Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
GOOD AND EVIL, CHARACTER AND MORALITY
by Robert M. Young
As I sat down to begin composing this lecture, I came across the
following statement in a posting to an internet discussion group on the practice of
psychotherapy: I strongly believe that the goal of any therapy is to work toward
responsible accountable behavior, even if that includes acceptance of powerlessness, and
then movement to accountable responsible behavior. If I understand this statement
correctly, it implies that moral accountability is a goal of psychotherapy, and it points
to a desirable trajectory from amorality or immorality or diminished responsibility toward
the realm of morality. You might think it eccentric or trendy of me to begin with quotes
from the internet, but I can assure you that important work is going on in cyberspace, no
matter how hyped it is in the mass media. When I last looked there were over 8000 people
taking part in nearly forty email forums in a consortium called Inter-Psych (founded,
incidentally by a mature student at Sheffield University), including psychoanalysis,
psychotherapy, psychiatry, psychiatric social work. Outside that consortium there are a
number of forums on counselling and other aspects of the helping professions. (I have just
worked my way through a list from one of the three main software formats of over 8000
email forums, including any topic you can think of, e.g., all sorts of disability, any
philosopher, any social or political or medical issue). Anyone wanting help about how to
get on-line and join in these global debates, please let me have your name and address,
and Ill send out a simple guide.
My point in bringing up the internet is that discussions about the
origins and psychology of evil and aggression and debates about morality in our field are
occurring all the time on the forums I mentioned, as well as others on the psychological
study of the arts and the philosophy of literature to which I subscribe. People are
shaken, sobered, shocked, searching. I have in mind the behaviour of young people, sexual
abuse, gangs, drugs, drive-by killings, riots, ethnic cleansing, genocide, proliferating
Mafias, yardies, Armageddon cults, the Bulger case, civil wars, murder of street urchins
and fatal neglect of babies. I was a child during World War Two and have vivid memories of
what it involved and what was revealed in its wake, yet I cannot remember such a morally
uncertain time as the present.
I chose the words in my title because they are, for the most part,
unfashionable in professional and medical and helping profession circles. Indeed, they are
unfashionable even embarrassing in all professional circles, except, perhaps
the professional circles of theologians, priests, ethics scholars and certain cultists.
Even so, I think they are important and that they are on our minds all the time. I want to
try to close the gap between what we do and those concepts. I am not here to argue
abstruse moral theory. Quite the reverse. I want to claim that we think in terms of good
and evil, character and morality all the time and want to suggest that we do so rather
less coyly.
I collect cartoons about psychotherapy and send them to Nina Coltart;
its a sort of affair, which recently gave birth to a collection of her essays. One
of my favourites shows the therapist leaning forward, over the top of the couch, so that
his face is directly over that of the patient. The caption reads, You swine!
We laugh because this is so utterly taboo. Patients laugh because it portrays a recurrent
fear. Therapist laugh because they want to do exactly this from time to time at
least I do.
But this is not my preferred entry point. That is the concept of the
perverse, one I want to distinguish, at least for the moment, from perversion, a more
problematic concept of which I have elsewhere asked if it is obsolete. The perverse,
however, is decidedly not so. Perverse thought involves precisely the inversion of the
moral order: fair is foul and foul is fair. The patient hates the good and pursues evil
with great gusto. Think of Richard III, Macbeth, people who torture and kill old people. I
have in mind a paper my Margot Waddell and Gianna Williams in which they describe a young
boy who is already deeply and they fear, irretrievably committed to perverse
thought. Herbert Rosenfeld has described destructive narcissism in similar terms. The
patient is in the thrall of a gang in the mind, subservient to a Mafia leader
who keeps the patient from co-operating with the authorities in the person of the
therapist. Betty Joseph describes people addicted to near death who only appear to take
part in the analytic process and are perversely chuntering and keeping change at bay.
I cite these clinical phenomena to make my point straightaway. We are
deeply into questions of good and evil. Our patients are persecuted by primitive guilt
feelings. They aspire to the good (we infer this from the fact that they keep coming) but
cannot allow themselves to develop anything like their full potentials, sometimes because
of terribly low self-esteem, sometimes because of fear of Oedipal triumph. They may long
for wholesome relations with another but find themselves caught up in a shameful,
primitive, even retaliatory part-object relationship involving cruelty and revenge. I have
a patient who hid behind a painful phimosis until he was in his mid-thirties. After
circumcision, when he could make love, he found he could only have an orgasm as a result
of spanking. Not playful, mind you: the sort of spank where you see the mark the next time
you meet the person. It took him more than a year to tell me about this and about the
prostitutes he visited. It took lots of work about his humiliating mother and aunt and his
castrated father before he could have penetrative sex and a lot more before he could love
his partner, who, in the meantime lost patience and withdrew from the relationship. I have
another patient in a position of moral trust who indulges in mutual masturbation with an
inappropriate and not fully consenting person. This patient is also put off and threatened
by penetrative sex. He would be the first to say that what he does is wrong. He manages it
by plying his partner with drink and having lots himself. He gives up the mutual
masturbation from time to time, but it was years before he acknowledged to me that this
weekly activity had been going on for more than a decade with a person whose father had
entrusted the partner to his care. He has not managed to achieve his goal of becoming
potent with a woman and having penetrative sex.
Both of these patients feel immoral, and I agree with them. They
brought the moral framework with them. My job was not to preach amorality. It was to get
behind the paralysing and unproductive guilt to understanding. However, while doing so I
never hinted that what they were doing was not wrong.
I went to a conference a couple of weeks ago and heard a paper on
breaches of confidentiality in the history of psychoanalysis. My own position on this
matter has always been that confidentiality is absolute, except for supervision. I
wont even respond to a letter from a training organisation except to tell them that
I do not answer such letters and that they should put no interpretation on this fact. One
of the commentators at the conference was a person who specialises in working with child
sexual abusers, that is, children who sexually abuse other children. She was perfectly
straightforward in saying that confidentiality is not always maintained in her work. More
than that, she argued persuasively that her patients are relieved to have boundaries
imposed where they had been weak in the family and in their inner worlds. Of course, she
doesnt ring the police on day one, but she does make it clear that if the child does
not stop the abuse and tell the relevant people, she will, in due course, do so. She takes
the same position about adult abusers. I found this implausible and asked if the therapy
was thereby made impossible. Not at all, she replied. It was enhanced. The patients knew
perfectly well that what they were doing was wrong, even evil.
How can we hold in our minds the moral and the clinical? I am
suggesting that one way is to see that they are not at odds. What are our goals? I can
recall two which I bear in mind during my work: to work and to love (from Freud) and
getting the patient to take back the projections (from Bollas). Another,
specifically Kleinian formulation, is to help the patient to dwell less in a frame of mind
that is persecutory, full of part-object relations and more in a position where there are
whole object relations, concern for the object, depressive rather than persecutory guilt
and efforts are made at reparation. I cannot see these as other than moral goals.
Our failures to approach them can be put in strictly moralistic
language as commandments or sins. Indeed, if we look at the seven deadly sins, they
can easily be recognised as symptoms: avarice, gluttony, pride, lust, anger, sloth and
envy. Each of those sins is easily expressed in clinical terms and seen as a symptom.
Indeed, Melanie Klein wrote a short book in which envy is paired with the constructive
emotion of gratitude. Klein says, There are very pertinent psychological reasons why
envy ranks among the seven "deadly sins". I would even suggest that it is felt
to be the greatest sin of all, because it spoils and harms the good object which is the
source of life. This view is consistent with the view described by Chaucer in The
Parsons Tale: "It is certain that envy is the worst sin that is; for all
other sins are sins only against one virtue, whereas envy is against all virtue and
against all goodness." The feeling of having injured and destroyed the primal object
impairs the individuals trust in the sincerity of his later relations and makes him
doubt his capacity for love and goodness. (Klein, 1957, p. 189). If we look at the ten
commandments and the beatitudes, we are also not far from symptoms: lying, covetousness,
murder, theft, adultery, and the positive injunctions to honour parents and God and keep
the Sabbath. Each has its psychopathological equivalent. The meek, the poor, the pure in
spirit, the peacemakers can be seen as people who dwell in the depressive position and do
not live by splits and persecutions.
Dont misunderstand me. I am not trying to psychoanalyse morality
or moralise psychoanalysis. I am merely pointing out that if we do not steep ourselves in
the scientistic language of some forms of metapsychology so much that we only refer to
structures, energies, cathexes and topographies, we are using moral concepts in our daily
clinical work, and we are certainly working with people whose distress involves guilt and
self-inhibition. As the conference rubric puts it, Our work is often with people who
are struggling with these themes as metaphors for their internal world. The failures
in relating which we seek to heal, the injunction not to treat fellow human beings as
objects or mere means to our own ends these strike me as goals which are at once
therapeutic and moral.
I want to take us to the heart of this matter developmentally. There is
a passage in a paper by Melanie Klein, presented in 1946, which purports to identify the
prototype for all aggressive object relations. If I understand this claim aright, she
believes that she has found the basis of all destructiveness, the elemental expression of
the death instinct. Before quoting it, I should say quite straightforwardly that neither
Freud nor Klein (nor, for that matter, Karl Menninger, the author of Man against
Himself, (1938), a classic on this topic) believed in innocence. All believed
that destructiveness was inherent in human nature. On this account, there is no innocence
to be lost. Instead, we are initially given to destructiveness, and our task is to become
civilised and to remain so as much as we can.
Klein concludes seven pages on the fine texture of early paranoid and
schizoid mechanisms as follows: 'So far, in dealing with persecutory fear, I have singled
out the oral element. However, while the oral libido still has the lead, libidinal and
aggressive impulses and phantasies from other sources come to the fore and lead to a
confluence or oral, urethral and anal desires, both libidinal and aggressive. Also the
attacks on the mother's breast develop into attacks of a similar nature on her body, which
comes to be felt as it were as an extension of the breast, even before the mother is
conceived of as a complete person. The phantasied onslaughts on the mother follow two main
lines: one is the predominantly oral impulse to suck dry, bite up, scoop out and rob the
mother's body of its good contents... The other line of attack derives from the anal and
urethral impulses and implies expelling dangerous substances (excrements) out of the self
and into the mother. Together with these harmful excrements, expelled in hatred, split-off
parts of the ego are also projected onto the mother or, as I would rather call it, into the mother. These excrements and bad parts of the self are meant not only to injure but
also to control and to take possession of the object. In so far as the mother comes to
contain the bad parts of the self, she is not felt to be a separate individual but is felt
to be the bad self.
'Much of the hatred against parts of the self is now directed towards
the mother. This leads to a particular form of identification which establishes the
prototype of an aggressive object-relation' (Klein, 1946, pp. 7-8). I want to note again
that we have here the model the template, the fundamental experience
of all of the aggressive features of human relations. Six years later Klein
adds the following sentence: 'I suggest for these processes the term "projective
identification"' (ibid.).
She goes on to say that if the infant's impulse is to harm, the mother
is experienced as persecuting, and that in psychotic disorders the identification of the
object with hated parts of the self 'contributes to the intensity of the hatred directed
against other people', that this process weakens the ego, that good parts are also
projected and that 'The processes of splitting off parts of the self and projecting them
into objects are thus of vital importance for normal development as well as for normal
object-relations' (pp. 8-9). In the course of all this, Klein makes it quite clear that
the very same processes involve 'anxieties characteristic of psychosis' (p. 2).
I am relating these matters in the way that I am in order to make it
apparent that the very same mechanisms are at work in a wide range of internal processes.
Moreover, the same mechanism is at work in both benign and malignant forms of projective
identification. In its benign form it is the basis of all communication, internally, with
the external world and with others. In its malignant form it underlies hatred,
murderousness, racism, virulent nationalism. I have made a careful study of the literature
on projective identification and am satisfied that this frustrating conclusion that
the same mechanism is involved in all communication as well as in good and evil object
relations is valid and supported by that literature. I concur with the following
summary by Torras de Beà. After reviewing the development of the concept, he writes,
'These authors consider that projective identification is the basic mechanism of empathy
and primitive communication and also of the defence mechanism which consists of
dissociating and projecting anxiety in order to be rid of it. I agree with this and think
also that what we call projective identification is the active element in every
communication from empathy to the most pathological and defensive' (Torras de Beà, 1989,
p. 266). He concludes that it is 'the mechanism basic to all human interaction' (p. 272).
So, when we ask what it is that we have to give up in order to know, I
suggest that we have to give up extremism. Put another way, in order not to give way to
evil and immoral impulses, we have to learn to sublimate our aggressive impulses and to
keep the unsublimated ones in a temperate band. This was, of course, Freuds basic
argument in the essays where he ruminated on the basic elements of human nature, e.g., Totem
and Taboo, Beyond the Pleasure Principle and Civilization and Its Discontents. He
saw our basic nature as riven with constructive and destructive impulses and claimed that
life is lived in the space between two basic instincts, of Eros or life and Thanatos or
death. In order to be civilised we have to learn to sublimate our greedy and rapacious
impulses, This is brought about by guilt, which keeps us within the system of norms, of
which the taboo against incest was the first and remains the most fundamental. The
struggle to maintain the veneer of civilisation is perpetual, and the price we pay for it
is the inevitability of discontent or neurosis. What we have to give up in order to know,
to put it differently yet again, is omnipotence and unrestrained self-indulgence.
I want to turn now to the topic of character, and I want to do so in
the context of our work with students. I say our in a straightforward way. I
do not currently teach undergraduates, but I do teach and supervise graduate students and
trainee psychotherapists. I have also had one or more child in the British educational
system for more than thirty years. More specifically, I was a college tutor for a long
time and wrote the document which led to the establishment of the Cambridge University
Counselling Service, where my wife worked for a number of years. I currently supervise
university counsellors. I say this to support my use of our work with
students.
It is my firm impression that current young people suffer from a
relative lack of the kinds of boundaries and moral frameworks which were taken for granted
when I was an undergraduate at Yale in the 1950s and when I was a Cambridge don in the
1960s and 70s. Such generalisations are notoriously suspect, and I accept that I run the
risk of striking you as a fuddy duddy. I dont mind if I do. The late lamented
historian and cultural critic, Christopher Lasch, once said that current youth suffer from
lack of project. Since three of my children are professionals working in areas
I admire screen writing, the bar and medicine you could say I am being too
fastidious., but I feel it all the same. I feel it with respect to the impact of the
relativism of postmodernism and the careerism of many young people. I often find students
wanting to know more about what is required than what is interesting, not reading around
their work. I do not need to be told that this is significantly related to cuts and rising
fees, for example, recent rises here. I am not saying that these young people have
inherently inferior moral fibre. What I am saying is that character suffers in times such
as ours.
Let me say what I mean by character, a term which is not used in the
lay sense in psychoanalysis. I shall approach the topic historically, partly because I am
an historian of psychology and partly because it will help me to make my point about our
need for a concept of character. Character was central to the psychology of the individual
until well into the twentieth century. Baldwins authoritative Dictionary of
Philosophy and Psychology said, Individual psychology is the science of
character (Baldwin, 1901, vol. 1, p. 173). The systematic study of individuals was a
discipline set apart from the mainstream of psychology in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries, which was intellectualist in its concerns, and was borne first by physiognomy
and then phrenology, whose greatest exponents were, respectively, J. C. Lavater (1775-78)
and F. J. Gall (1910-19. 1822-25; see Young, 1972, 1979a, 1990, ch. 1). These were
profoundly democratising traditions, claiming that character was apparent on the surface
of the visage, which, the phrenologists believed, reflected the size and importance of the
underlying brain structures. When Britains most eminent pre-evolutionary
psychologist, Alexander Bain, had finished publishing his major works in the prevailing
mode, he wrote a separate book, On the Study of Character, including an Estimate of
Phrenology (1861). It is said that the phrenological approach to understanding and
cultivating character was so popular that the households of self-improving artisans in
nineteenth-century Britain were likely to have three books: The Bible, Pilgrims
Progress and George Combes phrenological primer The Constitution of Man (1827).
However, as the turn of the century approached, the climate was so
changed away from characterology and toward personality that William
James masterpiece, The Principles of Psychology, did not include the topic
(1890). When, in 1927, A. A. Roback produced a comprehensive, magisterial tome, The
Psychology of Character, subtitled with a Survey of Personality in General, (which went through three editions, was still in print in the mid-1960s and was
accompanied by a book-length separate volume of references), character was
losing even more ground to personality as the prevailing concept for the
understanding of individuality. The terms Character and Personality (as in the
title of William McDougalls study of 1933; see Hearnshaw, 1964, p. 189) coexisted
for a time, but most surveys of the scope of psychology published during the period
1930-1950 gave little place to character, which increasingly found its main
expression, not in works in academic psychology but in searching biographies, of which
four classics of the genre (chosen because strong on character assessment) come to
mind: Ralph Barton Perrys The Thought and Character of William James (1935),
Carl Sandbergs six-volume Abraham Lincoln, (1926-39), Robert
Caros three-volume The Years of Lyndon Johnson (1983, 1990, vol. 3 in
preparation) and L. S. Hearnshaws Cyril Burt. (1979). The recent and
growing use of more or less sophisticated versions of psychoanalysis in the genre of psychobiography brings us full circle, since psychoanalysis is used as a tool in the
assessment of character, while the concept has little place in psychoanalysis itself. (In
separate essays I have put forward the claims of biography to be the basic discipline for
a human science, made a case study of Darwins biographers and have summarised the
strengths and weaknesses of psychobiography Young, 1987,1988, 1994c).
Character has disappeared entirely from the classificatory
scheme of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM III-R,
1987), the bible of orthodox psychiatric diagnosis. If you look carefully, you can find
the old character disorders alcoholism, drug addiction, sexual deviancy
and psychopathy (Magaro and Ashbrook, 1984) reclassified in sanitised form.
Alcoholism and drug addiction reappear as disorders in their own right, and the others
turn up as sexual, factitious, impulse control,
adjustment and personality disorders. Nor can the concept of
character be found in the widely-used UCH Textbook of Psychiatry (Wolff et al., 1990), though, once again, you can find personality disorders and disorders of impulse
control aplenty. The term character does make a number of appearances in
the psychoanalytic vocabulary, but in none of them is it unmodified. We find
character armour, character disorder, character
neurosis, character types (both Jungian and Eysenck), but nowhere is
character unadorned.
Laplanche and Pontalis go on and on about confusion, the
multiplicity of possible meanings and lack of rigour (1983, p. 67) with
respect to character neurosis. Their first definition refers to any clinical picture
which does not at first sight exhibit symptoms but merely modes of behaviour leading to
recurrent or permanent difficulty in the patients relation to his environment
(ibid.). They go on to a psychoanalytically oriented characterology which
correlates different character types either with the major psychoneurotic conditions
(speaking of obsessional, phobic, paranoiac characters and so on) or else with the various
stages of libidinal development (which are said to correspond to oral, anal, urethral
phallic-narcissistic and genital character types sometimes reclassified in terms of
the major opposition between genital and pre-genital characters). According to this
approach it is legitimate to speak of character neurosis when referring to any apparently
asymptomatic neurosis where it is the type of character which betrays a pathogenic
organisation (ibid.).
They next describe a character formation which involves a once-for-all
defensive structure adopted to preserve the patient against symptoms and against
instinctual threats. Sublimation, reaction formation and rationalisation predominate in
this syndrome. A fourth conception of character neurosis places anomalies of character
somewhere between neurotic symptoms and psychotic disorders (pp. 67-8). (It occurs to me
that this is one way of thinking about John Steiners concept of pathological
organisation of psychic retreat, stuck between the paranoid schizoid and depressive
positions.)
I find all these conceptions of interest, as I do Wilhelm Reichs
notion of character armour and the broader idea of character as defence
developed in his Character Analysis (1933) and his The Mass Psychology of
Fascism, that the character structure is the congealed sociological process
of a given epoch. He adds that A societys ideologies can become a material
force only on condition that they change the character structures of the people
(Reich, 1933a, p. xxvi). Frankly, however, none of these is what I am really after in my
present enquiry. Horace and Eva English take us to the concept I seek in their Dictionary
of Psychological and Psychoanalytic Terms (1958). First, they describe character as
that which makes a person different from someone else; then they take all such marks
collectively all the mental or behavioural traits of a person, the sum total of
their psychological traits. They point out that this was formerly the meaning of
character in English, as it still is in French and German. In English,
however, it has for the most part been replaced by the term which, as we have seen, has
become ubiquitous in the clinical realm: personality. You could say, then,
that personality is the concept in scientific psychology which has replaced character for
describing what is unique about a person.
I will not settle for this, and Ill bet you wont either. It
only takes a moment to see why. Try this: She has "personality". versus She has "character". She has a good personality. versus She has a good character. Not the same things at all, are they?
Whats the difference? English and English are perfectly clear about this. Their next
definition says just what I hoped it would: an integrated system of traits or
behavior tendencies that enables one to react, despite obstacles, in a relatively
consistent way in relation to mores and moral issues... It is distinguished from
personality by its emphasis upon (a) the volitional aspect, and (b) morality
(English & English, 1958, p. 83).
So, character is about being a moral person and involves volition or
intentions. An immoral person has a bad character. An unreliable person has a weak
character. Being of good character has a connotation of admirable steadfastness: Gary
Cooper in High Noon. He wants to run, and everyone says its okay if he
does. He might lose his new bride, who was Grace Kelly, after all. if he stays. But he has
to stay and face the man who, according to the theme song of the film, made a vow
while in state prison and said hed trade his life for hisn.
Its the lawmans duty, even though he had just handed in his badge. The new man
isnt arriving until tomorrow, and Coop has the character to stand firm, even though
hes scared and wants to go off and start his new life. This is the stuff of heroism.
It isnt just about physical strength and violence. Mother Teresa has character. The
good Samaritan had character. Ordinary people who behave well in ordinary situations and
at lifes extremes have character. Its not just ego strength; it cannot be
captured in a scientific or scientistic language, because its essence is moral
behaving well against the odds.
I think psychoanalysis has interesting things to say about character
but that its essence slips through the net, rather as Freud said that love slips through
its net. I think the things psychoanalysis says make it harder to be of good character,
since it takes us to the inner meaning of things. In legal parlance you can be of
good character if you pay your bills, dont get arrested and dont have
any County Court judgements against you. But in psychoanalytic terms, if your apparently
good self is the result of a violent split so that you are trading in idealisations, the
other side of the split will out. This was obvious in the case of the television preachers
in the US, many of whom turned out to be crooks and whore mongers. It is less obvious in
the case of some goody-goodies who get to be head girls and head boys in schools and
psychoanalytic training institutions, but it is axiomatic that it is there
somewhere in that persons phantasies and relationships. It is interesting to
speculate where the other side of Mother Teresas split manifests itself. It is said
that she only allows lepers to kiss her.
I am arguing that one of the reasons people come to us is that their
characters are not sufficiently strong to meet the compromises of the times, and they are
tempted by careerism, cynicism, opportunism, treating others as means, not ends. I am an
historian of ideas, among them what was known as the debate on mans place in
nature in nineteenth-century Britain, the furore about Darwinism, and I have spent a
lot of my life studying Victorian lives and letters and controversies. I also spent, as I
have said, a long time in Cambridge. I mention these facts to reassure you that I know
perfectly well that being attracted to careerism, opportunism and sleaze are not new
temptations in recent years. However, it is my firm belief that admirable alternatives to
these trajectories are not as apparently accessible and attractive to young people or to
any of us, for that matter, as they were even a decade ago. The squeeze on resources and
jobs and the rise of cynical, relativist, despairing and whimsical cultural theory have as
an obvious concomitant, a squeeze on moral space, and many people come to our consulting
rooms with less well laid foundations for their adult characters than they would be likely
to have done in earlier times.
I think this has two consequences, one very abstract, the other very
concrete. The abstract one is to make it an urgent desideratum in philosophy and cultural
theory to re-examine the fundamental split between fact and value and concomitant splits
between science and morality, mechanism and purpose and other parallel ones which are
fundamental to the modern world view. They became prominent in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries during the scientific revolution, and the Protestant and capitalist
revolutions interdigitated with it to give us new definitions of nature, human nature, the
individual and the relationship of the individual to values and morality. In all of these
movements value was sequestered sequestered from scientific explanation, from the
labour process in manufacturing and was driven deep inside the individuals
inner world. It could be that psychiatry, psychotherapy and psychoanalysis are the final
repositories of this sequestration, a thesis argued by Michel Foucault as the final
conclusion of his book, Madness and Civilisation: that the final frontier in the
trajectory from chains to moral treatment is that we must take responsibility for our
unconscious motivations.
I do not wish to shy away from that responsibility. However, being
clear that we and our patients should bear it is impeded by a number of attitudes which
are heir to the triple revolution in science, the mode of production and possessive
individualism which brought in the modern era. One is the neutrality of science. We are
now learning that science is not neutral: it is the embodiment of values in
theories, therapies and things, in facts and artefacts. Scientists and technologists
pursue agendas, they have philosophies of nature, world views. All facts are theory-laden;
all theories are value-laden; all values exist within an ideology or world view. New
developments in medicine, genetic engineering, information technology and threats to the
environment are making it a matter of extreme urgency that we reintegrate values and
science or, more accurately, make explicit the values which have been sequestered in
scientific explanation.
This topic is not only out there in the wider environment, external to
the consulting room. It affects how we see ourselves in our professional roles. One of the
manifestations of scientism was the ideology of professionalism, which claimed that
professionals were, in their ways, like scientists, above the battle of political and
economic and ideological forces. It is not so, and this takes me from the very abstract
consequence I have been outlining to the very concrete one with which I shall conclude. We
are in the thick of it. Of course, we have our forms of tolerance, forbearance and
abstinence, but the whole point of my paper today has been to say that these aspects of
the analytic frame are there in order to facilitate our being of service to our patients
and clients in the struggle to behave morally and to build character, to have strong
enough internal objects so that people can behave well in spite of the forces which are at
work leading us to treat the relations between people as though they were relations
between things. The helping professions exist to fight reification, of which envy and
virulent projective identification are prime examples. To revert to the rubruc of
todays conference, what we have to give up in order to know is the false
consciousness of professionalism: we are moral, political and ideological practitioners,
and we have to take responsibility for being implicated in the struggles in the world,
represented in the institutions and cultures in the minds of our patients and
clients. The analytic frame provides a relatively safe space to go into the intimate
aspects of these matters, but it does not make us free from the vicissitudes of being
morally implicated. That makes our clinical task of containment and detoxification even
more challenging and urgent.
This is the text of a paper presented to the annual conference of the
Oxford University Counselling Service 23 June 1995, on the topic: The Loss of
Innocence: What Do you Lose in Order to Learn?.
Addres for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Rd., London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
© The Author
|
|