopled, but for the superiority of the power
of population to the means of subsistence. . . . Had population and food increased in the
same ratio, it is probable that man might never have emerged from the savage state. [24]He says on the next page that 'If no man could hope to rise or fear to fall, in
society, if industry did not bring with it its own reward and idleness its punishment, the
middle parts [i.e., the middle class] would not certainly be what they now are.[25]I have quoted Malthus at length, because I think that his argument is a watershed for
conceptions of man in nature, and I think that we still live in that watershed. It is a
century and three-quarters since Malthus penned those words about the middle class. I
venture to suggest that many would still accept his assertions about the middle class, but
with heavy irony. Malthus's analysis set in train a double history, a history of science
inextricably bound up with ideology, which embraced man as a part of nature and subject to
natural laws, at the same time that the findings and laws of the scientific study of man
were interpreted in a reconciling and rationalizing way, bringing men to accept the
existing order of society as part of the immutable order of nature.There are two points to be made about this: a general one about the
relations between scientific naturalism as applied to man in general and the uniformity of
nature on the one hand, and particular laws about particular societies on the other; and a
second, deeper point which raises the problem of how much the ideological perspective is
determinate in the formation of particular reputable scientific laws. Since Malthus, it
has been increasingly assumed that the hopes of man for a better society are faced with
two insurmountable mundane obstacles: the limits of his own nature and the niggardliness
of a hostile environment. He lacks resources sufficient to exploit nature to yield plenty,
and his own sloth and his own cravings produce inevitable suffering. The Malthusian
argument, I stated a moment ago, is a watershed. I mean this in a general sense - that, as
someone said, it cast gloom over the whole nineteenth century,[26] and I think we can find
that gloom still spread over our newspapers. But, more particularly, it was a direct and
specific influence in the development of the theories of evolution, on which our own
interest in the biological limits of human nature depends. Thus, for example, Darwin
specifically and avowedly derived his own mechanism of natural selection from Malthus.
Darwin was stuck for an answer and he picked up Malthus one day in 1838 and had a proper
'Eureka!' experience. [27] Having gained respectability in biology, the same theory, now
in a scientific form, emerges again as a social theory in the ideas of Walter Bagehot and
in the whole development of Social Darwinism - the theories of the group of writers
discussed by Raymond Williams.[28] The general conception which was put forward was the
promise of progress at the cost of struggle, a conception which Malthus was offering as a
modification of the belief in inevitable and relatively painless progress towards utopia.
His was a more painful process of progress through struggle.In the course of the nineteenth century the concept of progress came to
depend on the theory of organic evolution. Condorcet, Benjamin Franklin, William Godwin
and others had written on progress as a theoretical possibility and placed their hopes for
it in the future developments of science. But, as Dubos reminds us, it was the doctrine of
organic evolution - the mechanism which Darwin developed on the basis of Malthus's theory
- 'which eventually provided the theoretical basis for the concept of progressive
historical change. The doctrine of evolution therefore provides one of the most striking
examples of the influence of scientific knowledge on modern culture', an influence which
is now almost universal.[29] Theoretical biology has introduced into human thought a new
element - guaranteed progress - which pervades all aspects of traditional culture.[30] But
- and this is one of the themes I wish to stress - at a price. It is a double-edged
theory: progress through struggle. We must reconcile ourselves to the 'necessary'
inequalities and suffering as the 'inevitable' price which we must pay for that progress. IVYou can buy a book called Marx and Engels on Malthus. That is,
Marx and Engels spent so much time fulminating against Malthus that somebody thought that
it was worth the trouble to collect it all together in one book.[31] And the reason they
did so was that the Malthusian conception - and the other ideas of classical economics
which were intimately related to it - took existing social and political relations and
called them natural relations. Existing social relations were rooted in the conventions of
the existing power-structure, but they came to be seen as manifestations of unalterable
laws of nature. Marx and Engels were utterly opposed to the claim that it is unnatural
that other kinds of society might come to be. This was not only the nineteenth-century
critique of Marx and Engels: if you are following the current debate, you will find that
it is the same critique mounted by Georg Lukács in History and Class Consciousness. The
same critique was mounted by Lucien Goldmann, by István Mészáros, by Wilhelm Reich, by
Herbert Marcuse and by Jürgen Habermas.[32] But it is neither a new debate nor one
confined to Marxist circles. In the nineteenth century, the argument took place within the
biological and critical literature. For example, the co-discoverer of the theory of
organic evolution was Alfred Russel Wallace. Just six years after he had discovered the
theory independently from Darwin, he came to consider its relationship to his own
socialist beliefs. In that tussle the Malthusian aspect of evolution lost, and Wallace's
socialism won out. Similarly, Henry George juxtaposed the conceptions of Progress and
Poverty, and produced for the nineteenth century the alarming thesis that progress produced poverty.[33] And finally, as Raymond Williams has mentioned, Prince Kropotkin tried to
say, 'Yes, of course we must base our social theory on biological theory, but let us look
again at biological theory.' He found that mutual aid and co-operation were extremely
important factors in evolution, balancing the role of struggle for existence.[34]All of these views in the biological and social sphere were explicitly
anti-Malthusian. One of the things I am trying to support is the claim that we are still
living according to a conception of human nature which is fundamentally Malthusian. This
conception lies at the bottom of our interest in ethology and psychology and genetics as
potential keys to the limits of human nature. But instead of turning directly to these
disciplines, I want to conduct my argument as a critique of some aspects of
psychoanalysis, a discipline which depends on the same assumptions about the limits of
human nature. Before doing that, however, lest you think that I am creating straw men, I
should like to refer you to the arguments of Professor C. D. Darlington, which have
recently been erected on the basis of genetics: that the existing order of society is as
it is and as it must be because genetics says so. I have discussed this elsewhere and do
not want to go into it here.[35] But I have found a new piece of evidence which I should
like to share with you. This is a recent Friday Evening Discourse at the Royal Institution
in London by Sir Hans Krebs, Nobel Prize Winner in Physiology and Medicine, and Professor
of Biochemistry at Oxford: 'Some Facts of Life - Biology and Politics [36] It begins
by suggesting that we take a biological approach to social problems:My approach is based on my training as a physician and a biologist, and
the thesis which I shall put forward argues that one of the roots of many troubles is an
inadequate appreciation of basic biological principles - of the facts of life - which
govern the conduct and wellbeing of homo sapiens.[37]Fact No. 1: unless life is constantly renewed by hard effort, it runs down. The
individual must eat and drink, and through clothing and shelter he must protect himself
against the inclement environment. In a highly developed society he has to earn so that he
can buy food and shelter; and to earn means that he must render some service for which
somebody is willing to pay. He who does not render such service to society fails to
contribute to life and has to be carried by others.[38]Fact No. 2: is the fact that the lives of societies, such as nations,
are, in principle, subject to the same laws as the lives of individuals. A nation, like an
individual, has to earn its living in the face of tough competition. [39]Fact No. 3: is the fact that homo sapiens, like all other
species, does not by nature work unless he has an incentive. Effective incentives are the
need for food and shelter, and a desire for pleasure. In the last resort these are all to
be had for money, and for the great majority of homo sapiens (there are of course
exceptions) money is the greatest single incentive for overcoming natural laziness.... If
productive work is one of the bases on which the well-being and strength of society rests,
the laws of social organization should do everything to encourage work .[40]Successive governments, by their tax laws, have deterred people from
making the optimal contribution to the welfare of the country and, indeed, unions have
done the same thing by their restrictive practices. 'Let me emphasize that this is a
mistake of successive governments irrespective of party. I am not concerned with party
politics but with biology; the need for incentives is a biological phenomenon. [41]... a continued decrease in working hours is an unrealistic and utopian
dream. The survival of nations, alas, is a matter of ruthless competition with other
nations. An ineffectual or lazy nation is weak in competing in world trade because the
goods that it produces are liable to be expensive. It's also slow in making weapons to
defend itself against harder working nations. It may thus be starved out or destroyed by
them.[42]A strong society, then, is one where constructive work - and this of
course includes the unpaid labour of the housewife and voluntary social work and creative
hobbies - is planned to be healthy and efficient .[43](I am sure that, having read this argument, the supporters of Women's
Liberation will cease forthwith to fly in the face of these 'facts of life'.)Sir Hans Krebs goes on to talk about 'the beast in man', the genetic
basis of criminality, and the failure of the law to protect society. In short, he assumes
that inequality, private property and deviant behaviour are the result of unalterable laws
of nature.He also thinks that it is extremely important that society - for
biological reasons, of course - should not change too rapidly because man cannot adapt to
the welfare state, trade union protection, the restraining influences of competition, or
changes in customs such as the new permissiveness. It is 'the responsibility of society to
keep a constant watch on the consequences of any change which it introduces....[44]
We must keep society in 'equilibrium' - one of the concepts which I said I wished there
was space to discuss.[45] His account is also said to explain 'anti-foreigner and the
anti-racial feeling and the religious strife which we at present witness in Northern
Ireland'. All these attitudes have a deep biological root.[46] Krebs says we must 'face
the facts' and orient our lives accordingly. All this follows 'logically', he claims, from
what he has stated before, such as the biological basis of the evil-doer. [47] What we
need, he concludes, is a 'spiritual revival', new 'inspiring leadership' and close
attention to the 'facts of life. [48]Now, of course, I have chosen this because it is an easy target. But I
have also chosen it because of the position which Sir Hans Krebs occupies as a professor,
as a Nobel Laureate (every medical student - I had to do it when I was a medical student -
has to learn the Krebs Sugar Cycle). It is the relationship between that eminence and
these arguments to which I wish to draw attention. The eminence provides a licence to
mount these arguments. When Richard Nixon elicits deference by extolling the 'work ethic'
or national security, we are at least clear that he is talking politics; when eminent
biologists do so we are increasingly finding ourselves deferring on the basis of respect
for science. I take it that this is why the series of talks on 'The Limits of Human
Nature' was organized, and why the latter may sell a lot of paperbacks. But I also chose
to discuss Krebs's arguments, because they so neatly echo the passages from Malthus which
I was quoting earlier. Malthus, Krebs and Nixon have a considerable amount in common,
aside from being winners in the struggle for existence. Have we no alternative but to
defer to them? VI think we do have an alternative and I now want to spell it out by
considering a version of neo-Malthusianism. The current analogy to the dismal science of
classical economics - i.e., to the arguments of Adam Smith, Malthus and Ricardo - is, I
think it fair to say, the psychoanalytic view of man, one which is slowly being reinforced
by and integrated with ethology. The arguments which I shall review are, in principle,
based on the same sort of approach. A critique of some of the assumptions of
psychoanalysis can thus lead to a general critique of science and scientism. You will
recall that Freud strove mightily to formulate his theory in terms of the physico-chemical
sciences. Indeed, in 1895 he engaged on a project which he wrote out and later ordered to
be torn up (it wasn't), in which he tried to express his new and odd findings in strictly
neurophysiological terms .[49] He later moved on to a metaphorical representation of the
same conception, so that we have in the psychoanalytic theory 'mental forces', mental
energies', 'mental structures' - that is, terms borrowed from the physical and chemical
sciences and expressed metaphorically. We also have the biological conception of
'instinct'.[50] The theory of instincts provides the basic structure of psychoanalytic
theory.[51]Freud developed his views of man in society in an essay, 'Civilization
and its Discontents',[52] and it is these views, as explicitly expressed there and as
contained throughout his mature writings, which I wish to review through the perspectives
of two theorists, Wilhelm Reich and Herbert Marcuse. I am using this approach as an
analytic tool to give us some conception of what it is like to get underneath the
'givenness' of these theories of instincts, of territory, of hierarchy, or of any other
theory which claims man must be like this or that and there is nothing we can do about it.
As Reich points out,Freud's cultural and philosophical standpoint was always that culture
owes its existence to instinctual repression and renunciation. The basic idea is that
cultural achievements are the result of sublimated sexual energy; from this it follows
logically that sexual suppression and repression are an indispensable factor in the
cultural process.This is the 'reality principle' on which civilization depends.[53]
Reich argues that 'What is correct in this theory is only that sexual suppression forms
the mass psychological basis for a certain culture, namely, the patriarchal
authoritarian one in all its forms. What is incorrect', he says, 'is the formulation
that sexual suppression is the basis of culture in general.' [54]It is a basic error of official psychoanalysis to think of the impulses as absolute
biologically given facts; true, this is not inherent in psychoanalysis but in the
mechanistic thinking of the analysts which, as is always the case with mechanistic
thinking, is supplemented with metaphysical theses. Impulses also develop, change and
subside.[55]Reich also argues that anti-social impulses 'result from social
repression of normal sexuality', and that 'they have to be repressed because society -
rightly - does not allow them to be satisfied'.... these impulses are considered biological facts by
psychoanalysts. ...This naïve mechanistic biologism is so difficult to unmask because it
serves a definite function in our society: that of shifting the problem from the
sociological to the biological realm where nothing can be done about it.[56]Reich argues, on the other hand, that 'There is such a thing as the sociology of the unconscious and of antisocial sexuality, that is, a social history of
the unconscious impulses with regard to their intensity as well as their contents. Not
only is repression a sociological phenomenon, but also that which causes the
repression. [57]The fact that this reality principle is itself relative, that it
is determined by an authoritarian society and serves its purposes, this decisive fact goes
carefully unmentioned; to mention this, they say, is 'politics' and science has nothing to
do with politics. They refuse to see the fact that not to mention it is also politics.[58]When psychoanalysis does not dare to accept the consequences of its
findings, it points to the allegedly non-political (unpragmatic) character of the science,
while, in fact, every step of the psychoanalytic theory and of the practice deals with
political (pragmatic) issues. [59]The compulsive moral point of view of the political reaction is that of
an absolute antithesis between biological impulse and social interest. Based on this
antithesis, the reaction points to the necessity of moral regulation; for, they say, were
one to 'eliminate morals', the 'animal instincts' would gain the upper hand and this would
'lead to chaos'. It is evident that the formula of the threatening social chaos is nothing
but the fear of human instincts.[60]'What is meant by social order', he argues, is the particular, and in
his view 'the reactionary social order, and by personality development is meant the
development of a personality which is capable of adjusting to that order.[61]
He talks in particular about the role of the family. One of the conceptions which lies at
the root of psychoanalytic assumptions is that the psychoanalytic drama is worked out
within the family. In a similar way the studies in ethology, e.g., the studies of rearing
of monkeys, take particular sorts of family relationship as basic. Reich wants to offer a
critique of the family, a critique of the concept of work, and of all the things which are
taken as fixed and unalterable in the project of research on the limits of human nature.
He points out that the role of the family has changed in the development of modern society
from a primarily economic to a political function.Its cardinal function, that for which it is mostly supported and
defended by conservative science and law, is that of serving as a factory for
authoritarian ideologies and conservative structures. It forms the educational
apparatus through which practically every individual of our society, from the moment of
drawing his first breath, has to pass. It influences the child in the sense of a
reactionary ideology not only as an authoritarian institution, but also on the strength of
its own structure; it is the conveyor belt between the economic structure of conservative
society and its ideological superstructure; its reactionary atmosphere must needs become
inextricably implanted in every one of its members. Through its own form, and through
direct influencing, it conveys not only conservative ideologies and conservative attitudes
towards the existing social order; in addition, on the basis of the sexual structure to
which it owes its existence and which it procreates, it exerts an immediate influence on
the sexual structure of the children in the conservative sense .[62]The basis of the middle class family is the relationship of the
patriarchal father to wife and children. He is as it were the exponent and representative
of the authority of the state in the family. Because of the contradiction between his
position in the production process (subordinate) and his family function (boss) he is a
top-sergeant type; he kowtows to those above, absorbs the prevailing attitudes (hence his
tendency to imitation) and dominates those below; he transmits the government and social
concepts and enforces them.[63]'The anchoring of sexual morality and the changes it brings about in
the organism, create specific psychic structures which form', Reich argues, 'the mass
psychological basis for an authoritarian social order.' He concludes that 'the evaluation
of the family thus becomes the keystone for the evaluation of the general nature of
different kinds of social order'.[64]I am not asking you to agree with this point of view, but only to
notice that he has adopted a critical attitude to what is taken as biologically fixed in
the orthodoxy of psychoanalysis, of ethological studies, and, a fortiori, to the
belief that you can mount very general social and political arguments on the basis of
genetics or any branch of the biological sciences. Let me take an example which makes
criticisms of Reich's work based on ethology. In his disappointing book on Reich, Charles
Rycroft argues: 'His whole political, social and sexual stance can indeed be interpreted
as a massive rejection or dismissal of the problem of dominance in human relationships. It
was, he believed, possible to conceive of a world in which nobody dominated anybody in any
way whatsoever.' I said that I was going to attempt to illuminate assertions about
ethology by discussing psychoanalysis. Rycroft goes on: 'One again wonders what he would
have made of the recent ethological work which suggests that the establishment of
hierarchies, in which each member of a group has and knows his place, is one of the basic
biological mechanisms for maintaining peace and cohesion within groups. [65] Thus,
Reich's arguments are decisively refuted by the pecking-order in any farmer's henyard.This cryptic dismissal of Reich's views on dominance and hierarchies should not be
taken lightly. There is a developing alliance between orthodox psychoanalysis and the
rapidly-growing field of speculation based on the study of animal behaviour, ethology. For
our purposes, this marriage of ideological convenience begins with certain speculations (On
Aggression) which Konrad Lorenz, the father of much of both scientific and pop'
ethology, developed while working with American psychoanalysts.[66] On the particular
question of dominance, my own fleeting reference to the pecking-order in a farmer's henyard refers to the beginnings of the modern ethological investigation of one organism's
keeping another in check by threatening behaviour. This competitiveness had been justified
on economic and then biological grounds throughout the nineteenth century.[67] But since
the observations of domestic fowls by the Norwegian zoologist Thorlief Schjelderup-Ebbe in
1913, the alleged biological basis for the hierarchical division of labour has received
renewed support from the study of animal behaviour.[68] The generalizations and
extrapolations which have been based on this and on other studies are now much disputed.
For example, one recent critical reviewer of the shortcomings of social dominance theory
remarks:There remains the problem of why social dominance came to be accepted
as the normal structuring mechanism of primate societies. There is a great deal of
evidence indicating that the early studies which contributed so much towards the
establishment of the concept as a normal structuring mechanism, were in fact studies of
populations under severe social stress .[69]But the caution with which these concepts are treated in the
professional literature has not inhibited popularizers of ethology from making the sorts
of remarks which give critics of the critics of orthodox psychoanalysis - e.g., Rycroft -
a confident air. For example, in one of the most widely-read works in this genre, Desmond
Morris says of us 'naked apes', 'As primates we were already loaded with the hierarchy
system. This is the basic way of primate life.[70] More recently, two South African
authors have devoted an entire book to the issue: The Dominant Man: The Mystique
of Personality and Prestige. Here are some representative passages from their chapters
'Animal Dominance' and 'The Submissive Personality': 'History and anthropology demonstrate
that all human societies are organized around some kind of dominance hierarchy . . .'.
But, they say, this must be seen in the light of 'the animal background against which
human dominance must be viewed if we want to keep it in its proper biological perspective
. . .'.[71]In a matter of two or three decades, the ethologists have brought about
a revolution in man's understanding of his social behaviour. . . . In particular, we now
know that a type of dominance that can scarcely be distinguished from human dominance is
characteristic of all socially organized birds and mammals .[72]In fact, the dominance hierarchy, of which the chicken-yard pecking order is an
elementary example, has since been shown to be the basic form of social organization in
all vertebrate species. [73]So, biology proves that society cannot be fundamentally changed, and human history
reflects this 'basic form'.Frequent reference to dominance and subordination in our day-to-day
language, as well as man's long-standing dependence on the division of large communities
into caste hierarchies, clearly shows the extent to which the dominance order system
continues to play a central part in human affairs. In fact, the anthropologist Lionel
Tiger has referred to the dominance order as the universal spinal cord of a human
community. Throughout history, certain basic social patterns along pecking order lines
have recurred time and again with little variation. Human communities have displayed an
overwhelming tendency to stay in the well-worn grooves of dominance and submission.
Political revolutions break out with brilliant new social ideas. One or two new ideas may
stay, but for the most part the hierarchy system reasserts itself in a new disguise and
the egalitarian movement disintegrates.[74]Lionel Tiger and his collaborator, Robin Fox, have indeed combined
anthropological, sociological and ethological arguments in support of this conclusion,[75]
and it has been further supported by a recent historical and political analysis of ten
modern revolutions, none of which resulted in the elimination of an hierarchical social
order but which - whatever their other achievements - only produced 'the circulation of élites' in politics and society.[76] The author of Modern Revolutions would be the
last to appeal to biology in support of his conclusions, but biologists and social
scientists seem only too willing to lend a pessimistic basis to the dismal failure to
transcend authoritarian structures which history does indeed indicate. We are assured in The
Dominant Man that pre-history, history and genetics say that it must be so.The result of many millions of years' development in a social direction
is that every hierarchical animal now possesses the ability to abandon its competitive
feelings in the presence of an acknowledged superior - a special arrangement of
psychological equipment which allows a weaker animal to accept the domination of a worthy
leader.[77]The exact way in which a subordinate submits to authority will
obviously vary from one species to another. The various psychological and physiological
processes that contribute to the deferential behaviour of a human being will presumably be
more amenable than most to cultural conditioning. Nevertheless, the presence of an
underlying genetic foundation is beyond question.'[78]Man, like every other successful vertebrate, has evidently inherited a
well-developed capacity for deference which checks his dominance ambitions at appropriate
moments.... Since everybody must settle for a unique interpersonal position relative to
everybody else's, we are left with a society of unequals.'[79]I have quoted this book at length as a parallel to my treatment of Sir
Hans Krebs's 'Facts of Life' and for the same reasons. I have done so before concluding my
remarks on Reich's critique of psychoanalysis, in order to help us to see what we are up
against in attempting to take a critical approach to various forms of biologism. Reich was
deeply critical of Freudian biologism, 'the tendency to treat as universal and
biologically inevitable attitudes and impulses' which can be equally argued to be
determined by cultural conditions. He rejected biologism and accepted Freud's early view
'that neurosis is basically the result of the conflict between instinctual needs and the
reality which frustrates them', but he felt that the outcome of this conflict was not
biologically predetermined. The problem was one of altering the social reality rather than
of succumbing to Freud's pessimistic cultural philosophy, with its roots in biologistic
fatalism. Rather than seeing society as the result of a biologically-based psychic
structure, he saw character-structure as the result of a certain kind of society.[80] 'As
soon as an ideology has taken root in the structure of people and has altered it, it has
become a material social power.[81] His advocacy of psychoanalysis was combined with a
critical approach to its implicit support for authoritarian society. He argued that
bourgeois society produces the character structure it requires by means of the mediation
of social institutions.His criticisms of authoritarianism in the family, the school and in
religion were based on an attempt to integrate his Marxism with his psychoanalytic work.
Where Freud saw a contradiction between Marxism and psychoanalysis, Reich used aspects of
each to provide illumination and evaluation of the other. He was as critical of official
communist orthodoxy as he was of the orthodox Freudians, and was also an early explorer of
the parallels between Hitler's fascism and Stalin's. All three orthodoxies reviled him: he
was expelled from Freud's circle as well as from the Communist Party, he had to flee from
Hitler's Germany, and his works were banned by the Gestapo.Nearly four decades have elapsed since his early work, which is now being separated
from the eccentricities of his later ideas, his bizarre theories and his tragic end in an
American prison.[82] If we want to learn about the role of ideology in our definitions of
'the limits of human nature', a critical reading of Reich's work is of great potential
benefit, especially The Mass Psychology of Fascism, The Sexual Revolution and
his pamphlets 'What is Class Consciousness?' and 'Dialectical Materialism and
Psychoanalysis. [83] VINow I want to discuss Marcuse for a while. I am lumping Marcuse and
Reich together, rather than splitting them, although there are important differences
between them.[84] For example, Marcuse argued that Reich failed to make any essential
distinction between repressive and non-repressive sublimation, and that Reich's
sociological insights involve what Marcuse calls 'a sweeping primitivism'. He agreed with
Reich's emphasis on instinctual repression as the root cause of authoritarianism and
deference to it but disagreed with Reich's belief that it could be overcome by
concentrating on sexual liberation.[85] Marcuse raises the same sorts of issues that I
have been discussing but in a slightly more precise and systematic (and therefore less
personally resonant) form. He grants that there is such a thing as the reality to which
man must adapt, but he wants to distinguish the inescapable aspects of that reality from
those aspects which are peculiar to the existing social order. That is, he wants to make a
distinction between the Freudian reality principle and the extra requirements of existing
societies which he calls the 'performance principle [86] Similarly, he wants to make
a distinction between the legitimate domain of repression and that extra or 'surplus'
repression which is attributable to specific social orders.[87] And finally, he wants to
note that 'sublimation' is not easily put aside, in the sense that one can come along and
say, 'Oh! we now have a permissive society'. Society can and does offer that kind of
permissiveness in a repressive form which he calls 'repressive de-sublimation'.[88] He
makes an analogous argument at the straightforward political level about the concept of
tolerance - that you can let tolerance flower in a way which is objectively repressive,
just as you can de-sublimate in a way which is objectively repressive.[89] Like Reich,
Marcuse argues that psychoanalysis - which represents itself as based on biology - is
fundamentally social and historical. He turns psychoanalysis against itself, and claims
that the Freudian theory of instincts makes it possible to understand the hidden nature of
certain decisive tendencies in current politics. He points out that the basic
psychoanalytic concepts are social and political. They 'do not have to be
"related" to social and political conditions - they are themselves social and
political categories'. Thus, he argues that Freud 'discovered the mechanisms of social and
political control in the depth dimension of instinctual drives and satisfactions'.[90] In
the Freudian account of socialization, the superego absorbs the authoritarian models of
'the father and his representatives, and makes their commands and prohibitions its own
laws, the individual's conscience'.[91] Thus, 'The individual reproduces on the deepest
level, in his instinctual structure, the values and behaviour patterns that serve to
maintain domination. . . .[92] This occurs within the family, which reflects the
dominant patterns in the society. He goes further and claims that society has proceeded to
take some of these functions out of the hands of the family and place them in the schools,
in the mass media, and in other public forms.[93]Marcuse maintains that if we take seriously the possibilities of
liberation, we must acknowledge that our struggles will fly in the face of conceptions of
'the biologically given', and transcend 'the laws of nature' as now conceived. His
argument rests on two assertions. The first is that science has created the means to
overcome the scarcities, the struggle for existence, on which the pessimistic and
repressive social extrapolations from biology depend. This point is related to a deeper
one - that all human needs have an historical character. They are not merely fixed
by inheritance. They 'lie beyond the animal world. They are historically determined and
historically mutable.[94]When Marcuse was asked point-blank if he meant quite literally that this would involve
a 'qualitative transformation of the physiological structure of man' he said yes, but
added that human nature is not merely physiological. It is historically determined and
develops in history. Man does not thereby cease to have a natural history, but he can be
freed from its character of struggle for existence, and authoritarianism and alienation,
by our placing the techniques of advanced technology in the service of democracy rather
than domination.[95] Elsewhere, in his Essay on Liberation, Marcuse
equivocates on this point, and says that he does not use the terms 'biological' and
'biology' in the scientific sense.[96] But he turns around about ten pages later and
writes about changing the instinctual nature of man.[97] I make this point about his
equivocation, because I do not want it to be thought that the Right has a monopoly on
biologization. Both Reich and Marcuse - and indeed Reich to an absurd extent in his later
life - attempted to base their claims about the social changes they wanted, on exactly the
kinds of biological assumptions which they are criticizing in the works of traditional
theorists.[98]What I want to emphasize about these arguments, however, is that they
are deeply anti-Malthusian - or perhaps I should say post-Malthusian. That is, Malthus and
Freud argued that 'Progress is only possible through the transformation of instinctual
energy into the socially useful energy of labour, that is, progress is only possible as
sublimation.[99] Culture, according to Freud, 'is sublimation: postponed,
methodically controlled satisfaction which presupposes unhappiness. The "struggle for
existence", "scarcity", and co-operation all compel renunciation and
repression in the interests of security, order, and living together.[100] But the very
achievements of Malthusian and Freudian sublimation have opened the way to its
transcendence. The repressive reality principle becomes superfluous to the extent that
civilization is no longer oppressed by the kinds of scarcity, the struggle for existence,
which have led to our seeing them as absolute laws of nature. So the achievements of
repressive progress can 'herald the abolition of the repressive principle of progress
itself'.[101] 'What on more primitive cultural levels was - perhaps - not only a social
but also a biological necessity for the further development of the species has become, at
the height of civilization, a merely social, political "necessity" for
maintaining the status quo." [102] We have here an analogy to Reich's views on the
family. The reality principle has changed functions, from that of necessity in the
biological sense to that of necessity in the political and ideological sense. Marcuse
claims that '. . . at the present stage of civilization, much of the toil, renunciation,
and regulation imposed upon men is no longer justified by scarcity, the struggle for
existence, poverty, and weakness.[103]As I said, I have stressed the similarities between Reich and Marcuse,
but there are important differences. Reich considered Freud's essay 'Civilization and its
Discontents' an unmitigated disaster, and he rejected the Freudian antithesis between life
and death instincts, between love and aggression, Eros and Thanatos. Marcuse accepted the
distinction but wanted to modify it. But if we look at their respective later works, we
find Reich moving (as he became more paranoid) towards an antithesis between basic
energies - good and bad (there was the bad orgone for those who are connoisseurs of Reich)
- while Marcuse (I think under a certain amount of pressure from the student movement)
became more overtly libertarian. Marcuse advocated some forms of sublimation, but Reich
went much further and stressed the genuinely liberating potential of unqualified
desublimation. Thus we find them on some kind of continuum extending from Freud's
conventional Malthusian pessimism, in which civilization depends on repression; to
Marcuse's modified view, in which you divide between a natural and a conventional aspect
(that is, between proper repression and surplus repression, between a reality-principle
and a performance-principle) and in which the role of the second aspect of these was
particular to existing societies as distinct from possible ones; and finally to Reich's
nearly pure libertarianism, which led ultimately to arguments for sexual revolution which
concentrated on what might be called 'the politics of intimacy' at the expense of more
traditional radical strategies. Achieving orgiastic release was increasingly seen by Reich
as prior to attempts to change social and political structures in the public world.Marcuse and Reich have in common a critique of what Freud takes to be
'given' and 'natural', fixed and inevitable. They consider man's alleged instinctual
limitations to be problematic and historical. They may be 'given' for the individual, but
they are not assimilable to the immutable laws of nature. Rather, they are reflections of
a particular historical conjuncture, and different men with a different consciousness, not
fettered with Malthusian, Freudian, ethological, and/or genetic pessimism, might try to
bring about a different world.I hope that I have laid the groundwork for making comprehensible one of
Marcuse's more abstract passages on the need to transcend present views of science, of
nature and of human nature:In Nature as well as in History, the struggle for existence is the
token of scarcity, suffering and want. They are the qualities of blind matter, of the
realm of immediacy in which life passively suffers its existence. This realm is gradually
mediated in the course of the historical transformation of Nature; it becomes part of the
human world, and to this extent, the qualities of Nature are historical qualities. In the
process of civilization, Nature ceases to be mere Nature to the degree to which the
struggle of blind forces is comprehended and mastered in the light of freedom.And, to the degree to which Reason succeeds in subjecting matter to
rational standards and aims, all sub-rational existence appears to be want and privation,
and their reduction becomes the historical task. Suffering, violence, and destruction are
categories of the natural as well as human reality, of a helpless and heartless universe.
The terrible notion that the sub-rational life of nature is destined forever to remain
such a universe, is neither a philosophic nor a scientific one. . . .[104]Rather, its role is political in the widest sense: 'Glorification of the natural is
part of the ideology which protects an unnatural society in its struggle against
liberation.'[105] VIII want, finally, to consider some of the wider implications of this
critique. Marcuse points out that if we are going to take a transcending view of human
nature, then we must also take a transcending view of science. Once we have unmasked the
political character of much which passes for the 'given' in nature and human nature, then
we have to go on to see that there is an intimate relationship between our scientific
views and our political views. Marcuse says: 'But this development confronts science with
the unpleasant task of becoming political - of recognizing scientific consciousness
as political consciousness, and the scientific enterprise as political
enterprise.[106]Much depends on the way one asks the questions and what one is prepared
to accept as answers. Of course one would find limits to an ideological approach to
science and nature, as anybody who was wanting to have some wheat in the Soviet Union
during the Lysenko period could tell you.[107] At the same time, to be naïve about the
role of political assumptions in science is to acquiesce in a particular representation of
man, one which is in the service of a particular social order.We can generalize the discussion in the light of the views of Lukács,
Marcuse and Habermas. One of Habermas's disciples, Trent Schroyer, argues that
'Contemporary science and technology serve as a new strategy for legitimating power and
privilege.' 'Insofar as the practice of the scientific establishment is held to be
neutral' and applicable to all aspects of society 'while actually justifying the extension
of repressive control systems, we can assert that the contemporary self-image of science
functions as an all-embracing 'technocratic ideology'.[108] The gap of which I spoke
before, between the general principles of scientific naturalism and particular problems of
man in society, has been filled by the scientistic self-image of science. Where knowledge
is absent, extrapolation fills the domain of the moral and political debate about the
conflicting goals and interests of men. "'Scientism" means science's belief in
itself: that is, the conviction that we can no longer understand science as one form
of possible knowledge, but rather must identify [all] knowledge with science."[109]
Indeed, Schroyer claims that 'the scientistic image of science has become , a dominant
legitimating system of advanced industrial society.[110]More and more spheres of decision-making are being seen in a
technological and scientific way, requiring information and instrumental strategies
formulated by experts, and are therefore removed from political and moral debate.' [111]Now, I want to cast us back to Marx. He was able to formulate his
critique against a particular set of economic doctrines - the classical economics of
Smith, Malthus and Ricardo. We are forced to broaden ours in the face of this kind of
generalization of science, to the whole 'scientistic' theory of science itself, an
approach which Schroyer sees as 'the fundamental false consciousness of our epoch'.[112]
If we are going to begin to free ourselves from this defeatist approach; it seems to me
that we have to take a critical view of science, one which demystifies the treatment of
men as things, completely assimilable to the laws of the natural sciences as now
understood and as illegitimately generalized. This is the project which we are engaged
upon when we criticize the belief that we can find the limits of human nature. And if we
fail to seek the human limits of nature we will find ourselves in the position where the
distinction between deliberate, reasoned, debated social action and adaptive,
technological deferential action breaks down.' [113] That is, the distinction is becoming
meaningless without the kinds of critical reflection in which I think Reich and Marcuse,
for all their undoubted faults, have been engaged. If we do not take this kind of
approach, we shall find ourselves in the curious position of freeing man from the tyranny
of nature, of transcending the struggle for existence, but replacing that freedom with a
perfectly assimilated social coercion, again in the name of nature and of science. Science
therefore becomes the ideology of power, a totalized world view which produces a fatalism
on the one hand, and amenability to technological manipulation on the other. The
alternative is a critical and transcending view of science, one which looks hard at its
reifications, its fetishisms, its role in alienation, and, indeed, at the whole
scientistic programme.I am not suggesting that science is merely ideology, but that it is
ideology as well. This is especially true of debates about human nature. Our concepts of
nature and human nature are to a considerable extent mediations of our social, economic,
political and ideological preconceptions. When we turn to experts for knowledge of the
limits of human nature we are engaged in more far-reaching and fundamental forms of
deference than we realize. Marx taught us that exchange relationships, commodities, even
the means of production, are only the social relations and the labour of men in an
intransigent, fetishized, reified and alienated disguise. We should ask ourselves the
extent to which our ideas of nature and human nature are exactly the same thing. Ideology
is an all-pervasive material force, penetrating into our most intimate and subjective
relationships as well as into our putatively disinterested inquiries in the biological and
human sciences. We must recover our right to define our own nature through our struggles
to overcome our limitations. One component of this is the need to demystify the limits of
human nature. As Reich said, 'We must get into the habit of subjecting every fetishised
matter to the glaring light of naïve questions, which are notoriously the most testing,
the most promising and the most far-reaching. [114]This is not, of course, an entirely new view of science. In earlier periods there were
rich and deep criticisms of science which juxtaposed its presumption with human moral
values. They are worth re-reading: Marlowe's Doctor Faustus, Swift's Gulliver's
Travels, Mary Shelley's Frankenstein, Zamiatin's We. Then, perhaps, we can
approach B. F. Skinner's Walden Two and Beyond Freedom and Dignity, and some
other works which I have mentioned, with less deferential attitudes. We might even begin
to see the need to move on from interpreting the world in various fatalistic ways, to
changing it.
NOTES
1 Robert M. Young, 'Association of Ideas', in Philip P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary of
the History of Ideas (Scribner's, New York: in press).2 R. M. Young, Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth Century (Oxford
University Press, 1970); The Role of Psychology in the Nineteenth-Century
Evolutionary Debate', in Mary Henle et al., eds., Contribution to the History
of Psychology (Springer, New York: in press).3 Henri F. Ellenberger, The Discovery of the
Unconscious: The History
and Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry (Allen Lane The Penguin Press, 1970, esp.
Chs. 4, 5, 7).4 Henri Lefebvre, The Sociology of Marx (1966); trans. Norbert
Guterman (Allen Lane, 1968; also paperback), ch. 3, p. 64.5 ibid.6 ibid., p. 70.7 ibid., pp. 65-6.8 ibid., p. 65.9 ibid., p. 71.10 ibid., p. 70.11 ibid., p. 80.12 ibid., p. 69.13 Kari Marx and Frederick Engels, The German Ideology (1845-7);
trans. Clemens Dutt et al. (Progress, Moscow 1964); there are a number of paperback
editions of selections, for example the one edited, with an Introduction, by C. J. Arthur
(Lawrence & Wishart, 1970).14 Lefebvre, op. cit., p. 68. The internal quotation is from the
classical passage in The German Ideology (Progress edition), p. 61.15 Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests (1968),
Appendix: 'Knowledge and Human Interests: A General Perspective' (1965), trans. Jeremy J.
Shapiro (Heinemann, 1972; also paperback), p.311.16 For a representative selection of Herbert Spencer's views, see The
Man versus the State, with Four Essays on Politics and Society, edited, with an
Introduction, by Donald MacRae (Penguin Books, Harmondsworth 1969). For Huxley's
criticisms, see Thomas H. Huxley, Evolution and Ethics and Other Essays (1886-94), Collected Essays, vol. 9 (Macmillan, 1894).17 Liam Hudson has made a promising beginning to an analysis of the role of ideology in
psychology in The Cult of the Fact (Cape, 1972), esp. ch. 11; cf. David Ingleby,
'Ideology and the Human Sciences: Some Comments on the Role of Reification in Psychology
and Psychiatry', in Counter Course: A Handbook for Course Criticism, ed. Trevor
Pateman (Penguin Books, Harmondsworth 1972), pp. 51-81.18 René Dubos, 'Science and Man's Nature', in Science and Culture, ed. Gerald
Holton (Beacon paperback, Boston 1967), pp. 251-72, esp. pp. 259-60.19 See p. 13.20 See p. 49 ff.21 See p. 158 ff.22 See Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations (1776). A convenient edition is the Everyman, 2 vols. (Dent,
1910, etc; and Dutton, New York). Cf. R. M. Young, 'Darwinism and the Division of Labour'
(a sketch from Smith to the present), in Listener 88, No. 2264 (17 August 1972),
pp. 202-5.23 Thomas Robert Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population,
as it Affects the Future Improvement of Society with Remarks on the Speculations of
Mr. Godwin, M. Condorcet, and Other Writers (1798); a convenient reprint of the first
edition, from which these passages are quoted, is edited, with an introduction, by Antony
Flew (Penguin Books, Harmondsworth 1970), p. 203.24 ibid., pp. 205-6.25 ibid., p. 207.26 Humphrey House, 'The Mood of Doubt', in Ideas and Beliefs of the Victorians (Dutton paperback, New York 1966), pp. 71-7.27 R. M. Young, 'Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of
Biological and Social Theory', Past and Present No. 43 (May 1969), pp. 109-45, esp.
pp. 128-9.28 See p. 115 ff.29 Dubos, op. cit., pp. 253-4. Strictly speaking, the theory was
jointly discovered by Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace, and its popularization as
the basis for a theory of social progress owed more to Herbert Spencer than to Darwin and
Wallace. However, it is 'Darwinism' which gave scientific respectability to the general
conception. For a discussion of the public debate and its relations with the idea of
progress, see R. M. Young, 'The Impact of Darwin on Conventional Thought', in The
Victorian Crisis of Faith, ed. Anthony Symondson (S.P.C.K., 1970), pp. 13-35.30 Dubos, op. cit.31 Marx and Engels on Malthus, ed. Ronald L. Meek, trans.
Dorothea L. and R. L. Meek (International, New York 1954; also paperback).32 In a general essay of this kind it would be tedious and pointless to
cite much of the relevant literature, so I shall only mention certain key works. I have
attempted to provide a general overview of science and its history from a radical
perspective - with particular reference to the nineteenthcentury debate - in 'The
Historiographic and Ideological Contexts of the Nineteenth-Century Debate on Man's Place
in Nature', Changing Perspectives in the History of Science, ed. Mikulás
Teich and R. M. Young (Heinemann, 1973), pp. 344-438. These issues are related to the
current debate in an earlier paper 'Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and Now', in Science
Studies 1 (1971), pp. 177-206. Both of these papers are extensively annotated. The
present essay is in some ways an extension of those articles while at the same time it is
intended to be both more accessible to the general reader and a more particular
application of the issues raised therein, concentrating as it does on the relations
between biology and psychology. See Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness (1923); new edn (1967) with Preface, trans. Rodney Livingstone (Merlin, 1971); Lucien
Goldmann, The Human Sciences and Philosophy (1966), trans. Hadden V. White
and R. Anchor (Cape, 1969; also paperback); István Mészáros, Marx's Theory of
Alienation, 2nd edn (Merlin, 1970; also paperback); Wilhelm Reich, The Mass
Psychology of Fascism (1933), 3rd edn, revised and enlarged, trans. Vincent R.
Carfagno (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New York 1969; also paperback); Herbert Marcuse, One
Dimensional Man: the Ideology of Industrial Society (Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1964; also paperback); Jürgen Habermas, Toward a Rational Society: Student
Protest, Science, and Politics (1968-9), trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Heinemann, 1971;
also paperback), esp. ch. 6; see also above, note 15 and below notes 51, 53, 80-86, 88-90,
96, 98.33 See R. M. Young, "'Non-Scientific" Factors in the
Darwinian Debate', Actes du XIIe Congrès International d'Histoire des
Sciences (Blanchard, Paris 1971), vol. 8, pp. 221-6.34 Peter Kropotkin, Mutual Aid.. a Factor of Evolution (1902;
Allen Lane The Penguin Press, 1972); see also p. 125.35 C. D. Darlington, The Evolution of Man and Society (Allen
& Unwin, 1969); R. M. Young, 'Understanding It All', New Statesman 78 (26
September 1969), pp. 417-18; cf. 'Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and Now', op.
cit. (note 32), pp. 188, 205.36 Proceedings of the Royal Institution of Great Britain 44
(1971), pp. 169-184; reprinted in Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 15 (1972),
pp. 491-506.37 ibid., pp. 170-1.38 ibid., pp. 171-2.39 ibid., p. 172.40 Loc. cit.41 ibid., p. 173.42 ibid., pp. 173-4.43 ibid., p. 174.44 ibid., p. 179.45 The ideological use of the concepts of adaptation and equilibrium
have been touched upon in Cynthia E. Russett, The Concept of Equilibrium in
American Social Thought (Yale, New Haven 1966), and Barbara Heyl, 'The Haryard
"Pareto Circle"', J. Hist. Behav. Sci. 4 (1968), pp. 316-334.46 Krebs, 'Some Facts of Life', op. cit. (note 36), p. 180.47 ibid., p. 181.48 ibid., pp. 180,181, 183.49 Sigmund Freud, 'Project for a Scientific Psychology' (1895), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (Hogarth,
1966), vol. 1, pp. 283-346; M. Peter Amacher, Freud's Neurological Education and its
Influence on Psychoanalytic Theory (International Universities, New York 1965); Karl
H. Pribram,'The Neuropsychology of Sigmund Freud', in Experimental Foundations of
Clinical Psychology, ed. Arthur J. Bachrach (Basic Books, New York 1962), pp. 442-68;
'The Foundation of Psychoanalytic Theory: Freud's Neuropsychological Model', in Adaptation:
Selected Readings, ed. K. H. Pribram (Penguin Books, Harmondsworth 1969), pp. 395-432.50 Sigmund Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams (1900), in Standard
Edition, vols. IV-V, esp. ch. vii; 'Instincts and their Vicissitudes' (1915) and 'The
Unconscious' (1915), ibid., vol. XIV, pp. 109-40, 159-215; The Ego and the Id (1923),
ibid., vol. XIX, pp. 3-66; New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-analysis (1933),
lecture xxxi: 'The Dissection of the Psychical Personality', ibid., vol. XXII; Siegfried
Bernfield, 'Freud's Earliest Theories and the School of Helmholtz'in Psychoanalytic
Quarterly 13 (1944), pp. 341-62; 'Freud's Scientific Beginnings', Amer. Imago 6
(1949), pp. 3-36; 'Sigmund Freud, M.D., 1882-1885', International Journal of
Psycho-analysis 32 (1951), pp. 204-17; David Rapaport and Merton M. Gill, 'The Points
of View and Assumptions of Metapsychology', ibid., 40 (1959), pp. 153-62; David Rapaport, The
Structure of Psychoanalytic Theory: A Systematizing Attempt (International
Universities, New York 1960) - both of these are reprinted in The Collected Papers of
David Rapaport, ed. M. M. Gill (Basic Books, New York 1967), along with other
pertinent articles. The physical and physiological aspects of Freud's approach are also
discussed at length in the first volume of Ernest Jones, The Life and Work of Sigmund
Freud, 3 vols. (Basic Books, New York 1953-7).51 Although many aspects of the psychoanalytic movement - and in
particular the school known as 'ego psychology' - have played down the role of instinct,
it would be difficult to convince a serious reader of Freud's own work that his views were
not fundamentally based on a theory of instincts as the biological basis for the
individual's personality and for social behaviour. Whatever reservations might be held
about the relations between Freud's views and those of Wilhelm Reich, Reich's exposition
of Freud's fundamental theories makes this point convincingly. See W. Reich, Dialectical
Materialism and Psychoanalysis (1929), trans. anon. (Socialist Reproduction pamphlet,
1972), pp. 20 ff.52 Sigmund Freud, 'Civilization and its Discontents' (1930), Standard
Edition, vol. XXI, pp. 59-145; cf. The Future of An Illusion (1927), ibid., pp.
3-56 and Beyond the Pleasure Principle (1920), ibid., vol. XVIII, pp. 3-64. The
following works provide useful short introductions to Freud's thought: Charles Brenner, An
Elementary Textbook of Psychoanalysis (International Universities, New York 1955; also
Anchor paperback); Richard Wollheim, Freud (Fontana paperback, 1971).53 Wilhelm Reich, The Sexual Revolution: Toward a Self-Governing
Character Structure (1930), trans. Theodore P. Wolfe, 4th edn (1949), revised (Vision,
1969; also paperback), p. 10.54 ibid.55 ibid., p. xxx.56 ibid., p. 17.57 ibid., p. 18.58 ibid., p. 19.59 ibid., p. 20.60 ibid., p. 22.61 ibid., pp. 40-1.62 ibid., p. 72.63 ibid., p. 73.64 ibid., p. 79.65 Charles Rycroft, Reich (Fontana paperback, 1971), p. 56.66 Konrad Lorenz, On Aggression (1963), trans. Marjorie Latzke
(Methuen, 1966; also paperback), pp. ix-xiii. When Lorenz spoke about his growing belief
that the findings of ethology could be integrated with those of psychoanalysis, at a
meeting of experimental ethologists in Cambridge in the early 1960s, he was met with a
scepticism which was very prescient in the light of subsequent further popularizations and
speculations. This scientific caution has since been united with a political critique of
the ideological role of both psychoanalysis and 'pop' ethology. For an example of the
liaison between ethology and psychoanalysis as seen from the psychoanalytic side, see
Anthony Storr, Human Aggression (Allen Lane, 1968), dedicated to Lorenz, who on the
dust-jacket praises the book as 'a real synthesis of psychoanalytical and ethological
thought'.67 See p. 265, note 22.68 T. Schjelderup-Ebbe, 'Social Behavior of Birds' in Handbook of
Social Psychology, ed. Carl Murchison (Clark, Worcester, Massachusetts 1935),
pp. 947-72.69 J. S. Gartlan, 'Structure and Function in Primate Society', in Folia Primat. 8 (1968), pp. 89-120, esp. p.115; cf. T. E. Rowell, 'Hierarchy in the
Organization of a Captive Baboon Group', in Animal Behaviour 14 (1966), pp. 430-43;
Irwin S. Bernstein, 'Primate Status Hierarchies', in Primate Behavior: Developments in
Field Laboratory Research, ed. Leonard A. Rosenblum (Academic, New York 1970),
pp. 71-109. For a balanced, liberal critique of social generalizations in popular works on
ethology, written by a professional physical anthropologist, see Alexander Alland, Jr, The
Human Imperative (Columbia paperback, New York 1972).A professional ethologist, Dr Patrick Bateson (of the Sub-Department of
Animal Behaviour, University of Cambridge), points out that proponents of the view that
dominance is a fundamental feature of animal and human social organization could reply
that animal data are all the more relevant to the study of man because most human
populations are , under severe social stress'. (See Desmond Morris, The Human Zoo [Cape, 1969; also Corgi paperback].) Therefore, the argument runs, hierarchies are
inevitable (and even desirable) in this context, and to attempt to break them down would
be to treat symptoms rather than causes. A radical critique of this defence has two
components. First, one should emphasize that the 'severe social stress' of human societies
(especially advanced technocratic ones) is a social and historical phenomenon, and
therefore amenable to alteration if one ceases to see social conventions in biologically
reductionist terms. Second, to attempt to break down hierarchies without attacking their
structural basis in the anti-democratic order of such societies would indeed be to treat
symptoms rather than causes. This is part of the essential point of overcoming biological
fatalism: as a prerequisite to believing that fundamental structural change in the social
order and the resulting social relations is possible.Turning once again to the dominance concept in ethology, Bateson argues
that its inadequacy is that it provides such a partial description of social organization
and has very little explanatory power. If it is observed that one individual displaces
another in a particular context, the chances of predicting which one will displace the
other in a different context are pretty poor. Furthermore, while dominance hierarchies are
found throughout the animal kingdom (including cockroaches!), the distribution is spotty,
and the available evidence supports the hypothesis that what we call 'dominance' behaviour
has evolved for all sorts of disparate reasons. These reasons make the extrapolation from
animal data to the layman's conception of dominance in the human hierarchical division of
labour far too facile. Sophisticated ethologists are currently very wary of genetic
reductionist explanations and are increasingly employing richer interpretations of
behaviour which is characteristic of a given species. They are also granting a very
important role to historical factors in understanding the antecedents and characteristics
of human behaviour.70 Desmond Morris, The Naked Ape (Cape, 1967; also paperback).
The quotation is taken from the 7th (!) Canadian printing of the Bantam Books paperback
edition (New York 1969) of 'The Runaway Bestseller in England and America', p. 128.71 Humphry Knipe and George Maclay, The Dominant Man: The Mystique of Personality and Prestige (Souvenir, 1972), p. 2.72 ibid., pp. 2-3.73 ibid., p. 5.74 ibid., p. 13.75 Lionel Tiger, Men in Groups (Nelson, 1969; also paperback);
Lionel Tiger and Robin Fox, 'The Zoological Perspective in Social Science', Man n.s. 1 (1966), pp. 74-81; The Imperial Animal (Secker & Warburg, 1972).76 John M. Dunn, Modern Revolutions: An Introduction to the Analysis
of a Political Phenomenon (Cambridge University Press, 1972; also paperback).77 Knipe and Maclay, The Dominant Man, p. 21 (see note 71).78 ibid., p. 29.79 ibid., p. 32.80 Paul Edwards, 'Wilhelm Reich', in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, (Macmillan & Free Press, New York 1967), vol. 7, pp. 104-15,
esp. pp. 109-10. This article is a very clear short account of Reich's ideas. A longer,
though less incisive, account is: Michel Catter, The Life and Work of Wilhelm Reich, trans.
Ghislaine Boulanger (Horizon, New York 1971).81 Reich, The Sexual Revolution, p. xxvi (see note 53).82 For a sympathetic treatment of Reich's later life, see Ilse
Ollendorff Reich, Wilhelm Reich: A Personal Biography (St. Martin's, New York 1969;
also Avon paperback).83 See above, notes 32, 51 and 53; Wilhelm Reich, 'What is Class
Consciousness?' (1933), trans. anon. (Socialist Reproduction pamphlet, 1971). The only
work of Reich's which remains acceptable in orthodox psychoanalytic circles is his Character
Analysis (1933), 3rd edn, trans. Theodore P. Wolfe (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New
York 1949; also Noonday paperback). On Reich's relationship with Freud, see Reich Speaks
of Freud, ed. Mary Higgins and C. M. Raphael (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New York
1967; also Noonday paperback). Reich's essays, written in the period before he emigrated
to the United States, are becoming more readily available. See 'The Sexual Struggle of
Youth' (Socialist Reproduction pamphlet, 1972); Sex-Pol: Essays, 1929-1934, ed. Lee
Baxandall, with an Introduction by Bertell Ollman (Random House, New York 1972; also
Vintage paperback). For related views of psychoanalysis and Marxism, see Erich Fromm, 'The
Method and Function of an Analytic Social Psychology: Notes on Psychoanalysis and
Historical Materialism' (1932), in Fromm, The Crisis of Psychoanalysis: Essays
on Freud, Marx and Social Psychology (Cape, 1971), pp. 135-62. Fromm later became a
socialist humanist, but this early essay is very sharply argued, while chapters 1 and 2,
on the current state of psychoanalytic orthodoxy and on a social view of Freud's model of
man, are illuminating.84 For useful expositions of the ideas of Reich and Marcuse, see Paul
A. Robinson, The Freudian Left: Wilhelm Reich, Geza Roheim, Herbert Marcuse (Harper
paperback, New York 1969), published in Britain as The Sexual Radicals (Temple
Smith, 1970; also paperback). For a political analysis of the implications of Reich's
work, see Maurice Brinton, 'The Irrational in Politics' (Solidarity pamphlet No. 33,
1970). One of the most widely-available short accounts of Marcuse's work is so
bad-tempered and nit-picking as to be worse than useless: Alasdair MacIntyre, Marcuse (Fontana
paperback, 1970).85 Rycroft, Reich, p. 45; Herbert Marcuse, Counter-revolution
and Revolt (Allen Lane The Penguin Press, 1972), p. 130.86 Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilisation: A Philosophical Inquiry
into Freud (1955), with a Political Preface (1966) (Allen Lane, 1969; also
Abacus paperback); Abacus edn, pp. 42, 47-52, 66-7, 158-9 and ch. 6.87 ibid., pp. 31-4, 42.88 Marcuse, One Dimensional Man, pp. 69-76. For a discussion of the history and
political role of popular music which develops a critique of it in terms of repressive
de-sublimation, see R. M. Young, 'A New Nation?', Bath Festival of Blues and Progressive
Music, Programme June 1970, pp. 29-34. The festival was held in the heady atmosphere of
libertarian hopes which were, however briefly, raised by the Woodstock Festival. The
article was reprinted with reflections on the festival as 'The Functions of Rock', in New
Edinburgh Review No. 10 (December 1970), pp. 4-14; cf. Herbert Marcuse, Negations:
Essays in Critical Theory, trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Beacon, Boston 1968; also
paperback), p. 239; Counter-revolution and Revolt, p. 115.89 Herbert Marcuse, 'Repressive Tolerance', in Robert P. Wolff et al, A Critique
of Pure Tolerance (Cape paperback, 1969), pp. 93-137.90 Herbert Marcuse, Five Lectures: Psychoanalysis, Politics and Utopia, trans.
Jeremy J. Shapiro and Shierry M. Weber (Allen Lane The Penguin Press, 1970), p. 44.91 ibid., p. 2.92 ibid., p. 3.93 ibid., p. 47.94 ibid., pp. 62, 63, 65.95 ibid., pp. 71-2, 80-1.96 Herbert Marcuse, An Essay on Liberation (Beacon paperback, Boston 1969), p.
10 n.97 ibid., p. 21; cf pp. 16,17, 51, 63, 88,91. The chapter in which these issues are
mainly discussed is entitled 'A Biological Basis for Socialism?' Marcuse has returned to
this issue in his latest book. See the chapter on 'Nature and Revolution' in Counter-revolution
and Revolt.98 Reich's appeal to both the politically revolutionary and the mystical wings
of the youth movement is based on the intimate mixture of political critique,
half-developed philosophical criticisms of the conceptions of traditional mind-body
dualism, and very complex speculations on a putative 'life energy', the orgone. On his
relevance to psychosomatic medicine, see the Translator's Preface (1941) to Wilhelm Reich, The Function of the Orgasm (1927) 2nd edn, trans. Theodore P. Wolfe (Panther
paperback 1968), pp. 15-24. On the orgone, see Ola Raknes, Wilhelm Reich and Orgonomy (St
Martin's, 1970; also Penguin Books, Baltimore, Maryland).99 Marcuse, Five Lectures, p. 36.100 ibid., p. 5.101 ibid., p. 39.102 ibid., p. 18.103 ibid., p. 4. Related arguments in favour of the revolutionary potential of
modern technology are presented by Roger Garaudy, The Turning Point of Socialism (1969), trans. Peter and Betty Ross (Fontana paperback, 1910), esp. chapter I and pp.
237-8; see also Murray Bookchin, PostScarcity Anarchism (Ramparts paperback,
Berkeley 1971). This point of view ignores the problems of imperialism and the third
world.104 Marcuse, One Dimensional Man, p. 186.105 ibid., p. 187; see also Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interest, p.
312. It is at this point that non-Marxists tend to shrug and walk away, while orthodox
Marxists tend to shout abuse about Hegelian revisionism and idealism. Both reactions could
benefit from an extremely careful reading of Marx, which has been made accessible to the
uninitiated: Bertell Ollman, Alienation: Marx's Conception of Man in Capitalist Society (Cambridge 1971). On the specific issue raised here, see pp. 273 n. 35 and 285 n. 16. On
the same theme, Charles Taylor writes: 'One of the key theses of Marxism is that human
nature changes over history, that human motivation is not perennially the same, but that
with the growth of consciousness, men seek new ends; their grosser needs become refined'.
'Marxism and Empiricism' in British Analytical Philosophy, eds. Bernard Williams
and Alan Monteflore (Routledge, 1966), pp. 227-46, esp. p. 235.106 Marcuse, One Dimensional Man, p. 183.107 I have discussed this episode in the ideological definition of
nature in Young, 'Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and Now', op. cit. (note
32), at pp. 186-8, where references to the relevant literature are given; a more
considered discussion of Lysenkoism will appear in the chapter 'The Ideology of Nature' in
my forthcoming book, Ideology and the Human Sciences (Allen Lane and
Doubleday, New York). The point of the example is that the hegemony of Lysenko's absurd
and highly ideologically determined biological theories in Soviet agriculture produced
catastrophic crop-failures.108 Trent Schroyer, 'The Critical Theory of Late Capitalism', in
Fisher, The Revival of American Socialism: Selected Papers of the Socialist
Scholars Conference, ed. George Fisher (Oxford University Press, New York 1971;
also paperback), pp. 297-321, esp. p. 297.109 Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests, p. 4 (see note 15).110 Schroyer, op. cit., p. 301 (see note 108).111 ibid., p. 300.112 ibid., p. 301.113 ibid., pp. 307-8.114 Reich, 'What is Class Consciousness?', p. 44 (see note 83).It has been pointed out to me that - except for one parenthesis - I
have not connected the argument of this talk with the Women's Liberation movement. The
remark surprised me for two reasons: first, because I had the connection in mind
throughout the composition of the talk and, second, because this awareness is not, in
fact, manifested in the text. On reflection, I suppose that I did not make it explicit
because it has become clear to me in various ways that at the present time - and for
perfectly understandable reasons - most women's liberationists are struggling against,
rather than in solidarity with, men. A contribution from a man on this theme would
therefore be considered male chauvinist, presumptuous and unwelcome. A second issue is
that until very recently the Women's Liberation movement has concentrated on consciousness
- raising in small groups and has made this approach a priority over relating its
struggles to theoretical critiques. Lately, however, efforts have been made to integrate
these and other activities with a more general marxist critique, although I have also
heard these writers referred to dismissively as 'the theoretical heavies'.It seems to me that there is a very large gap between the writings of
Marx and Engels on the one hand and the existing Women's Lib literature on the other. (An
exception is Frederick Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and
the State in the Light of the Researches of Lewis H. Morgan, written 1884; 4th
edn, 1891, trans. anon., International, New York 1942; also paperback, especially ch. 2,
sect. 3.) Similarly, biological arguments have played - and continue to play - an
important part in reactionary responses to attempts on the part of women and men to
transcend their mutual oppression. I believe that the demystification of the search for
the limits of human nature can make a contribution to the demystification of male, female
and familial roles and that the arguments of Reich and Marcuse go a long way towards
filling the gap mentioned above.On the relationship between the modern family and the rise of
industrial capitalism, see Philippe Ariès, Centuries of Childhood.. A Social History
of Family Life, trans. Robert Baldick (Cape, 1962; also Vintage paperback, New York).
For a general discussion of the relationship between sexuality and Marxism, see Reimut
Reiche, Sexuality and Class Struggle, trans. Susan Bennett and David
Fernbach (New Left Books, 1970). Reiche's argument is based on a Marcusan interpretation
of psychoanalysis and also draws on a number of Wilhelm Reich's conceptions. His
discussions of current issues and practices of New Left libertarians and of 'late
capitalist sexual practices' are excellent, particularly his critique of facile and
mechanistic attempts to overcome repressive de-sublimation (chs. 5-7).The literature which I have seen from the Women's Liberation movement
does not seem to have drawn significantly on the writings of Reich and Marcuse. In her
chapter 'Freudianism: the Misguided Feminism' in The Dialectic of Sex (Cape, 1971;
also Paladin paperback), Shulamith Firestone praises Reich in passing and mentions
Marcuse's concept of repressive de-sublimation but sees psychoanalysis as competing with
and suppressing feminism. In her chapters 'The Ideology of the Family' and 'Psychoanalysis
and the Family' in Woman's Estate (Pelican Books, Harmondsworth 1971), Juliet
Mitchell mentions Marcuse and dismisses Reich in an aside which implies a valid criticism
of his later writings but not those of the 1930s. She also argues that psychoanalysis - at
least potentially - offers much to the cause of women's liberation. She puts the point of
my argument very neatly: 'Reactionary ideology always returns us to our biological fate' (p. 171).Kate Millett's Sexual Politics (Rupert Hart-Davis, 1971; also
Abacus paperback) ofrers a well-argued critique of Freud's work and the reactionary role
of orthodox psychoanalysis. She is especially incisive about the mixture of biological and
social (i.e. conventional) categories under the guise of biology (Abacus edn, pp. 157-233,
esp. pp. 180, 187, 190 fr.). However, her use of the ideas of Reich and Marcuse is
limited. She draws on Reich primarily for insights into the role of sexual repression in
supporting the authoritarianism of German fascism and also uses him as a stick with which
to beat Norman Mailer. Marcuse is mentioned in passing as one who, like Reich and
Horkheimer, stressed the links between patriarchialism and authoritarian governments.The Women's Liberation literature on domination and deference fits perfectly with the
arguments of Reich and Marcuse given above. Perhaps it is not too soon to suggest that
women and men can begin to work together on both the theoretical front and that of praxis,
although the rising movement of radical feminism indicates that this suggestion may still
be premature. For an introduction to the Women's Liberation literature, see Sisterhood
is Powerful: An Anthology of Writings from the Women's Liberation Movement, ed.
Robin Morgan (Vintage paperback, New York 1970) - which concentrates on the American
movement and includes a large bibliography; Michelene Wandor (compiler), The Body Politic:
Writings from the Women's Liberation Movement in Britain, 1969-1972(Stagelpaperback,
1972). For a comprehensive bibliography on the relationship between feminism and
revolutionary politics, see Sheila Rowbotham, 'Women's Liberation and Revolution: A
Bibliography' (Falling Wall Press, 1972, 79 Richmond Rd, Montpelier, Bristol, B56 5EP).
Intellectual production and reproduction are social processes, although
individual 'authorship' masks this. In very different ways - and in some cases very
indirectly and even unwittingly - the following people contributed to the conception and
production of this essay. I want to thank them and to implicate them in the result:
Jonathan Treasure, John Fekete, Derek Newton, George Gross, Rudi Dutschke, Jeremy Mulford,
Sheila Young, Margot Waddell, Anne Venge, Jonathan Rosenhead, Patrick Bateson, Maureen
Fallside, Jeremy Lewis, Jonathan Benthall, Martin Richards, Stephen Guyon, Tamsin
Braidwood, Diana Guyon, Heather Glen, Raymond Williams, Pat Reay, Rita van der Straeten.
|
|