MERITOCRACY: A CRITIQUE
Essay review of The Big Test: The Secret History of the
American Meritocracy by Nicholas Lemann. New York: Farar, Straus and Giroux,
1999. Pp. Vii+406 Hb $27 Pb $15
by Robert M. Young
The Rise of the Meritocracy:1870-2033: An Essay on
Education and Equality (1958) is a very well-known yet widely unread book. I
bought a copy of the Penguin edition in 1974, and it remains unopened. We all
know that it advocates a society in which advancement is based on merit, and
Tony Blair has recently said that he wants Britain to be a meritocracy.
Actually, that’s the opposite of what the book said. It is not about an
ultimately fair society; it is about a dystopia, as the author, Michael Young
(Lord Young of Dartington, main author of the Labour Party’s first post-war
manifesto, begetter of the Open University, of Which and of much else) has
recently stressed in an article in The Guardian.
I learned that I carried about this very widely-believed
wrong assumption about the original meaning of meritocracy from a remarkable
book by a very thoughtful author, Nicholas Lemann, whose essays I first
encountered in the 1970s when he was writing for the Texas Monthly , where I
read an essay which in many ways points the way toward the book under review,
‘Sherwood Blount’s First Million’, about how a working class boy becomes a
football star and a successful real estate broker by virtue of being a good ole
boy. (It is reprinted in a collection of his essays, The Fast Track: Texans and
Other Strivers). Lemann went on to become a staff writer for The Atlantic and,
more recently, The New Yorker. He is also the author of The Promised Land, a
moving book on the migration of blacks from the American South when the
mechanical cotton picker eliminated their livelihoods. I have felt for a long
time that if something has been written by Nicholas Lemann, I will almost
certainly benefit from reading it.
The book in question is The Big Test: The Secret History of
the American Meritocracy. You may respond to this title with scepticism, but I
think it is appropriate. In particular, it is a history of the Educational
Testing Service (ETS) at Princeton, New Jersey, the people who originated and
administer the College Board Exams, the Graduate Record Test, the Medical School
Aptitude Test (all of which I have taken), as well as many other tests of
aptitude and achievement which play central roles in the gateways to various
American educational institutions, the military and many other settings. This
story is intrinsically interesting, but it is particularly so now, since there
are forces at work seeking to bring these tests to Britain as part of a reform
of university admissions at our own elite universities in the wake of a very
talented woman’s being turned down by and Oxford college and going to Harvard.
The book is, I suggest, a cautionary tale for us.
At the centre of Lemann’s story is the idealism of James
Bryant Conant, who, on becoming President of Harvard in 1933, encouraged one of
his deans, Henry Chauncey, to embark on an ambitious programme of educational
testing. Chauncey is the central figure in the ETS story. Conant and Chauncey
had a vision, admirable in its essence, that the future of American democracy
crucially depended on opening up its elite educational institutions to a much
wider constituency of talented people than the scions of the rich who gained
most of the places in Ivy League (Yale, Harvard, Princeton, etc.) and similar
colleges and universities. They embarked on a huge project of social engineering
– find talented young people and open the best institutions to them. Their aim
was to create, as Lemann puts it, ‘a scientized social utopia’ by applying a
‘standard gauge’ to people (p.58).
I, like many others, was a beneficiary of this approach. I
was plucked from relative obscurity of a state school in the suburbs of Dallas
which had never sent anyone to Yale and given a full scholarship. We found
ourselves mixes with graduates of the great private secondary schools – called
‘prep (for preparatory) schools’ in America, e.g., Groton, Exeter, Andover,
Lawrenceville, Deerfield in New England, along with some less well-known private
schools dotted around the country. Their graduates were certainly better
prepared than we, and some of us had to attend remedial courses and to work like
stink to keep up. Soon, however, we found ourselves on the Dean’s List of the
top ten percent and even the Dean’s Honors List of the top ten people in
academic results in a given year. What we lacked in urbanity we made up for with
industry. In my second year my roommate (from a Los Angeles state school) and I
had an arrangement whereby one of us was always awake and rolled out the other
after four hours of sleep. We had a lot less money than the preppies, and we
certainly appreciated the opportunity we had been given. Both of us went on to
medical school. He practiced pathology in St. Louis, and I went to Cambridge and
trained as an historian of science and taught there for over a decade, was an
admissions tutor at one of the ancient colleges, King’s, and eventually became a
psychotherapist and university professor. I suppose the social engineers would
say that we were successful products of the strategy to ferret out talent from
new places. I relate the personal side of this, partly to convey some of the
fruits of the new educational policy, partly to make clear why I should find the
book so interesting.
Yet it is much more than a history of an educational strategy
and a social experiment. The story the author tells centres on the lives and
careers of a few individuals who exemplify the themes he is exploring. One is
about race and positive discrimination. The story he tells about this theme is
complex and murky, and the outcome is by no means unequivocally progressive. It
takes us a long way from the elite universities to the great state university
systems, in particular, that of California, which had both educational
opportunity for all and a policy of fostering certain very privileged
institutions for the brightest students. Many conundrums and contradictions
occurred as a result of the social engineering embarked upon by the leader of
the California university system Clark Kerr. Admirable social goals, for
example, positive discrimination and rewarding educational achievements) came
into sharp and prolonged conflict. The Ivy League schools on the East coast had
their own contradictions. Fostering people like me and my roommate meant having
quotas limiting how many Jews from New England could be admitted, no matter what
their educational attainments. Much of the book is concerned with legal and
policy issues surrounding positive discrimination in university education and
employment.
The largest issue considered by Lemann, however, is a
tremendously serious one which is hard to fathom. ‘Merit’ meant ‘ability’, and
the ETS set out to measure it by putatively value-free tests. The most important
of these is the College Boards, and the ETS social engineers made every effort
to make the tests measure ability independent of knowledge. They were attempting
to construct a meritocracy, even though they were blissfully ignorant of why
Michael Young opposed this. His reason was that if you measure and reward
talent/ability/merit independent of values, goals, beliefs, character, politics
and all that determines how we deploy our gifts, you will generate a group of
mandarins who are not particularly interested in how their talents are made use
of. They want ‘success’, money, status and are not likely to be particularly
worried where they get it. I read a book recently which claimed that 80% of one
year’s graduating class from Yale in the 1980s applied to work for the
investment bankers, Lemann Brothers, the subject of the satirical and cynical
book, Liar’s Poker, by Michael Lewis, which probed the amoral world of selling
securities, gaining big bonuses and striving for the biggest accolade of all,
being called ‘a big swinging dick’. A mandarinate without moral rudders is
reminiscent of the people who did as they were told in dictatorial regimes and
other who just did not make waves and endanger their positions in questionable
companies and other institutions. My experience is that the places where I have
worked in television, publishing, academia and the helping professions are full
of such rudderless careerists.
Another sobering theme in Lemann’s story is that the testers
were suffering from a very bad case of complacency in their mistaken belief that
they could measure ability independent of cultural bias and educational
attainment. There is a large literature showing that IQ tests are not
culture-free or independent of educational attainment. It was also claimed by
the testers that one could not prepare for their tests. There was a man in New
York who set up a crammers. He coached people for the College Boards. Each was
told that if he or she brought back a question from the exam, the reward would
be a pizza. He soon built up a useful file of the sorts of questions that were
asked. The very upper class elite who Conant and Chauncey were trying to
outflank found their way to the crammer’s, and his methods were soon widely
emulated. The well-placed were fairly quick to learn how to play by the new
rules. The aristocracy and its new meritocratic recruits have managed very well
in seeing that their children get into the best universities. In the meantime,
the moral education of young people has taken a back seat to the search for
merit, an amoral category which brings you the clever careerists who dominate
public life and the institutions which govern our society.
The book is written with admirable care, letting the issues
emerge but remaining free from polemics. At the end, however, the author becomes
forthright about his own conclusions. Here is a passage which particularly
struck me: ‘The American meritocracy was founded on a linked chain of
presumptions, which people aren’t familiar with today because they weren’t
stated openly at the start. The first is that the system’s main task is to
select a small number of people to form a new elite – the goal of giving
opportunity to all Americans was added later, less as an essential element of
the system’s design than as a way of generating public support for it. The next
presumption was that the means of selection should be intelligence tests, as a
proxy for superior academic talent; the definition of “merit’, in other words,
is a purely intellectual, educational one. Finally, the purpose for which these
students are being selected to enter into the modern version of what Thomas
Jefferson called “the offices of government” – that is, administrative and
scholarly service to a modern bureaucratic state. What the founders of the
system envisioned was closer to the elite civil-service system of a country like
France or Japan than a meritocracy in the way the word is used today.
‘Over time the American meritocracy has developed into a more
general way of distributing opportunity to millions of people, fitting them into
places in a highly-tracked university system that leads to jobs and professions.
And its assumed purpose has changed from being a way to obtain highly capable
and well trained public officials to a way of determining fairly who gets
America’s material rewards. These changes were, substantially, accidental, the
result of both expansionist impulses within both ETS and the universities and
the privatism of American culture, but they have altered the moral calculus.
‘Let us say you wanted to design, from scratch, a system to
distribute opportunity in the fairest possible way. Would you design the
American meritocracy as it now exists? You would only if you believed that IQ
test scores and, more broadly, academic performance are the same thing as merit.
That’s a defensible position, but it ought at least to show itself openly to be
debated, rather than being presumed. If it did, the arguments against it would
quickly emerge. Merit is various, not unidimensional. Intelligence tests, and
also education itself, can’t be counted on to find every form of merit. They
don’t find wisdom, or originality, or humor, or toughness, or empathy, or common
sense or independence, or determination - let alone moral worth. Perforce they
judge people on their potential, not their actual performance over the long term
at the work for which they are being selected’ (pp. 344-45).
Turn the page, and you find: ‘…the idea of having a
general-purpose meritocratic elite generated through university admissions is an
idea we should abandon’ (p. 347).
To appear in Science as Culture
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
http://human-nature.com/