Robert M. Young Online Writings
CONCEPTUAL RESEARCH
by Robert M. Young
I came to this country in September 1960 to do a doctoral dissertation
at Cambridge on the history of ideas about mind and brain. When I first arrived and was
looking for a flat the landladies would ask me what I had come to do and suggested the
answer: 'Research?' I said no, that I was a 'graduate student'. I was from America, where
everyone knew that the people who did 'research' were scientists. Since I was going to
write an historical thesis, I thought it right to be straight: I was not a scientist and
therefore did not do research.
Thirty-odd years later I went to the first International
Psycho-analytic Association Conference on Research (a bit late to have the first one, you
might say), and I was absolutely sure I did research and minded very much that some of the
people there were trying to restrict the definition of research to empirical, positivistic
studies involving quantification and statistical methods.
The kind of research I do is conceptual research. I have thought of
other labels: historical research, critical history of ideas, critique. I remember with
great pride that P. F. Strawson, whose book Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive
Metaphysics remains one of those I most admire, reviewed my first book in the New
York Review. He said that I was absolutely right to put forward historical studies as
a method of research which could help to clarify concepts and advance the understanding of
mind-brain relations.
What I discovered in that piece of research is that the problem is not
how to localise functions in the brain. That is, of course, an important problem, but it
is less fundamental than discovering what questions to ask the brain. Not: 'How are the
functions localised?', but 'What are the concepts we need in order to specify the
functions whose mediation by the nervous system we wish to investigate?' Nature does not
provide the classification of functions; our differing concepts of human nature do. The
brain mediates all experience and behaviour. The categories we use depend on the
psychology we believe to be true, useful, efficacious. Different concepts of humanity will
lead to different conceptions and lists of functions. The history of localisation of
function is not merely one of advancing discovery; it involves, more fundamentally,
changing and differing conceptions of brain function and of human nature, e.g., primary
sensory projection areas, sensory-motor functions, rhinencephalon (smell brain),
proprioception, emotional functions, consciousness, respiratory and other physiological
functions. These overlap with, and are partially superceded by, recent conceptualisations
in terms of feedback systems and information theory. This list of examples could be
extended indefinitely
That research led onto the whole question of the concept of 'function'
itself and its fundamental role in the biological, behavioural and social sciences in the
twentieth century. That proved a fascinating enquiry, not least because the ambiguity of
the concept of function, lying as it does smack in the middle of the mind-body problem,
gave the human sciences a biological veneer, while making biology appear easily amenable
to being considered in humanocentric terms. All sorts of meanings of the concept of
function come easily to us and beg unresolved philosophical questions, e.g., as in 'The
mind is the net result of the functions of the brain'. 'The main function of the brain is
thought, just as producing insulin is the main function of the pancreas and filtration is
the main function of the kidneys.' What does it mean to speak of The Function of Social
Conflict' (the title of a sociological book) or Structure and Function in Primitive
Society (the title of a classical work in social anthropology)?
Indeed, it turned out as the context of my enquiries extended
further into the interrelations between psychology and biological thought that the
history of evolutionary thinking was deeply immersed in anthropomorphic and teleological
thinking and that this approach could be found at the heart of the most fundamental theory
in biology: Darwin's theory of evolution by means of natural selection. The metaphor
'natural selection' caused all sorts of grief for Darwin, yet he never abandoned it or
purged it of voluntarist and teleological resonances. If we look closely at the most
fundamental concepts in the natural sciences, many are anthropomorphic and metaphorical:
affinity in chemistry and gravity (gravitas) in physics, as
well as natural selection in biology.
Looking at the value laden aspect of scientific concepts has become a
fruitful line of enquiry among critical historians of ideas. This opens the door to
looking at the ways ideology value systems representing power relations constitute research agendas and valorise key concepts. Functionalism in the human sciences is an
excellent example, as a number of scholars have shown. Donna Haraway has done so with
great force and eloquence in her magisterial Primate Visions: Gender, Race and Nature
in the World of Modern Science and her essays, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The
Reinvention of Nature. She is, in my opinion, the foremost practitioner of the
analysis of scientific concepts which touch on our humanity, and her writings show the
integration of science, society and ideology. They are conceptual research at its best.
Practically everything I have done along these likes grew from feeling
confused and needing to stand back and sort out my ideas. The more I did this and went
back to basics, reading original sources and classical papers and monographs, the more I
found that I was not alone in feeling confused. That's how I got into the study of
concepts of cerebral localisation, into functionalism and into the close scrutiny of
Darwin's thinking about natural selection. Indeed, I recall the moment I read the
bibliographical essay at the end of C. C. Gillispie's Genesis and Geology and was
struck by the presence of Malthus Essay on Population and Paley's Natural
Theology as influential works in the Darwinian debate and in Darwins own
intellectual biography. Looking at their role led on to a whole rash of investigations of
the interrelations among scientific, theological and social theories.
In recent years I have found this approach fruitful in trying to sort
out key ideas in psychotherapy and psychoanalysis. In particular, I have tried to trace
the conceptual histories of transference and countertransference, psychotic anxieties,
projective identification and transitional objects and phenomena. In each case it has
proved illuminating to do a close reading of the key articles and books and to see how the
ideas have carried multiple meanings and have changed over time in important ways. For
example, countertransference started life as a nuisance, moved on to being something to
take account of in order to eliminate instances of its occurrence and is now seen as 'the
essence' of the analytic relationship. Similar things can be said about projective
identification, which is seen in some quarters as something we must abandon in order to
benefit importantly from psychotherapy, while in others it is seen as the basis for all
communication. In benign forms it is central to all relating, while in virulent ones it is
the primitive psychological mechanism for racism and nationalistic wars.
There is a similar and un-sorted out conceptual muddle about object
relations. Klein saw internal objects as essential to humanity and thought, while
Fairbairn saw all internal objects as pathological and their elimination as a central goal
of psychotherapy. Yet people have not sorted out the very different senses of object
relations and where the other main founder of that tradition, Winnicott, stands. Kleinians
tend to dismiss the concept of transitional objects and phenomena, while many independents
see their role as essential to development, play and the experience of culture.
I am currently in the foothills of trying to figure out why some people
insist on primary narcissism in infancy, before we move on to object relations, while
others have no need for primary narcissism and insist that we have full-blooded object
relations from birth. What hangs on this? Why is it important? Does anyone know? I haven't
got very far with this one yet.
There is a similar muddle about the female Oedipus complex and another
between Kleinian and Freudian ideas about the Oedipus complex more generally. I have made
a stab at the last of these muddles but remain daunted by the question of the female
Oedipus complex. Another conceptual muddle: what about the concept of 'perversion'? Is it
only an insult to practitioners of deviant sexuality or it it a concept which it is
important to retain in understanding psychopathology? The concept of
pychopathology its itself a fruitful subject of conceptual research.
I think we should study and teach psychology, psychotherapy and the
rest of the human sciences this way as exploration of concepts, along with debates
about their explanation and clinical meanings. Moreover, we should acquaint students and
trainees with recent debates about different modes of knowing, including some
understanding of verstehen, structural causation, hermeneutics, and narrative.
However, the powers that be in these disciplines seem not to take this kind of work very
seriously. I recently submitted a paper to a psychotherapy journal and had it rejected on
the single ground that it contained no clinical material. The editor remarked that the
referees said it had much interesting historical and conceptual material but nothing
clinical; by their criteria, it was therefore unpublishable. Another paper which
the editor of another journal had asked me to submit came back with the request
that all instances of the first person be removed. I had put them in to show the path of
my enquiry and to provide illuminating examples from my own experience (the paper was on
racism, and I grew up in Texas). More recently, a professor of psychiatry has said of my
entire list of publications that since it involves no quantitative research, it is
all navel gazing.
I mention these experiences to illustrate my point that positivistic
and objectivist norms are alive and well in the human sciences. I have a lot of criticisms
of postmodernism, but one thing I think we have to thank it for is the subversion of the
hegemony of privileged, foundational modes of discourse. We ought to be able to write
about things in any mode of discourse which is edifying and not insist on the objective
mode, which is so often a fig-leaf over a much more exciting tale only accessible
if you are on the right gossip network in any case.
REFERENCES
(Place of publication is London unless otherwise specified.)
Coser, Lewis (1956) The Function of Social Conflict. Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Demerath, N. J. and Peterson, R. A., eds. (1967) System, Change and
Conflict: A reader on Contemporary Sociological Theory and the Debate over Functionalism. Collier-Macmillan.
Gillispie, Charles C. (1959) Genesis and Geology: The Impact of
Scientific Discoveries upon Religious Beliefs in the Decades before Darwin. N. Y.:
Harper Torchbooks.
Greenberg, Jay R. and Mitchell, Stephen A. (1983) Object Relations
in Psychoanalytic Theory. Harvard.
Haraway, Donna J. (1989) Primate Visions: Gender, Race and Nature in
the World of Modern Science. Routledge.
______ (1990) Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Free Association Books.
Heyl, Barbara S. (1980) The Harvard Pareto
Circle, J. Hist. Behav. Sci. 4: 316-34 (on the historical roots of
functionalism).
Malthus, Thomas R. (1798) An Essay on the Principle of Population. Johnson.
Paley, William (1802) Natural Theology. Baynes.
Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1952) Structure and Function in Primitive
Society: Essays and Addresses. Cohen and West.
Rorty, Richard (1989) The Contingency of Selfhood, in Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge, pp. 23-43.
Sandler, Joseph, ed. (1991) Freuds On Narcissism: An
Introduction. Yale.
Strawson, Peter F. (1959) Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive
Metaphysics. Methuen.
Young, Robert M. (1970) Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth
Century: Cerebral Localization and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier. Oxford:
Clarendon; reprinted with new preface N. Y.: Oxford, 1990.
______ (1972) Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and
Now, in W. Fuller, ed. The Biological Revolution: Social Good or Social Evil?. N.
Y.: Doubleday Anchor, pp. 241-82.
______ (1981) The Naturalization of Value Systems in the Human
Sciences, in Problems in the Biological and Human Sciences. Milton Keynes:
Open University Press, pp. 63-110.
______ (1985) Darwins Metaphor: Natures Place in
Victorian Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge.
______ (1993) Darwins Metaphor and the Philosophy of
Science, Sci. as Culture (no. 16) 3: 375-403.
______ (1993) Psychoanalytic Teaching and Research: Knowing and
Knowing About, Free Assns. (no. 29) 4: 129-37.
______ (1992) Science, Ideology and Donna Haraway, Sci.
as Culture (no. 15) 3: 7-46.
______ (1994) Is Perversion Obsolete?, paper
presented to Grand Rounds, Department of Psychiatry, University of Manitoba.
______ (1994) Mental Space. Process Press.
______ (1994) New Ideas about the Oedipus Complex, Melanie
Klein and Object Relations . 12 (no. 2): 1-20.
______ (1994) The Psychoanalysis of Sectarianism, British
Psychological Society, Psychotherapy Section Newsletter. no. 15: 2-15.
This essay appeared in Changes: An International Journal of
Psychology and Psychotherapy 13: 145-48, 1995
Address for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
e-mail: robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
© The Author
|